07.03.2013 Views

Aesthetic Perspectives in Music Therapy * - World Federation of ...

Aesthetic Perspectives in Music Therapy * - World Federation of ...

Aesthetic Perspectives in Music Therapy * - World Federation of ...

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

Frohne-Hagemann, I (2001) <strong>Aesthetic</strong> <strong>Perspectives</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>Music</strong> <strong>Therapy</strong>. <strong>Music</strong><br />

<strong>Therapy</strong> Today (onl<strong>in</strong>e), November, available at www.musictherapyworld.<strong>in</strong>fo<br />

<strong>Aesthetic</strong> <strong>Perspectives</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>Music</strong> <strong>Therapy</strong> *<br />

Isabelle Frohne - Hagemann<br />

Abstract:<br />

<strong>Aesthetic</strong>s have to do with how we perceive and evaluate the "world" (our<br />

experiences). From a philosophical perspective, little research has been done<br />

so far on the subject "<strong>Aesthetic</strong>” <strong>in</strong> music therapy. This is surpris<strong>in</strong>g, as<br />

different theories <strong>of</strong> aesthetics have a fundamental <strong>in</strong>fluence on music therapy.<br />

They reach from metaphysical to physical and from anaesthetiz<strong>in</strong>g to<br />

aesthetiz<strong>in</strong>g positions.<br />

A short discussion on the history <strong>of</strong> aesthetic theories from Plato to modern<br />

philosophers may help us to better place the different explicit and implicit<br />

philosophies and theories that are used by modern music therapists <strong>in</strong> order to<br />

legitimate their music therapy approaches.With regard to the development <strong>of</strong> a<br />

basic theory <strong>of</strong> music therapy it might be helpful to work out a meta-theory <strong>of</strong><br />

aesthetics that music therapists can refer to.<br />

It could be <strong>in</strong>terest<strong>in</strong>g to have a look at the aesthetic dimensions <strong>of</strong> music<br />

therapy s<strong>in</strong>ce it is <strong>in</strong> this field that various theories are applied that correspond<br />

with different historical periods. It may be <strong>in</strong>structive to relate the aesthetic<br />

positions <strong>of</strong> the last 2500 years and music therapy today, to provide a new<br />

and better aesthetic motivation to this k<strong>in</strong>d <strong>of</strong> therapy and promote an<br />

evolv<strong>in</strong>g development.<br />

The history <strong>of</strong> aesthetics is perhaps not as much a history <strong>of</strong> art than a history<br />

<strong>of</strong> the "body" 1 (German: Leib). <strong>Aesthetic</strong>s have to do with the awareness <strong>of</strong><br />

hav<strong>in</strong>g a body and be<strong>in</strong>g a body. One could assume it as the history <strong>of</strong><br />

suppress<strong>in</strong>g our bodily condition or, on the other hand overstress<strong>in</strong>g the<br />

importance <strong>of</strong> the ego.<br />

* 5. European congress for <strong>Music</strong> <strong>Therapy</strong>, Naples April 21rst to 24 th 2001<br />

1 In <strong>in</strong>tegrative music therapy the concept <strong>of</strong> "body" (Leib) implies the body (the pure matter),<br />

the soul and the spirit, all <strong>of</strong> them m<strong>in</strong>gled with the surround<strong>in</strong>g environment. We are not<br />

connected to our ecological environment only through the food cha<strong>in</strong> but also through our<br />

belong<strong>in</strong>g to the so called "social worlds" whose components taught us how to th<strong>in</strong>k, feel and<br />

act. The "body" <strong>in</strong>cludes all this. An American colleague once told me that <strong>in</strong> English it would<br />

be better to add "The person <strong>in</strong> the world" to the word "body". Or maybe the person seen as a<br />

bio psychosocial be<strong>in</strong>g or as an ecological be<strong>in</strong>g? I will put the word body <strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong>verted commas<br />

when the concept <strong>of</strong> the "Leib" is meant.<br />

1


Frohne-Hagemann, I (2001) <strong>Aesthetic</strong> <strong>Perspectives</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>Music</strong> <strong>Therapy</strong>. <strong>Music</strong><br />

<strong>Therapy</strong> Today (onl<strong>in</strong>e), November, available at www.musictherapyworld.<strong>in</strong>fo<br />

It is necessary at this po<strong>in</strong>t to clarify the notion <strong>of</strong> aesthetics. We generally<br />

mean <strong>in</strong> common language someth<strong>in</strong>g else than "bodily" perception. Our<br />

perception is related to objects as for <strong>in</strong>stance a nicely prepared table, a<br />

stylised Japanese garden. A well proportioned woman body is regarded to be<br />

aesthetic as well as a dance with harmonious movements. In these cases the<br />

aesthetic element emerges from an element which improves a trivial<br />

phenomena. It is called the "improv<strong>in</strong>g element" (Welsch, 1996, 24).<br />

<strong>Aesthetic</strong>s <strong>in</strong> its philosophical history was meant as an embellishment, a<br />

creation <strong>of</strong> objective art work and therefore as a way <strong>of</strong> master<strong>in</strong>g the world<br />

outside. The idea that the word aesthetics comes from "aisthesis" ("bodily" or<br />

sensitive perception) was not considered as essential although the "body" is<br />

man's only organ for perception and cognition!<br />

It was only with Feuerbach and Nietzsche that these concepts started hav<strong>in</strong>g<br />

such a mean<strong>in</strong>g attached to them (cfr. Jung, 1994; Petzold, 1985).<br />

Where is the world created and formed? Our "body" is the place where this<br />

happens. An aesthetics start<strong>in</strong>g from the "body" 2 <strong>in</strong> the sense <strong>of</strong> the "body" as<br />

a "complete sensorial organ", to quote Merleau-Ponty (1945) did not exist.<br />

The perception <strong>of</strong> the external reality was referred to what is beh<strong>in</strong>d the<br />

material world, the metaphysical part - from Plato to Romanticism - or to the<br />

subjective perspective - dur<strong>in</strong>g the Romantic Age. Either Materialism or<br />

