19.10.2014 Views

1 On tough-movement* Milan Rezac, University ... - Multimania.co.uk

1 On tough-movement* Milan Rezac, University ... - Multimania.co.uk

1 On tough-movement* Milan Rezac, University ... - Multimania.co.uk

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

that it involves an Ā-step between two A-positions, and interpretation of thematic properties in<br />

one position and quantificational in another. The TM subject-gap <strong>co</strong>rrelation is troubling because<br />

there is a <strong>co</strong>mplete Ā-chain (or on a different view, a pro) in the OP clause whose existence,<br />

unlike that of other Ā-chains and other pro's, depends on a separately base-generated DP, the TM<br />

subject. I aim to show that these anomalies largely follow from syntactic mechanisms that are<br />

needed anyway to derive and interpret more orthodox structures.<br />

2 Basic properties of <strong>tough</strong>-movement<br />

I start out from the <strong>co</strong>nclusion of Berman (1973), Chomsky (1981:309ff.), Brody (1993), among<br />

others, that the TM subject is not selected by the TM trigger. The position in which it appears<br />

can be filled by the it expletive in the clausal subject <strong>co</strong>nstruction (2) (I return to the absence of<br />

the there expletives in 3.2). It is thematically interpreted in and subject to selectional restrictions<br />

imposed on the gap in the OP clause (Lasnik and Fiengo 1974:536ff.): the hatchet in (3)a is<br />

interpretable either idiomatically or literally as the object of bury, and deviant as an argument of<br />

be impossible alone (3)b. 2 However, quantificational properties of the TM subject are not<br />

interpreted in the gap, so the two expressions in (4) are not synonymous: (4)b has the s<strong>co</strong>pe<br />

reading hard >> nothing that (4)a lacks. Deriving these facts will be a major result of section 3.<br />

(2) a. Nearly every dragon i is easy for his i foe to admire e.<br />

b. It is easy for his *i/j foe to admire nearly every dragon i .<br />

(3) a. The hatchet is impossible to bury e after all these years.<br />

b. #The hatchet is impossible.<br />

c. #Re<strong>co</strong>nstruction is easy to dance with e.<br />

d. #I danced with the flight of these birds.<br />

(4) a. Nothing is hard for Melvin to lift. ≠<br />

b. It is hard for Melvin to lift nothing.<br />

(Postal 1974:356)<br />

An alternative hypothesis that has been proposed is that the TM subject is interpreted as an<br />

argument of the TM trigger: Yann Gerven is easy to read is essentially Yann Gerven is easy, with<br />

the infinitive as an adjunct (Williams 1983, Wilder 1991). That is a hard road to take<br />

semantically (cf. Hey<strong>co</strong>ck 1994:259ff.). There are no relations such as entailment between the<br />

two <strong>co</strong>nstructions when both are available to TM triggers, (5)a, (5)b, yet these are expected when<br />

adjunct (modifier) interpretation is involved, (5)c (I use x ⊂ y for x entails y).<br />

(5) a. The stone is easy [to lift e] ⊄ The stone is easy.<br />

b. The hatchet is easy [to bury e] ⊄ The hatchet is easy.<br />

c. Tartalo bought the pig [to eat e] ⊂ Tartalo bought the pig.<br />

If the TM subject's position is non-thematic, it should allow idiom chunks selected for in the<br />

gap. 3 However, only some are permitted. Two alternative hypotheses seem <strong>co</strong>mpatible with the<br />

data: that the permitted idiom chunks are those which may head restrictive relative clauses and<br />

3

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!