01.12.2014 Views

The Right to Dignity Rex D. Glensy - Columbia Law School

The Right to Dignity Rex D. Glensy - Columbia Law School

The Right to Dignity Rex D. Glensy - Columbia Law School

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

2011] <strong>The</strong> <strong>Right</strong> <strong>to</strong> <strong>Dignity</strong> 121<br />

intervene on behalf of) human dignity.” 254 In practice, what this<br />

means is that one arm of the state will take it upon itself <strong>to</strong> make<br />

sure that another arm of the state is not infringing upon those rights<br />

<strong>to</strong> which individuals are deemed entitled. In the United States, this is<br />

how jurisprudence pertaining <strong>to</strong> constitutional rights has developed,<br />

and it applies across the board <strong>to</strong> such mainstays of American rights<br />

as equal protection, due process, free speech, and cruel and unusual<br />

punishment. A negative rights approach <strong>to</strong> the right <strong>to</strong> dignity would<br />

add dignitary interests <strong>to</strong> those rights that the state would be unable<br />

<strong>to</strong> impinge. <strong>The</strong> right <strong>to</strong> dignity would become a de fac<strong>to</strong> background<br />

norm and an independent consideration <strong>to</strong> contend with when a<br />

claimant alleges a violation that would impact human dignity.<br />

In speaking of human dignity, Eleanor Roosevelt remarked<br />

that it reflected the notion that “every human being is worthy of<br />

respect” and thus explained “why human beings have rights <strong>to</strong> begin<br />

with.” 255 This means that “human dignity or a similar understanding<br />

of universal humanity underlies all human rights.” 256 In other words,<br />

the negative rights approach is based on the understanding that<br />

human dignity is the source of human rights and hence is anterior or<br />

above the state and <strong>to</strong> which it does not belong conceptually. What<br />

follows, consequently, is that in the right <strong>to</strong> dignity is embodied the<br />

notion that it is beyond the reach of the state. In this guise, the right<br />

<strong>to</strong> dignity becomes a metric against which other rights can be<br />

measured. Because, as an ideal, dignity is “clearly accepted as<br />

universal,” 257 it is reflected in this role as a standard bearer, lying just<br />

below the surface of enumerated rights.<br />

<strong>The</strong> main idea behind incorporating the right <strong>to</strong> dignity as a<br />

background norm is the notion that human dignity itself is a quality<br />

closely associated with a liberal concept of governance. 258 Indeed,<br />

dignity has been described as one of “the cardinal principles for which<br />

the [United States] Constitution stands.” 259 In other words, it could be<br />

254. Beth Simmons, Civil <strong>Right</strong>s in International <strong>Law</strong>: Compliance with<br />

Aspects of the “International Bill of <strong>Right</strong>s”, 16 Ind. J. Global Legal Stud. 437, 440<br />

(2009).<br />

255. Mary Ann Glendon, A World Made New: Eleanor Roosevelt and the<br />

Universal Declaration of Human <strong>Right</strong>s 146 (2001).<br />

256. Donna Greschner, <strong>The</strong> Purpose of Canadian Equality <strong>Right</strong>s, 6 Rev.<br />

Const. Stud. 290, 321 (2002).<br />

257. Schachter, supra note 14, at 849.<br />

258. See Daniel Bodansky, Is <strong>The</strong>re an International Environmental<br />

Constitution?, 16 Ind. J. Global Legal Stud. 565, 569 (2009).<br />

259. Trop v. Dulles, 356 U.S. 86, 100–02 (1958) (noting that stripping an<br />

individual of his citizenship was “offensive” <strong>to</strong> this principle); see also Goodman,

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!