Idealism but without any exchange processes between these two positions.<br />

And even today man does not consciously consider his "body" as a place <strong>of</strong><br />

aesthetic knowledge. On the contrary, the more the body (here: the pure<br />

matter) is the focus <strong>of</strong> attention, the more our "bodily" dimension is neglected;<br />

the more the body is made aesthetic the more it is made anaesthetized.<br />

In the digital era human body (meant as the body that we have but not the one<br />

that we are) appears more and more unnecessary (who needs a body <strong>in</strong> order<br />

to chat on the Internet?), but as <strong>in</strong> fact we need the body as a necessity as<br />

long as we live we try to dom<strong>in</strong>ate the body by programm<strong>in</strong>g and mould<strong>in</strong>g it<br />

as we like. Today as never before our body is submitted to aesthetical<br />

treatments, massages and relax<strong>in</strong>g techniques <strong>in</strong> fitness centres, sport clubs<br />

and beauty farms, and it is adorned with dresses, tattoos, pierc<strong>in</strong>g and so on<br />

(Kle<strong>in</strong>, 2000). With this body we present ourselves to the external world. Not "I<br />

am my body" (Marcel, 1985, but 15) I just possess a physical body. However,<br />

our "body" is still our total sensory organ through which we experience the<br />

world, get <strong>in</strong> touch with other people and live with heart and soul!<br />

2 The concept <strong>of</strong> aesthetics derived from aisthesis and the "body" means that man takes much more<br />

<strong>in</strong>to account his bodily relation towards whatever he creates. To create someth<strong>in</strong>g does not mean to<br />

only focus on external rules <strong>of</strong> aesthetic beauty but to perceive and feel (through the "body") what a<br />

certa<strong>in</strong> phenomenon (as for <strong>in</strong>stance a musical <strong>in</strong>strument or a musical idea) causes <strong>in</strong> us as<br />

perceptions, thoughts, associations, memories, images, emotions, and so on. We then perceive, <strong>in</strong><br />

turn, what comes out <strong>of</strong> the relationship between the "body" and the created object.<br />

2


Frohne-Hagemann, I (2001) <strong>Aesthetic</strong> <strong>Perspectives</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>Music</strong> <strong>Therapy</strong>. <strong>Music</strong><br />

<strong>Therapy</strong> Today (onl<strong>in</strong>e), November, available at www.musictherapyworld.<strong>in</strong>fo<br />

Now, if I really am my body and not only own one then I am identical with the<br />

entire world. This is because I keep <strong>in</strong> my body the history <strong>of</strong> my social life,<br />

the spirit <strong>of</strong> my time and I am m<strong>in</strong>gled with the environment I live <strong>in</strong>. This is the<br />

social - ecological mean<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> me be<strong>in</strong>g a "body". Therefore it does not make<br />

any sense just wish<strong>in</strong>g to mould the "body" aesthetically. On the other hand, it<br />

does make sense to abandon oneself to the "body", and therefore to the<br />

world, and thus trust the flow<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> our be<strong>in</strong>g.<br />

Let's take the example <strong>of</strong> the improvisation used <strong>in</strong> music therapy. What<br />

matters is not as much the aesthetical representation <strong>of</strong> a form. The client<br />

does not have to play "well" but start<strong>in</strong>g from an experience he is <strong>in</strong>vited to<br />

follow the flow<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> its becom<strong>in</strong>g, to follow the sounds as they come out <strong>of</strong><br />

him/herself and be surprised by the creative way <strong>in</strong> which they comb<strong>in</strong>e<br />

themselves and almost autonomously assume a Gestalt which unfolds its<br />

mean<strong>in</strong>g only with<strong>in</strong> this process. There is no reason to stick aesthetically to<br />

an externally established rule but it is the aesthetical process <strong>of</strong><br />

GESTALTBILDUNG 3 that matters.<br />

Philosophical aesthetics <strong>in</strong> history<br />

I would like to trace now, always mak<strong>in</strong>g short comments on music therapy<br />

aesthetical dimensions, the course <strong>of</strong> the history <strong>of</strong> aesthetics which, from a<br />

very metaphysical position gradually and cautiously also developed a<br />

consciousness for the position <strong>of</strong> the 'I am my "body"' dimension. Today<br />

aesthetics does not refer only to the completed object but starts process from<br />

the <strong>of</strong> the "body" <strong>in</strong> resonance: it is the bio psychosocial "body" which<br />

perceives and resonates. <strong>Aesthetic</strong> creation emerges by respond<strong>in</strong>g to the<br />

resonances <strong>of</strong> the "body". <strong>Aesthetic</strong>s is a process <strong>of</strong> cont<strong>in</strong>uous creation.<br />

It was not always like that. Let's have a look at history (Helferich, 1998, 464;<br />

Hauskeller, 1999, 9).<br />

Classical antiquity<br />

In classical antiquity the aims <strong>of</strong> aesthetics were the recognition <strong>of</strong> div<strong>in</strong>e<br />

perfection, truth and good. The aesthetic issue was also an issue <strong>of</strong><br />

epistemology. Issues perta<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g to philosophical aesthetics became only part<br />

<strong>of</strong> the figurative arts, because. art was able to represent reality visually and<br />

what one believes is generally considered more true than that which is felt<br />

through other senses.<br />

Accord<strong>in</strong>g to Plato the experience <strong>of</strong> beauty had an educational function. Art<br />

should not rouse our senses or excite our emotions. On the contrary it should<br />

teach man how to control his emotions and live a virtuous life and be <strong>in</strong>cl<strong>in</strong>ed<br />

to truth. Aristotle's, on the other hand, said that strong excitement, if<br />

3 With reference to the Gestalt psychology, a Gestalt is someth<strong>in</strong>g more and different from the sum <strong>of</strong><br />

the different components. A Gestalt is a cont<strong>in</strong>uous process <strong>in</strong> which the components relate to each<br />

other and to the whole. A subject will respond to the whole as an entity as well as to the parts. In fact it<br />

responds to the movements and relations.<br />

3


Frohne-Hagemann, I (2001) <strong>Aesthetic</strong> <strong>Perspectives</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>Music</strong> <strong>Therapy</strong>. <strong>Music</strong><br />

