08.12.2012 Views

Siegecraft - TerpConnect - University of Maryland

Siegecraft - TerpConnect - University of Maryland

Siegecraft - TerpConnect - University of Maryland

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

Introduction<br />

by choice <strong>of</strong> terminology, his conceptualization <strong>of</strong> his new approach to<br />

technical illustration as at the level <strong>of</strong> what the senses see, the surface<br />

appearance, while suggesting that the approach found in his sources is at<br />

a higher level <strong>of</strong> abstraction.<br />

The validity <strong>of</strong> this interpretation is strengthened not only by the<br />

nature <strong>of</strong> the illustrations in Vat. gr. 1605, but also by overt references in<br />

the texts. The Anon. Byz. (3:9–14) cites Porphyry (ı polÁw §n s<strong>of</strong>¤&), on<br />

Plotinus (ı m°gaw), that Plotinus was “concerned only with the concept<br />

and the things. For he knew that reality is tripartite: words, concepts,<br />

and things” (mÒnou toË noË ka‹ t«n pragmãtvn §xÒmenow. Trittå går tå<br />

ˆnta ±p¤stato, n te fvna›w noÆmas¤ te ka‹ prãgmasi). The phrase “and<br />

the things” (ka‹ t«n pragmãtvn) is not in any manuscript <strong>of</strong> the cited<br />

passage <strong>of</strong> Porphyry’s Vita Plotini and has apparently been added here by<br />

the Anon. Byz. to the citation. The view <strong>of</strong> reality as tripartite is found<br />

in the sixth-century Neoplatonists Olympiodorus and Elias. 27 The sentence<br />

also seemingly reflects what S. Gersch 28 has described in another<br />

context as the extensive Neoplatonic controversy about the subject <strong>of</strong><br />

Aristotle’s Categories, 29 whether it classifies “words” (fvna¤), “things”<br />

(prãgmata), or “concepts” (noÆmata), and which as Gersch notes was<br />

commented on by Porphyry and is, among extant works, best documented<br />

in Simplicius. The Anon. Byz. next argues (3:18–22) that one<br />

who errs about “things,” his worst-case scenario, falls into Plato’s “double<br />

ignorance,” êgnoia (“knowing that one knows and not understanding<br />

that one is ignorant”). Thus the Anon. Byz. cites Plato and Neoplatonists<br />

by name, deliberately supplements the text <strong>of</strong> the Vita Plotini to mark a<br />

contrast between “concepts” and “things” (noÆmata and prãgmata), shows<br />

a specific, if unsophisticated, 30 knowledge <strong>of</strong> Neoplatonic epistemology,<br />

27 See Olymp. Phil., Proll. 18:25–27, and Elias Phil., In Cat.129:9–11.<br />

28 From Iamblichus to Eriugena (Leiden, 1978), 96 n. 76.<br />

29 On the centrality <strong>of</strong> Aristotles’ Categories and Porphyry’s commentary thereon<br />

in Byzantine philosophical education, as well as the growing interest in Neoplatonism<br />

in the late 9th and 10th centuries before the “renaissance” associated with M. Psellos,<br />

see R. Browning, The Byzantine Empire, rev. ed. (Washington, D.C., 1992), 138, and<br />

Lemerle, Byzantine Humanism, 251–55.<br />

30 The Anon. Byz. appears to use two levels <strong>of</strong> reality, that <strong>of</strong> sense perception and<br />

a level above, which he uses <strong>of</strong> both noÆmata and mathematical objects §n fantas¤&,<br />

levels that are <strong>of</strong>ten distinguished by some Neoplatonists (see, e.g., the distinction<br />

between fantas¤a and diãnoia in Syrianus below, note 31). Gersch, however, observes<br />

[ 12 ]

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!