24.12.2012 Views

The Trinitarian Theology of Saint Thomas Aquinas - El Camino ...

The Trinitarian Theology of Saint Thomas Aquinas - El Camino ...

The Trinitarian Theology of Saint Thomas Aquinas - El Camino ...

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

110 <strong>The</strong> Person<br />

<strong>The</strong> early Franciscan school <strong>of</strong>ten used this definition, and it is still the<br />

primary one for St Bonaventure.36 St <strong>Thomas</strong> was quite well aware that<br />

God is eminent in dignity or, rather, ‘surpasses every dignity’. He does not<br />

oppose the Master’s definition, but it is only interesting to him as an evocative<br />

allusion; it does not have the wealth or precision <strong>of</strong> that <strong>of</strong> Boethius.<br />

<strong>The</strong> third traditional definition comes from Richard <strong>of</strong> <strong>Saint</strong>-Victor: a<br />

person is ‘an incommunicable existence <strong>of</strong> divine nature’.37 Richard substituted<br />

this definition for Boethius’, because, in his opinion, Boethius’ definition<br />

leads one to conceive the divine substance as a person and thus creates a<br />

confusion between the common substance and the distinct Three in God.<br />

This is why Richard’s definition indicates what distinguishes the persons (the<br />

principle <strong>of</strong> ‘individuation’), that is, the ex-sistere (indicating directly the<br />

origin from another; holding his existence from someone) which is incommunicable<br />

(the distinct singularity and irreducible singularity <strong>of</strong> the person).<br />

In addition, Richard replaced the adjective ‘reason’ with a conditioning<br />

quality, ‘divine’. <strong>The</strong> accuracy <strong>of</strong> Richard’s criticisms is debatable, since for<br />

Boethius divine substance is not an ‘individual substance’ in the meaning<br />

which his definition <strong>of</strong> person gives it,38 and the note <strong>of</strong> incommunicability is<br />

expressed by the notion <strong>of</strong> ‘individual’. However that may be, very many<br />

theologians united around Richard’s objections. In every quarter, even<br />

amongst those who retained Boethius’ definition, the criticisms attracted<br />

great attention. One still finds traces <strong>of</strong> them in Albert, who judges that ‘as<br />

Boethius defines it, the person does not fit into God, unless one explains<br />

substance in the sense <strong>of</strong> existence, as Richard puts it’.39 Bonaventure, who<br />

was likewise receptive to Boethius’ definition, explains that it applies as much<br />

to creatures as to God, whereas Richard’s applies exclusively to God: the<br />

Franciscan master concludes that one can say that Richard’s definition uses<br />

language ‘more appropriately’.40<br />

nobilitatem pertinens’ (I Sent. d. 25, q. 1, a. 1, ad 8). St Albert the Great observed that ‘<strong>The</strong><br />

masters got their definition by way <strong>of</strong> a comparison with social values or civil functions’ (Albert,<br />

I Sent. d. 25, a. 1 in fine).<br />

36 See Bonaventure, I Sent. d. 23, a. 1, q. 1; d. 25, a. 1, q. 1.<br />

37 Richard <strong>of</strong> <strong>Saint</strong>-Victor, De Trinitate, Book IV, ch. 22 (SC 63, pp. 280–283): ‘naturae<br />

divinae incommunicabilis exsistentia’. This definition has lately given rise to several anachronistic<br />

interpretations <strong>of</strong> Richard’s idea. For the Victorine, the definition is based on the concept <strong>of</strong><br />

nature and also implies the notion <strong>of</strong> substance, for ‘the word existence signifies substantial<br />

being’ (Book IV, ch. 23; SC 63, pp. 282–283); cf. N. Den Bok, Communicating the Most High: A<br />

Systematic Study <strong>of</strong> Person and Trinity in the theology <strong>of</strong> Richard <strong>of</strong> St. Victor (1 1173), Paris and<br />

Turnhout, 1996.<br />

38 Cf. Schlapkohl, Persona, pp. 150–151, 155. 39 Albert, I Sent. d. 25, a. 1.<br />

40 Bonaventure, I Sent. d. 25, a. 1, q. 2, ad 4. Although the Scotist definition <strong>of</strong> person is not<br />

identical to Richard’s, Duns Scotus takes over Richard <strong>of</strong> <strong>Saint</strong> Victor’s definition and his<br />

critique <strong>of</strong> Boethius (see Schlapkohl, Persona, pp. 155–169; F. Wetter, Die Trinitätslehre des<br />

Johannes Duns Scotus, Münster, 1967, pp. 272–273).

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!