<strong>Therapy</strong> Today (onl<strong>in</strong>e), November, available at www.musictherapyworld.<strong>in</strong>fo<br />

experienced <strong>in</strong> the right place at the right moment, could by all means have a<br />

moral value and be compatible with m<strong>in</strong>d. Art was ma<strong>in</strong>ly seen as a valve <strong>of</strong><br />

affect and one should be <strong>in</strong> touch with it <strong>in</strong> a correct way. As <strong>in</strong> Plato's op<strong>in</strong>ion<br />

art served to metaphysics. In the world <strong>of</strong> art one was to meditate about ideas<br />

and the senses were to be domesticated.<br />

Such an aesthetic position, def<strong>in</strong>ed by W. Welsch as a "metaphysical<br />

position", was present throughout classical antiquity. Despite <strong>of</strong> a passionate<br />

admiration for everyth<strong>in</strong>g spiritual, it is a basically anti-sensory position. The<br />

senses and the "body" are actually a means to pass from sensory<br />

experiences to extrasensory ones. Therefore, the metaphysical position is<br />

essentially an "anaesthetiz<strong>in</strong>g aesthetics" (Welsch, 1990, 27).<br />

We f<strong>in</strong>d such a metaphysical position also <strong>in</strong> music therapy when music is<br />

used to transcend and/or dom<strong>in</strong>ate our drives rather than to express our<br />

personal emotions. It is present when music is used <strong>in</strong> order to arrange and<br />

structure the soul and the client is to follow the music as his/her teacher. We<br />

can f<strong>in</strong>d the same position not only <strong>in</strong> some music therapy conceptions, as for<br />

<strong>in</strong>stance Anthroposophical <strong>Music</strong> <strong>Therapy</strong>, but also <strong>in</strong> GIM or <strong>in</strong> Analytical<br />

<strong>Music</strong> <strong>Therapy</strong>, or whenever that we deal with the concepts <strong>of</strong> transcendence<br />

or sublimation.<br />

We could reproach Freud for not hav<strong>in</strong>g valued drives and the Id, because he<br />

wanted to submit them to the Ego. Accord<strong>in</strong>g to Freud be<strong>in</strong>g sensory should<br />

be sublimated. This can make sense <strong>in</strong> many cases but each music therapist<br />

has to ask him/herself whether he/she uses music <strong>in</strong> order to restra<strong>in</strong> or to<br />

<strong>in</strong>crease the "body's" wisdom and whether the sense perception itself is<br />

sufficiently valuated as a subject <strong>of</strong> reflection.<br />

Medieval aesthetics<br />

Back to history. In medieval aesthetics the purpose <strong>of</strong> art was not only to<br />

highlight beauty but also to show the essence <strong>of</strong> the <strong>in</strong>visible <strong>in</strong> through the<br />

visible, that is to reveal div<strong>in</strong>e signs to the world. What could not be perceived<br />

by the senses, was to be represented aesthetically us<strong>in</strong>g light and colours,<br />

thus through sight. The <strong>in</strong>visible needs symbols <strong>in</strong> order to be represented.<br />

This expla<strong>in</strong>s the wide use <strong>of</strong> symbols and allegories not only <strong>in</strong> the pictorial<br />

arts, but also <strong>in</strong> music.<br />

What cannot be perceived by the senses certa<strong>in</strong>ly is much more <strong>in</strong>terest<strong>in</strong>g<br />

than that which can be perceived. In music we perceive not only sounds but<br />

also take <strong>in</strong>to the awareness energy fields and relations (Zuckerkandl, 1963)<br />

which refer to symbolic mean<strong>in</strong>gs. They also play an important role <strong>in</strong> music<br />

therapy. However, as for the <strong>in</strong>terpretation <strong>of</strong> symbols and a general<br />

<strong>in</strong>terpretation there are different trends. Among music therapists some<br />

scholars consider the aesthetical representation and <strong>in</strong>terpret the<br />

extemporary work <strong>of</strong> art accord<strong>in</strong>g to certa<strong>in</strong> theoretical criteria while others<br />

prefer to concentrate on the aesthetical processes as for <strong>in</strong>stance <strong>in</strong>tensify<strong>in</strong>g,<br />

4


Frohne-Hagemann, I (2001) <strong>Aesthetic</strong> <strong>Perspectives</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>Music</strong> <strong>Therapy</strong>. <strong>Music</strong><br />

<strong>Therapy</strong> Today (onl<strong>in</strong>e), November, available at www.musictherapyworld.<strong>in</strong>fo<br />

widen<strong>in</strong>g, shorten<strong>in</strong>g, , distort<strong>in</strong>g, sharpen<strong>in</strong>g, <strong>in</strong>vert<strong>in</strong>g , merg<strong>in</strong>g or<br />

transpos<strong>in</strong>g musical motifs, figures and forms <strong>in</strong> their relation to psycho<br />

dynamical processes. The second group is the one I prefer. Instead <strong>of</strong> try<strong>in</strong>g to<br />

understand the symbol as an accomplished piece <strong>of</strong> aesthetical presentation I<br />

try to understand the symbolization. Symbolization is a way to create Gestalt<br />

configurations and an aesthetic dimension used f. ex. <strong>in</strong> Morphological <strong>Music</strong><br />

<strong>Therapy</strong> (accord<strong>in</strong>g to Salber, 1991, 6 Gestalt factors). Here the process <strong>of</strong><br />

transformation is more important than the created product.<br />

Two dimensions concern<strong>in</strong>g aesthetical perception come clearly out: some<br />

music therapists focus on the music as the accomplished creation <strong>of</strong> patients<br />

while the others highlight the act <strong>of</strong> creat<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> itself. As far as I know this last<br />

aesthetic position did not matter <strong>in</strong> the past.<br />

Renaissance<br />

Up to the XV century visible objects were considered as signs <strong>of</strong> a div<strong>in</strong>e<br />

