01.12.2014 Views

The Right to Dignity Rex D. Glensy - Columbia Law School

The Right to Dignity Rex D. Glensy - Columbia Law School

The Right to Dignity Rex D. Glensy - Columbia Law School

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

2011] <strong>The</strong> <strong>Right</strong> <strong>to</strong> <strong>Dignity</strong> 133<br />

While both of those sentiments have an attractive simplicity,<br />

a little inquiry under the surface reveals them <strong>to</strong> be somewhat<br />

lacking. As <strong>to</strong> the separate injury argument, while there are actions<br />

that can offend dignity that do not offend privacy, because privacy in<br />

many respects is itself subsumed within the concept of liberty, those<br />

actions that might not offend privacy but do offend dignity, now<br />

might be brought within the purview of an injury <strong>to</strong> liberty.<br />

Additionally, if these same actions do not offend liberty either, they<br />

arguably should not constitute imputable actions in the first place.<br />

<strong>The</strong> reply <strong>to</strong> the second argument is that, while it is clearly true that<br />

dignity and equality are not coterminous as a matter of vocabulary,<br />

they do overlap significantly, and it is that overlap that constitutes<br />

the basis for the proxy approach—not a search for perfect congruence.<br />

Another line of attack posits that if the right <strong>to</strong> dignity is<br />

simply viewed as another way of expressing another right, then its<br />

invocation adds very little, if anything, <strong>to</strong> the analysis, and does not<br />

help <strong>to</strong> interpret the underlying act for which it is being invoked as a<br />

proxy. 312 Some critics bolster this theoretical attack with examples<br />

drawn from actual jurisprudence. For example, in the case of the<br />

German Constitutional Court’s references <strong>to</strong> dignitary interests, it<br />

has been noted that when a violation of human dignity was alleged, it<br />

always “went along with the alleged violation of other individual<br />

rights so that access <strong>to</strong> the Court never depended on the qualification<br />

of human dignity as an individual right.” 313 In the same vein, Robert<br />

Post has a foundational critique of the proxy approach <strong>to</strong> the use of<br />

dignity, at least visàvis the linkage between human dignity and<br />

equality. He argues that antidiscrimination law should not be<br />

envisaged as concerned with the protection of human dignity, but<br />

rather as a legal enterprise, akin <strong>to</strong> a normative agent designed <strong>to</strong><br />

change a harmful social order that has oppressed traditionally<br />

disadvantaged categories of people. 314 Ronald Dworkin takes a similar<br />

view, but expands this notion <strong>to</strong> caution against the conflation of<br />

312. See Joel Feinberg, <strong>The</strong> Nature and Value of <strong>Right</strong>s, 4 J. Value Inquiry<br />

243, 252 (1970) (“[W]hat is called ‘human dignity’ may simply be the recognizable<br />

capacity <strong>to</strong> assert claims.”)<br />

313. Walter, supra note 210, at 27.<br />

314. See, e.g., Robert Post, Prejudicial Appearances: <strong>The</strong> Logic of American<br />

Antidiscrimination <strong>Law</strong>, 88 Cal. L. Rev. 1, 17 (2000) (arguing that American<br />

antidiscrimination law should be unders<strong>to</strong>od not as an attempt <strong>to</strong> transcend racial<br />

and sexual classifications in order <strong>to</strong> seize upon each person’s “individual worth,”<br />

but rather as sociological <strong>to</strong>ol regulating controversial, and prejudicial, social<br />

practices).

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!