27.01.2016 Views

THE CITY

h6c7p5d

h6c7p5d

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

The City<br />

A PARADIGM SHIFT<br />

The story of how the modern period lost the traditional problem<br />

of evil has been told by Susan Neiman in a fascinating book entitled<br />

Evil in Modern Thought: An Alternative History of Philosophy. There<br />

she describes how the problem of evil has undergone a number of<br />

transmutations and has come to be viewed in a radically different<br />

way as a result. In the introduction to that book, she states the<br />

fundamental conviction that drives the problem of evil: “Every<br />

time we make the judgment this ought not to have happened, we are<br />

stepping onto a path that leads straight to the problem of evil.” 1<br />

However, the judgment also raises a question that can hardly<br />

be ignored, and it is this: what reason do we have to think of any<br />

given event or incident that it ought not to have happened? What<br />

grounds this judgment that we often make with such certainty and<br />

conviction? What distinguishes those things that ought to happen,<br />

or that simply happen as a matter of course, from those that ought<br />

not to happen?<br />

These questions have a reasonably clear answer in Christian<br />

theology, where the reality of evil is apparent, as well as the sense in<br />

which it ought not to happen. Beginning with the Garden of Eden,<br />

if not in the primordial fall of Satan, evil has played a vital, if not<br />

central role in the drama of sin and redemption. Evil is very much a<br />

problem not only in the sense that it impairs the human flourishing<br />

that God intends for us and leads to various forms of suffering, but<br />

also in the sense that it has corrupted the entire fallen world and<br />

causes it to fall short of the purposes for which it was created. Evil is<br />

thus very much at odds with God and his purposes, and in this sense<br />

it ought not to happen.<br />

But here is the bottom line: our passionate judgment, “this ought<br />

not to have happened” only makes sense given certain convictions<br />

about ultimate reality. What has traditionally driven the problem<br />

of evil is that ultimate reality is good because ultimate reality is a<br />

God who is not only perfectly loving and good, but also supremely<br />

powerful. But what becomes of the problem of evil when this<br />

conviction no longer holds?<br />

1<br />

Susan Neiman, Evil in Modern Thought: An Alternative History of Philosophy (Princeton:<br />

Princeton University Press, 2002), 5.<br />

50

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!