<strong>in</strong>visible reality. Dur<strong>in</strong>g the Renaissance, <strong>in</strong>stead, objects now expressed<br />

themselves. If an object was considered beautiful, this meant to acknowledge<br />

the structural laws expressed by its appearance. Artists started to apply the<br />

laws <strong>of</strong> perspective. Th<strong>in</strong>gs can appear smaller or bigger, th<strong>in</strong>ner or larger,<br />

clearer or darker. Indeed, the discovery <strong>of</strong> perspective established a<br />

relationship between the object and the observer, the eyes. However,<br />

aesthetic perception rema<strong>in</strong>ed fixed on the object and was still basically<br />

visually oriented. There was no awareness <strong>of</strong> the sensory resonance <strong>of</strong> the<br />

"body" on the perception <strong>of</strong> the object.<br />

It is necessary to underl<strong>in</strong>e that the western aesthetics with its concepts <strong>of</strong><br />

experience and truth has been and still is strongly <strong>in</strong>fluenced by the Greek<br />

"theoreo" (I see). Cognition, and therefore theory, are connected to the eye<br />

which is as part <strong>of</strong> the bra<strong>in</strong>. This might be the reason why aesthetics were<br />

mostly applied to the pictorial arts and not so much to music. <strong>Aesthetic</strong>al<br />

concepts like vision, gaze, survey, perspective, lighten<strong>in</strong>g and so on have a<br />

visual nature and convey a different k<strong>in</strong>d <strong>of</strong> knowledge if compared with the<br />

sensory knowledge <strong>of</strong> hear<strong>in</strong>g, feel<strong>in</strong>g, touch<strong>in</strong>g and tast<strong>in</strong>g. This second k<strong>in</strong>d<br />

<strong>of</strong> knowledge has a "bodily" nature based on feel<strong>in</strong>gs, contacts, empathy and<br />

resonance. What is the difference between "hear<strong>in</strong>g some voices" and "have<br />

some visions"? The answer is that somebody who is "hear<strong>in</strong>g voices" is<br />

regarded to be a psychiatric case, whereas a person "hav<strong>in</strong>g visions" could<br />

be qualified to become a candidate at the State General Elections. The<br />

valuation <strong>of</strong> the importance <strong>of</strong> the eye goes along with a narrow-m<strong>in</strong>dedness<br />

for the other senses which means a reduction <strong>of</strong> knowledge!<br />

Romantic Age<br />

Dur<strong>in</strong>g the Romantic Age <strong>in</strong> the XVIII century an aesthetics <strong>of</strong> feel<strong>in</strong>g<br />

(Shaftesbury, Hutcheson, Burke) became to appear. What was perceived as<br />

beautiful could be considered as such, apart from the objective appearance <strong>of</strong><br />

5


Frohne-Hagemann, I (2001) <strong>Aesthetic</strong> <strong>Perspectives</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>Music</strong> <strong>Therapy</strong>. <strong>Music</strong><br />

<strong>Therapy</strong> Today (onl<strong>in</strong>e), November, available at www.musictherapyworld.<strong>in</strong>fo<br />

the object. The romantic approach which put human feel<strong>in</strong>gs on the<br />

foreground was prevail<strong>in</strong>g. The "felix estheticus" became the new ideal <strong>of</strong> man<br />

(Welsch, 1990, 28). This was the period when <strong>in</strong> 1750 Alexander Gottlieb<br />

Baumgarten <strong>in</strong> his work "Aestetica" (Schweizer, 1988) reconsiders the<br />

mean<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> aisthesis from which he takes the concept <strong>of</strong> sense perception and<br />

sense cognition. Man should become aesthetical himself through the arts.<br />

Such a conception could make us believe that man's sensibility, sensitivity and<br />

the wisdom <strong>of</strong> the "body", thus aisthesis, was to be recognized.<br />

But it was not like that. The "education <strong>of</strong> sensitivity", meant as an<br />

"ennoblement", to quote Schiller, marked the ultimate detachment from the<br />

primary sensory condition (Schiller, quoted <strong>in</strong> Welsch, 1996, 117). Accord<strong>in</strong>g<br />

to Schiller (1759 - 1805) art shows man what he could become, by realiz<strong>in</strong>g<br />

his becom<strong>in</strong>g a complete be<strong>in</strong>g through play<strong>in</strong>g. "Man is a complete human<br />

be<strong>in</strong>g only when he plays" (Schiller, quoted <strong>in</strong> Fricke, Göpfert, 1984, 618).<br />

However, Schiller did not mean by play<strong>in</strong>g a free game, or what is considered<br />

today a free improvisation, but he thought that when play<strong>in</strong>g we learn how to<br />

take possession <strong>of</strong> the "world", that is to mould it <strong>in</strong> order to possess it. He<br />

states that is necessary to modify everyth<strong>in</strong>g actively <strong>in</strong> a way that noth<strong>in</strong>g is<br />

as it was before but becomes as we want it to be (Schiller, 11. Lettera, 603).<br />

Schiller's theory reveals a lack <strong>of</strong> openness to submit oneself to an<br />

uncomplete process, to devote oneself to the subject and let us be changed by<br />

the material world. Schiller recommends, on the contrary, to control the<br />

material world. The world must be moulded and created without surrender<strong>in</strong>g<br />

to it and its peculiarities. "Festgemauert <strong>in</strong> der Erden, Steht die Form aus<br />

