15.11.2014 Views

Volume 7 Number 2 July 2006 - JICS - The Intensive Care Society

Volume 7 Number 2 July 2006 - JICS - The Intensive Care Society

Volume 7 Number 2 July 2006 - JICS - The Intensive Care Society

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

<strong>Volume</strong> 7 <strong>Number</strong> 2<br />

26<br />

Original Articles continued<br />

paradoxically, made identifying a point of death even<br />

harder. In the natural process of dying, the final<br />

elements of the closing down process come fairly<br />

close together; but we can now draw out those<br />

different elements, often independently, while<br />

monitors allow us to watch what is going on in<br />

previously impossible detail. <strong>The</strong> range from<br />

which to choose the point of death has expanded<br />

immeasurably.<br />

<strong>The</strong> resulting controversies about the point of death<br />

can become passionate, because holders of different<br />

views regard their opponents as doing serious,<br />

unjustified harm. People who accept the brain stem<br />

criterion, for instance, think that innumerable organs<br />

are lost to slow deterioration while ventilators<br />

maintain cardiopulmonary function, or monitors show<br />

the last flickers of cortical activity, in a patient<br />

already dead. Others with more conservative views<br />

– including many potential donors and their families<br />

– think their opponents are recommending the<br />

murder of dying patients.<br />

<strong>The</strong> only way out of this impasse involves<br />

recognizing a much more fundamental point: that<br />

science cannot establish a point of death. <strong>The</strong><br />

traditional view is that there is an objective fact<br />

about the matter: death is the final departure of<br />

some undetectable soul or élan vital. But if such<br />

things exist, science has no way of observing them.<br />

If, on the other hand, life is – as scientists<br />

increasingly believe – a function of the organization<br />

of material parts, there simply is no point of<br />

transition between life and death. Trying to pin it<br />

down is like trying to determine the point at which<br />

red becomes orange on a spectrum. On the<br />

traditional account, the question of when death<br />

occurs in the closing down process is scientifically<br />

unanswerable; on the more recent one, it is<br />

meaningless. Either way, it should be abandoned.<br />

<strong>The</strong> whole problem can then be approached from a<br />

different direction. Why are we so anxious to know<br />

whether someone is alive or dead? <strong>The</strong> reason,<br />

obviously, is our concern to treat the living and the<br />

dead appropriately.<br />

Instead of trying to keep the familiar categories and<br />

force the transitional states into them, we should<br />

address directly the problem of how people in those<br />

states should be treated. This question is not<br />

scientific, but moral. Science can tell us what states<br />

people are in and (with different degrees of certainty,<br />

and subject to change) whether those can be<br />

stabilized or reversed. It cannot answer the moral<br />

question of how we should treat people in those<br />

states.<br />

Traditional believers in an objective point of death<br />

will probably answer the moral question by<br />

maintaining an absolute prohibition on active<br />

hastening of death, and always presuming life in<br />

case of uncertainty. But for anyone who accepts<br />

that there is no definite point of death, but only a<br />

shading between clearly alive and clearly dead,<br />

moral judgments will need a different basis. <strong>The</strong><br />

most plausible view is that what matters is people’s<br />

interests.<br />

This kind of idea, when followed through, has<br />

radically different implications from those of the<br />

traditional view. <strong>The</strong>y can overlap in many areas,<br />

but in the penumbra between life and death, the two<br />

approaches come apart. When patients reach the<br />

point of having no interest in further treatment to<br />

reverse or delay the closing down process, they<br />

usually have no interest in whether it is further<br />

delayed, or accelerated, or redirected. From their<br />

point of view, accelerating the closing down process<br />

beyond the point of their interests is no more killing,<br />

in any morally relevant respect, than is accelerating<br />

the closing down of hair growth by cremation. At the<br />

same time, other people may have considerable<br />

interest in how the process happens – not only<br />

because of transplants, but because of the<br />

enormous resources that currently go into end-of-life<br />

care. From their point of view it matters a great deal<br />

whether we treat the dying according to their<br />

interests as we understand them, or rule out certain<br />

possibilities altogether until some (highly elusive)<br />

objective point of death.<br />

Law and professional practice already give great<br />

weight to patients’ interests, and most doctors would<br />

say those interests were the purpose of their work.<br />

But much of what is legally required and actually<br />

done has nothing to do with interests, and may<br />

actually work against them, because of ancient<br />

assumptions about an objective point of death and<br />

its moral relevance.<br />

Since every day extends our ability to separate and<br />

draw out the different elements of the closing down<br />

process that is death, it is essential to replace the<br />

anachronistic, apparently scientific debate about<br />

when death really occurs with the explicitly moral<br />

debate that it should be.<br />

J Radcliffe Richards<br />

Centre for Biomedical Ethics and Philosophy UCL<br />

<strong>July</strong> <strong>2006</strong><br />

<strong>The</strong> Journal of the <strong>Intensive</strong> <strong>Care</strong> <strong>Society</strong>

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!