01.12.2014 Views

The Right to Dignity Rex D. Glensy - Columbia Law School

The Right to Dignity Rex D. Glensy - Columbia Law School

The Right to Dignity Rex D. Glensy - Columbia Law School

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

122 COLUMBIA HUMAN RIGHTS LAW REVIEW [43:65<br />

defined as the Constitution’s tuning fork, <strong>to</strong> which all elements of the<br />

orchestra need <strong>to</strong> be harmonized. 260 Giving the right <strong>to</strong> dignity a<br />

negative dimension thus gives substance <strong>to</strong> a theoretical<br />

underpinning <strong>to</strong> which numerous commenta<strong>to</strong>rs and jurists (some on<br />

the Supreme Court) have persistently referred. <strong>The</strong>refore, under this<br />

reading, what begins as a foundational aspiration (that all people be<br />

treated with dignity by their government) is transformed in<strong>to</strong> a basis<br />

for justice as a normative goal, <strong>to</strong> be effectuated through legal<br />

processes. <strong>The</strong> right <strong>to</strong> dignity, thus viewed, would be given a<br />

constant force that is consciously present in those situations in which<br />

it is implicated; it would accordingly provide an internally coherent<br />

common standard of guidance as an interpretative principle.<br />

Consequently, there would be a certain synonymy between dignity<br />

and human rights. 261 Importantly, however, this would not merely<br />

play out on a constitutional level; rather, as explained above for the<br />

positive rights approach, other rights protected through common law<br />

or statute could easily be infused with this dignity component. In<br />

sum, and in a semantic irony, the negative right <strong>to</strong> dignity acts as a<br />

suprapositive principle. 262<br />

<strong>The</strong> practical implication for this application of the right <strong>to</strong><br />

dignity would be, over time and through the development of legal<br />

rules and doctrine, the enunciation of some minimal standards of<br />

conduct <strong>to</strong> which the government has <strong>to</strong> adhere. Granting citizens<br />

this right then provides not only the moral justification <strong>to</strong> challenge<br />

government behavior that debases, degrades, or humiliates, but also<br />

the legal means <strong>to</strong> have that behavior curtailed absent extenuating<br />

circumstances. This reflects the Kantian notion of human dignity, by<br />

giving this right “a very strong negative sense, viz., independence<br />

from the determining causes of the sensible world” that is regarded as<br />

supra note 23, at 761 (characterizing dignity as “a value which underlies the<br />

Constitution”).<br />

260. See Mary Ann Glendon, Propter Honoris Respectful: Knowing the<br />

Universal Declaration of Human <strong>Right</strong>s, 73 Notre Dame L. Rev. 1153, 1173 (1998)<br />

(using this metaphor in suggesting that the right <strong>to</strong> dignity is the ultimate value<br />

captured by the Universal Declaration of Human <strong>Right</strong>s).<br />

261. See, e.g., Ronald Dworkin, Is Democracy Possible Here?: Principles for<br />

a New Political Debate (2006) (equating dignity with human rights); Martha<br />

Nussbaum, Frontiers of Justice: Disability, Nationality, Species Membership 7<br />

(2006) (articulating a “capabilities approach” <strong>to</strong> social justice, as part of a set of<br />

political principles promoting human dignity).<br />

262. See Gerald Neuman, Human <strong>Right</strong>s and Constitutional <strong>Right</strong>s:<br />

Harmony and Dissonance, 55 Stan. L. Rev. 1863, 1868–71 (2003).

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!