Lehm gebrannt; Heute soll die Glocke werden, Frisch, Gesellen, seid zur<br />

Hand; Soll das Werk den Meister loben, Doch der Segen kommt von oben" (<br />

the burnt clay shape is walled up <strong>in</strong> the earth; today the bell will be moulded,<br />

my friends be ready to operate; if the teacher praises the work it is from above<br />

that the bless<strong>in</strong>g comes) (Schiller, Die Glocke). This aga<strong>in</strong> is the situation <strong>of</strong><br />

the traditional aesthetics.<br />

We can see that the projects aim<strong>in</strong>g at mak<strong>in</strong>g the romanticism aesthetical did<br />

not recover the concept <strong>of</strong> aisthesis. If senses are only meant to serve for<br />

be<strong>in</strong>g educated and if they are not allowed to speak for themselves, it is better<br />

to become <strong>in</strong>sensitive and anaesthetized. <strong>Music</strong> teachers at colleges <strong>of</strong> music<br />

teach their students not to sense their own feel<strong>in</strong>gs and not to express<br />

themselves with the unprejudiced enthusiasm children still have. The<br />

musician who is taught to restra<strong>in</strong> his abilities with<strong>in</strong> the limits <strong>of</strong> aesthetical<br />

perfection will go to the doctor for <strong>in</strong>flammated tendons or to the psychoanalyst<br />

for be<strong>in</strong>g stressed. This is the other part <strong>of</strong> the process <strong>of</strong> becom<strong>in</strong>g<br />

anaesthetized. Shouldn't there be a correspondence between sens<strong>in</strong>g and<br />

mould<strong>in</strong>g?<br />

Also <strong>in</strong> music therapy there are therapeutical approaches based on the idea<br />

that everyth<strong>in</strong>g can be treated by apply<strong>in</strong>g perfect techniques and rules that<br />

the patient's soul. If our Governments compels us to demonstrate the<br />

effectiveness <strong>of</strong> music therapy methods and techniques but at the same time<br />

they should accept the concept <strong>of</strong> "aisthesis" as a treatment tool. In therapy<br />

6


Frohne-Hagemann, I (2001) <strong>Aesthetic</strong> <strong>Perspectives</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>Music</strong> <strong>Therapy</strong>. <strong>Music</strong><br />

<strong>Therapy</strong> Today (onl<strong>in</strong>e), November, available at www.musictherapyworld.<strong>in</strong>fo<br />

there are illnesses which, accord<strong>in</strong>g to modern aesthetics, cannot be solved if<br />

we do not give the client the possibility <strong>of</strong> com<strong>in</strong>g to an understand<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong><br />

his/her pa<strong>in</strong> by aesthetically process<strong>in</strong>g his/her own feel<strong>in</strong>gs, perceptions and<br />

actions. Play rules and tasks shouldn't be used as prescription but they should<br />

be <strong>of</strong>fered as different experience fields with<strong>in</strong> which the client experiments<br />

with the adequate aesthetical perspectives on his disturbances and where<br />

he/she is responsible for his will<strong>in</strong>gness to give <strong>in</strong> aesthetical poiesis.<br />

When we merely let us be moulded from an external norm, like Schiller's bell,<br />

we loses our "bodily" nature <strong>of</strong> perception and are forced to restra<strong>in</strong> our<br />

uniqueness. Our pseudo-aesthetical trend towards becom<strong>in</strong>g aesthetical by<br />

mould<strong>in</strong>g, absorb<strong>in</strong>g and exploit<strong>in</strong>g the world around us has devastat<strong>in</strong>g<br />

consequences: If everyth<strong>in</strong>g can be made and moulded, noth<strong>in</strong>g can<br />

possibly be felt <strong>in</strong> resonances and therefore noth<strong>in</strong>g can be improved <strong>in</strong><br />

an aesthetical process. What is left is a temporary kick out <strong>of</strong> it which leaves<br />

an empty space. Any perception is illusion and senseless without the ability <strong>of</strong><br />

empathy and resonance. In my op<strong>in</strong>ion, Schiller's idea <strong>of</strong> mould<strong>in</strong>g oneself and<br />

the world by play<strong>in</strong>g leads to nowadays conception accord<strong>in</strong>g to which we<br />

strongly anaesthetize ourselves with everyth<strong>in</strong>g aesthetical.<br />

Already 200 years ago, however, it was Kant who <strong>in</strong>dicated this different<br />

direction from the theoretical aesthetics perspective. In his Criticism <strong>of</strong> Reason<br />

(Kritik der Urteilskraft), § 9, (Weischedel, 1974) he claims that beauty comes<br />

from the "free game <strong>of</strong> cognitive abilities". A sensational statement! Accord<strong>in</strong>g<br />

to him beauty is not created out <strong>of</strong> the complete absence <strong>of</strong> rules but by the<br />

artist himself who <strong>in</strong>troduces his own aesthetical rules .<br />

Kant demonstrated that the basis <strong>of</strong> what we call reality is <strong>of</strong> fictious nature.<br />

We recognize only what we put <strong>in</strong>to the th<strong>in</strong>gs. But these recognitions<br />

are based on purely aesthetical suppositions(Welsch, 1996, 47).<br />

Nietzsche developed further Kant's knowledge: What we perceive as reality is<br />

based all together on aesthetical projections. Recogniz<strong>in</strong>g is therefore a<br />

ma<strong>in</strong>ly metaphoric activity (Welsch, 1996, 47).<br />

This aesthetical turn has a remarkable <strong>in</strong>fluence on hermeneutic and<br />

diagnostic issues <strong>in</strong> music therapy (Frohne-Hagemann, 1999a, b). <strong>Aesthetic</strong>al<br />

poiesis is cont<strong>in</strong>uous. This means that each acquired piece <strong>of</strong> cognition is just<br />

a temporary arrival po<strong>in</strong>t and at the same time the start<strong>in</strong>g po<strong>in</strong>t <strong>of</strong> a new<br />

movement <strong>of</strong> aesthetical search (hermeneutics). Any explanation, any<br />

<strong>in</strong>terpretation <strong>of</strong> a process <strong>in</strong> music therapy is a hypothesis that has to be<br />

verified.<br />

The aesthetical turn started by Kant and Nietzsche prevents us from putt<strong>in</strong>g<br />

diagnostic statements on record. It is necessary to be very cautious with<br />

cl<strong>in</strong>ical stigmatisation by music therapy improvisation. <strong>Music</strong>al processes can<br />

