19.01.2018 Views

Judicial ReEngineering

Judicial ReEngineering

Judicial ReEngineering

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

2001]<br />

PROPER JUDICIAL ACTIVISM<br />

baby out with the bath water. The contributors to the First Things<br />

debate decry the evils of judicial activism, but they enthusiastically<br />

support the idea of natural law.210 As we saw in Part III, as well as in<br />

Part I while defining judicial activism, natural law is open to the same<br />

abuses that judicial activism engenders. In fact, several of the decisions<br />

about which First Things complains, such as Roe, ground their opinions<br />

in a kind of natural law jurisprudence. The point here is not that the<br />

editors of First Things must either support Roe v. Wade or renounce<br />

natural law - clearly their version of natural law can be different from<br />

the Court's in Roe; the point is to understand that judging inherently<br />

involves the kinds of problems that the editors declare represent the<br />

"end of democracy." The solution to those problems is not to declare the<br />

system broken, but to demand adherence to true fidelity to that system<br />

(i.e., the Constitution). And it is perfectly within the power of the People<br />

to demand this, because, as we have learned, the power of the Supreme<br />

Court is wholly dependent on its legitimacy. 21 '<br />

Obviously, several other theories of constitutional jurisprudence<br />

exist that have not been addressed. Only those that speak most directly<br />

to the position being advocated in this article have been rejoined.<br />

Structural activism is but one piece of the constitutional fabric, but it is<br />

a very important piece. It is time for advocates of both jurisprudential<br />

activism and judicial restraint to consider its validity.<br />

Having preached the virtues of judicial restraint for several<br />

generations, conservatives will have to reevaluate their position. As<br />

they did in the late 1930's, liberals and conservatives in the late 1990's<br />

will debate about whether the courts or the political process are better<br />

equipped to police the boundaries of federalism and the separation of<br />

powers. 212<br />

210 Bork, Our <strong>Judicial</strong> Oligarchy, supra note 205, at 6 ("Among the most elementary<br />

principles of Western Civilization is the truth that laws which violate the moral law are<br />

null and void and must in conscience be disobeyed.").<br />

211 Robert A. Dahl, Decision-Making in a Democracy: The Supreme Court as a<br />

National Policy-Maker, 6 J. PUB. L. 279, 285 (1957).<br />

The fact is ... that the policy views dominant on the Court are never for<br />

long out of line with the policy views dominant among the lawmaking<br />

majorities of the United States. Consequently it would be most unrealistic<br />

to suppose that the Court would, for more than a few years at most, stand<br />

against any major alternatives sought by a lawmaking majority.<br />

Id.<br />

Of course, sadly this is part of the problem to begin with-that the<br />

Court follows policy preferences at all, when it ought to be following the<br />

Constitution. But the point here is that the Court can only get away with what<br />

we let it get away with, given a certain amount of time.<br />

212 Jeffrey Rosen, Nine Votes for <strong>Judicial</strong> Restraint, N.Y. TIMES, June 29, 1997, at<br />

HeinOnline -- 14 Regent U. L. Rev. 177 2001-2002

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!