<strong>in</strong>dicate the texture and the activity <strong>of</strong> an illness (the process) but not a fixed<br />

classified disease.<br />

7


Frohne-Hagemann, I (2001) <strong>Aesthetic</strong> <strong>Perspectives</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>Music</strong> <strong>Therapy</strong>. <strong>Music</strong><br />

<strong>Therapy</strong> Today (onl<strong>in</strong>e), November, available at www.musictherapyworld.<strong>in</strong>fo<br />

Our clients' aesthetical way <strong>of</strong> act<strong>in</strong>g is a creative process (noth<strong>in</strong>g rema<strong>in</strong>s<br />

unchanged, everyth<strong>in</strong>g flows), a free "game <strong>of</strong> cognitive abilities". Accord<strong>in</strong>g to<br />

Nelson Goodman, born <strong>in</strong> 1906, the world is created on the basis <strong>of</strong> our way<br />

<strong>of</strong> be<strong>in</strong>g related to it, and the way we are consider<strong>in</strong>g, def<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g and describ<strong>in</strong>g<br />

the world (Goodman, 1968, 242). We take actively part <strong>of</strong> the cont<strong>in</strong>uous<br />

creation <strong>of</strong> lived world. Therefore the how, why and aim <strong>of</strong> perception and<br />

cognition are much more important than the perceived object. Each aesthetical<br />

perception no matter whether it the "body" is consciously <strong>in</strong> action or not, is<br />

already an <strong>in</strong>terpretation. What we consider true and real is only what matches<br />

our perceptive habits which can be very much different accord<strong>in</strong>g to the<br />

moment and the culture we come from. When we <strong>in</strong>terpret a music therapy<br />

improvisation we have to take <strong>in</strong>to account our previous aesthetical and<br />

theoretical assumptions about (music)therapy. This is important because<br />

by <strong>in</strong>terpret<strong>in</strong>g we also produce new realities.<br />

Modern aesthetics<br />

Modern aesthetics changes from be<strong>in</strong>g "op<strong>in</strong>ion (or attitude)" to be<strong>in</strong>g<br />

"(<strong>in</strong>ter)action". <strong>Aesthetic</strong>s means cont<strong>in</strong>uously to create and re-create.<br />

Understand<strong>in</strong>g and creation go together. A modern aesthetical experience <strong>in</strong><br />

music therapy is characterized by an exchange <strong>of</strong> a th<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong>g that is sensed<br />

and felt and a feel<strong>in</strong>g that is reflected by th<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong>g and act<strong>in</strong>g. This is the<br />

reference to the body.<br />

The body as a central concept<br />

Who has been the first <strong>in</strong> history to valuate the "bodily" sensory aspect and<br />

sensory cognition? Schopenhauer, Feuerbach and Nietzsche were the three<br />

philosophers who actually gave importance to the "body". Schopenhauer was<br />

the first to claim that the "body" is the foundation <strong>of</strong> cognition (Helferich, 1998,<br />

340). Art can only portray the ideas (because, as I would add, it serves our<br />

sight) while music is an expression <strong>of</strong> our own will. If music is an expression<br />

<strong>of</strong> our will, we can assume that man is able to feel this will <strong>in</strong> himself.<br />

Therefore "bodily" perceptions, music and sensory cognition are <strong>in</strong><br />

correspondence with each other. Such a "bodily"- musical correspondence"<br />

(Frohne-Hagemann, 1999b) is for me <strong>of</strong> the outmost importance because it<br />

shows the possibility <strong>of</strong> "recogniz<strong>in</strong>g" ourselves <strong>in</strong> musical creations through<br />

our "bodily" wisdom. When I listen to music and experience it <strong>in</strong> an<br />

aesthetical way, the <strong>in</strong>terpretation <strong>of</strong> such music is connected with my<br />

sensitiveness for the moment be<strong>in</strong>g, with my way <strong>of</strong> feel<strong>in</strong>g and with my<br />

personal and cultural experiences. There is less projection on my side rather<br />

than creation.<br />

Expression as a way <strong>of</strong> acquir<strong>in</strong>g knowledge was essential also <strong>in</strong> Benedetto<br />

Croce's op<strong>in</strong>ion (1866 - 1952). We acquire the knowledge <strong>of</strong> someth<strong>in</strong>g only<br />

the very moment <strong>in</strong> which we express a subjective feel<strong>in</strong>g (Croce, 1930,4).<br />

It is above all with Feuerbach (1985) and Nietzsche (1988, KSA 4, 15) that<br />

the dichotomy between physical body and spirit comes to be overcome.<br />

8


Frohne-Hagemann, I (2001) <strong>Aesthetic</strong> <strong>Perspectives</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>Music</strong> <strong>Therapy</strong>. <strong>Music</strong><br />

<strong>Therapy</strong> Today (onl<strong>in</strong>e), November, available at www.musictherapyworld.<strong>in</strong>fo<br />

Human "body" becomes a central concept without any metaphysical reference.<br />

Actually <strong>in</strong> the XX. Century aesthetics becomes more and more "physical" and<br />

therefore " lived world (lebensweltlich)" 4 because the body is meant as "the<br />

person <strong>in</strong> the world". The "body" is the embodiment <strong>of</strong> the world <strong>in</strong> which we<br />

live. <strong>Aesthetic</strong>s does not relate only to art but also to experiences <strong>in</strong> the lived<br />

world. Hence the experience <strong>of</strong> the "beautiful" arts expires. The <strong>in</strong>tegral world<br />

is completely out.<br />

Free improvisation and non conventional <strong>in</strong>strumental sounds make also the<br />

cacophony to be appreciated s<strong>in</strong>ce it is part <strong>of</strong> aesthetics just as is<br />

consonance and harmony. Heal<strong>in</strong>g means be<strong>in</strong>g able to look aga<strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong>to the<br />

abysses without suppress<strong>in</strong>g the feel<strong>in</strong>gs connected to it and be<strong>in</strong>g allowed to<br />

express one's feel<strong>in</strong>gs.<br />

In the middle <strong>of</strong> the last century Adorno (1903-1969) added an important<br />

aspect on the concepts <strong>of</strong> the aisthesis (Adorno, 1973, 53 and on). Art should<br />

not comply with today's "titty-ta<strong>in</strong>ment" (consumption <strong>of</strong> art and music as<br />

"suckl<strong>in</strong>g the tits" like a baby). It should not address unsatisfied people's need<br />

for enterta<strong>in</strong>ment. <strong>Aesthetic</strong>al processes are not comfortable. What is clear<br />

and simple to understand cannot be def<strong>in</strong>ed as art, neither as, I would say,<br />

therapy. <strong>Music</strong> <strong>Therapy</strong> deals with the <strong>in</strong>credible and the extraord<strong>in</strong>ary not<br />

only <strong>in</strong> the psyche but also <strong>in</strong> social life.<br />

Moreover Adorno underl<strong>in</strong>es the importance <strong>of</strong> the context and the critical<br />

judgement <strong>of</strong> social contexts and debates for understand<strong>in</strong>g and <strong>in</strong>terpretation.<br />

This is an aesthetical and gnoseologic dimension <strong>of</strong> music therapy that shows<br />

the importance to perceive the conditions <strong>of</strong> certa<strong>in</strong> socially determ<strong>in</strong>ed ways<br />

<strong>of</strong> life.<br />

F<strong>in</strong>ally I would like to take <strong>in</strong>to consideration another existential aspect <strong>of</strong><br />

aesthetics. We become more and more personally responsible <strong>of</strong> our way <strong>of</strong><br />

life and <strong>in</strong> our search for a coherent identity we note that and how we submit to<br />

an ongo<strong>in</strong>g process <strong>of</strong> aesthetical transformation. The more we undergo such<br />

a process the more aesthetics makes us confront with the <strong>in</strong>comprehensibility<br />

<strong>of</strong> be<strong>in</strong>g.<br />

Accord<strong>in</strong>g to Jean François Lyotard, born <strong>in</strong> 1924, aesthetics deals with<br />

<strong>in</strong>comprehensibility mean<strong>in</strong>g by that <strong>in</strong> the presence someth<strong>in</strong>g can happen<br />

that the <strong>in</strong>tellect cannot control (see Hauskeller, 1999, 95). Lyotard def<strong>in</strong>es this<br />

quality as the Sublime. The Sublime is someth<strong>in</strong>g too big and powerful to be<br />

completely understood by imag<strong>in</strong>ation. as Death is an example. Be<strong>in</strong>g obliged<br />

to stand the moment <strong>in</strong> which someth<strong>in</strong>g happens or does not happen is<br />

terrible but healthy at the same time. When a client <strong>in</strong> relation to his/her<br />

therapist lets his own sensitivity and feel<strong>in</strong>gs develop an aesthetical Gestalt<br />

both do not know where this journey will take them. They abandon themselves<br />

to the mere present, and what is <strong>in</strong>comprehensible is this be<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> the here<br />

and now. The <strong>in</strong>tellect has to confide completely <strong>in</strong> the "body" and "bodily"<br />

4 A world meant as <strong>in</strong>dividual, social and cultural realities experienced personally (Lebenswelt).<br />

9


Frohne-Hagemann, I (2001) <strong>Aesthetic</strong> <strong>Perspectives</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>Music</strong> <strong>Therapy</strong>. <strong>Music</strong><br />

<strong>Therapy</strong> Today (onl<strong>in</strong>e), November, available at www.musictherapyworld.<strong>in</strong>fo<br />

communication: a very important task from the po<strong>in</strong>t <strong>of</strong> view <strong>of</strong> commitment. It<br />

means to give up the anaesthetization <strong>of</strong> the body.<br />

From the post modern attitude <strong>of</strong> stress<strong>in</strong>g the unexpected and overcom<strong>in</strong>g<br />

rigid rules follows that also the music therapist should be open to the<br />

possibility that an improvisation might not develop along the therapeutic l<strong>in</strong>es<br />

he/she was expect<strong>in</strong>g that it should or could.<br />

Play rules should be considered as an open framework which can be<br />

abandoned each time it is needed for a s<strong>in</strong>gle client <strong>in</strong> regard to his<br />

perceptions, feel<strong>in</strong>gs and actions with<strong>in</strong> the therapeutic relationship.<br />

To summarize: we have experienced <strong>in</strong> the history <strong>of</strong> aesthetics a<br />

development and the shift from a metaphysical position towards a physical<br />

orientation <strong>of</strong> aesthetics (<strong>in</strong> the mean<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> "aisthesis") where the awareness<br />

<strong>of</strong> the process lies <strong>in</strong> the creation <strong>in</strong> itself.<br />

However, <strong>in</strong> spite <strong>of</strong> such a shift the anaesthetiz<strong>in</strong>g process goes on<br />

spread<strong>in</strong>g as a social way <strong>of</strong> anaesthetiz<strong>in</strong>g which leads to ignore the social<br />

needs. The results <strong>of</strong> modern aesthetical research do not f<strong>in</strong>d any resonance.<br />

Could a music therapy code <strong>of</strong> aesthetical awareness possibly contribute to<br />

change this process? From the aesthetical po<strong>in</strong>t <strong>of</strong> view it would be a major<br />

social service given by music therapy, not only to people <strong>in</strong> need <strong>of</strong> be<strong>in</strong>g<br />

treated but also to each and everybody.<br />

10


Frohne-Hagemann, I (2001) <strong>Aesthetic</strong> <strong>Perspectives</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>Music</strong> <strong>Therapy</strong>. <strong>Music</strong><br />

<strong>Therapy</strong> Today (onl<strong>in</strong>e), November, available at www.musictherapyworld.<strong>in</strong>fo<br />

References:<br />

Adorno (1973): Ästhetische Theorie, Frankfurt/Ma<strong>in</strong><br />

Bärmark, J., Hall<strong>in</strong>, M. (1999): Sail<strong>in</strong>g between the Charybdis <strong>of</strong> theoretical<br />

abstractions and the Scylla <strong>of</strong> unreflected experiences. In: Nordic<br />

Journal <strong>of</strong> <strong>Music</strong> <strong>Therapy</strong> 8 (2), 137-142<br />

Barz, H. (2000): Lebenskunst: Die Balance zwischen Muss und Muße. In:<br />

Psychologie heute, 9)<br />

Baumgarten, A.G.: Theoretische Ästhetik. Die grundlegenden Abschnitte der<br />

"<strong>Aesthetic</strong>a, hg. und übersetzt von Schweizer, H. R, Hamburg 1988<br />

Croce, B. (1930): Gesammelte philosophische Schriften <strong>in</strong> deutscher<br />

Übertragung, Bd. 1: Ästhetik als Wissenschaft vom Ausdruck und<br />

Allgeme<strong>in</strong>e Sprachwissenschaft, hrsg. von Feist, H. , Tüb<strong>in</strong>gen.<br />

Drewer, M. (2000): Gestalt - Ästhetik- Musiktherapie. Lit. Verlag, Münster<br />

Feuerbach, L. (1985): Anthropologischer Materialismus,. Ausgewählte Schriften<br />

Bd. I. Hg. von Alfred Schmidt, Frankfurt, Berl<strong>in</strong>, Wien<br />

Feyerabend, P. (1984): Wissenschaft als Kunst, Frankfurt/Ma<strong>in</strong><br />

Frohne-Hagemann, I. (1999a): Überlegungen zum E<strong>in</strong>satz musiktherapeutischer<br />

Techniken <strong>in</strong> der Supervision und zur speziellen Supervision<br />

musiktherapeutischer Situationen und Prozesse. In: Integrative Therapie 2-<br />

3, 25. Jg. Junfermann, Paderborn, 167-186<br />

Frohne-Hagemann, I. (1999b): Zur Hermeneutik musiktherapeutischer Prozesse.<br />

Metatheoretische Überlegungen zum Verstehen. In: Musiktherapeutische<br />

Umschau, 20, 103-113<br />

Frohne-Hagemann, I. (2000): Traumbearbeitung <strong>in</strong> der Integrativen<br />

Musiktherapie. In: Fitzthum, E., Oberegelsbacher, D., Storz, D. (Hrsg.):<br />

Wiener Beiträge zur Musiktherapie III, Praesens, Wien<br />

Goodman, N. (1968): Sprachen der Kunst. E<strong>in</strong> Ansatz zu e<strong>in</strong>er Symboltheorie,<br />

Frankfurt/Ma<strong>in</strong><br />

Hauskeller, M.(3/1999): Was ist Kunst? Positionen der Ästhetik von Platon bis<br />

Danto. Beck'sche Reihe<br />

Helferich, Chr. (1998): Geschichte der Philosophie von den Anfängen bis zur<br />

Gegenwart und östliches Denken, DTV, München<br />

Immanuel Kant: Werke <strong>in</strong> 10 Bänden. Bd. 10: Kritik der Urteilskraft § 9, Hrsg.<br />

Von Weischedel, W. (1974): Frankfurt/M.<br />

Kenny, C. B. (1999): Beyond This Po<strong>in</strong>t There Be Dragons. In: Nordic Journal <strong>of</strong><br />

<strong>Music</strong> <strong>Therapy</strong>, 8(2), 127-136<br />

Kle<strong>in</strong>, G. (2000): das Leibeigene. In: Die Zeit, 20.10.2000 Nr. 44<br />

Lyotard, J. F. (1987): Das Erhabene und die Avantgarde. In: Le Rider, J.:<br />

Verabschiedung der (Post)Moderne? Tüb<strong>in</strong>gen, 251-269<br />

Marcel, G. (1985): Leibliche Begegnung. In: Petzold, H. (Hrsg.): Leiblichkeit -<br />

Philosophische, gesellschaftliche und therapeutische Perspektiven,<br />

Junfermann, Paderborn<br />

Merleau-Ponty (1945): Phenomenologie de la perception, Paris<br />

Nietzsche, F. (1954 ): Sämtliche Werke Bd.1, Hrsg. von Schlechta, Hanser,<br />

München<br />

Nietzsche, F. (1980): Ueber Wahrheit und Lüge im aussermoralischen S<strong>in</strong>ne. In:<br />

Nietzsche, F.: (1988) Sämtliche Werke . Kritische Studienausgabe <strong>in</strong> 15<br />

Bänden, hrsg. von Giorgio Colli und Mazz<strong>in</strong>o Mont<strong>in</strong>ari, München<br />

Petzold, H. (Hrsg.): Leiblichkeit - philosophische, gesellschaftliche und<br />

therapeutische Perspektiven, Junfermann, Paderborn<br />

Petzold, H. (1993): Integrative Therapie, Bd. II/2, dar<strong>in</strong>: Das neue<br />

Integrationsparadigma, S. 927-1039<br />

Salber, W. (1991): Gestalt auf Reisen. Das System seelischer Prozesse. Bouvier,<br />

Bonn<br />

Schiller, F. (1980): Sämtliche Werke, Bd. 5: Über die ästhetische Erziehung des<br />

Menschen <strong>in</strong> e<strong>in</strong>er Reihe von Briefen, Hrsg. von Fricke, G., Göpfert, H.G.<br />

München, S. 570-669<br />

Ruud, E. (1998): <strong>Music</strong> <strong>Therapy</strong>: Improvisation, Communication and Culture.<br />

11


Frohne-Hagemann, I (2001) <strong>Aesthetic</strong> <strong>Perspectives</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>Music</strong> <strong>Therapy</strong>. <strong>Music</strong><br />

<strong>Therapy</strong> Today (onl<strong>in</strong>e), November, available at www.musictherapyworld.<strong>in</strong>fo<br />

Barcelona Publishers<br />

Welsch, W. (1990): Ästhetisches Denken, Reclam, Stuttgart<br />

Welsch, W. (1996): Grenzgänge der Ästhetik, Reclam, Stuttgart<br />

Zuckerkandl, V.v. (1963 ): Die Wirklichkeit der Musik, Rhe<strong>in</strong> Verlag<br />

12

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!