21.03.2013 Views

1 Dewey, Wittgenstein, and Linguistic Instrumentalism My paper ...

1 Dewey, Wittgenstein, and Linguistic Instrumentalism My paper ...

1 Dewey, Wittgenstein, and Linguistic Instrumentalism My paper ...

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

<strong>Dewey</strong>, <strong>Wittgenstein</strong>, <strong>and</strong> <strong>Linguistic</strong> <strong>Instrumentalism</strong><br />

<strong>My</strong> <strong>paper</strong> outlines some of the instrumentalist features of John <strong>Dewey</strong>’s<br />

philosophy of language. It will draw parallels to the later Ludwig <strong>Wittgenstein</strong>,<br />

especially Philosophical Investigations. While using <strong>Wittgenstein</strong> to illumine <strong>Dewey</strong>, I also<br />

believe <strong>Dewey</strong> elucidates <strong>Wittgenstein</strong>. 1 We will concentrate on their many similarities,<br />

leaving the task of working out any differences for another occasion. Whatever their<br />

discrepancies, I am inclined to believe they may be made to complement each other<br />

more than conflict. Mostly their dissimilarities involve the scope <strong>and</strong> purpose of<br />

philosophy, which <strong>Dewey</strong> pursues in its most expansive etymological sense. 2<br />

We will concentrate on such familiar themes in <strong>Wittgenstein</strong> as context, use,<br />

practice, <strong>and</strong> “form of life.” These resonate strongly with similar themes in <strong>Dewey</strong>.<br />

However, this approach is fraught with great danger since neither of them is a linguistic<br />

instrumentalist per se, although it does contribute to their thinking about language.<br />

Many make the catastrophic mistake of confusing <strong>Dewey</strong>’s instrumentalism with<br />

his entire philosophy. For him, “communication is consummatory as well as<br />

instrumental” (LW 1: 157). The consummatory phase or what he calls “immanent” or<br />

“sense” meaning includes instrumental linguistic reference while exp<strong>and</strong>ing on it.<br />

Involving feeling <strong>and</strong> doing not just thinking, consummatory meaning is an integral<br />

component of <strong>Dewey</strong>’s aesthetics. Those who accuse him of narrow instrumentalism<br />

ignore the fact that he wrote an influential book on aesthetics.<br />

Instrumental meanings, like logical means to ends, mediate experience while<br />

consummatory meanings are, like ends, immediately immanent in the intellectual<br />

1


eference. Immanent meanings provide a richer underst<strong>and</strong>ing <strong>and</strong> appreciation of an<br />

otherwise cold proposition. They are the unity not just of the thought that went into<br />

arriving at the conclusion or reference, but also of the feeling <strong>and</strong> action. It is largely a<br />

matter of distinguishing linguistic reference from an embodied, habitualized, <strong>and</strong> felt<br />

consummatory qualitative experience of the self in practical dynamic unity with the<br />

world, which the reference provides as an aid to coordinating our activity. 3<br />

While an ardent anti-dualist, <strong>Dewey</strong> is always willing to support subtle<br />

distinctions as long as we do not hypostatize them. Here is a particularly relevant<br />

example where he distinguishes among three aspects of experience:<br />

It is not possible to divide in a vital experience the practical, emotional, <strong>and</strong><br />

intellectual from one another <strong>and</strong> to set the properties of one over against the<br />

characteristics of the others. The emotional phase binds parts together into a<br />

single whole; “intellectual” simply names the fact that the experience has<br />

meaning; “practical” indicates that the organism is interacting with events <strong>and</strong><br />

objects which surround it. (LW 10: 61)<br />

Instrumental, referential, or what <strong>Dewey</strong> calls “significant” meanings emphasize the<br />

intellectual component of vital experience, while immanent meaning includes the other<br />

two phases in proper dynamic equilibrium. Immanent meanings involve an<br />

underst<strong>and</strong>ing, appreciation, perhaps even an enjoyment that depends on the prior<br />

achievement of objective intellectual reference. Because they are not cognitive, the<br />

affective <strong>and</strong> practical features are, in themselves, inarticulate. At best, words may only<br />

gesture toward them, yet they matter immensely in the wise conduct of life.<br />

2


Ignoring <strong>Dewey</strong>’s aesthetic dimension has disastrous consequences for<br />

comprehending his philosophy, including his philosophy of language. In Art as<br />

Experience, <strong>Dewey</strong> writes: “works of art are the only media of complete <strong>and</strong> unhindered<br />

communication between man <strong>and</strong> man that can occur in a world full of gulfs <strong>and</strong> walls<br />

that limit community of experience” (LW 10: 110). The artful use of language may<br />

achieve unhindered communication by creating a community of shared aesthetic<br />

communion. <strong>Dewey</strong> declares:<br />

Communication is uniquely instrumental <strong>and</strong> uniquely final. It is instrumen tal as<br />

liberating us from the otherwise overwhelming pressure of events <strong>and</strong> enabling<br />

us to live in a world of things that have meaning. It is final as a sharing in the<br />

objects <strong>and</strong> arts precious to a community, a sharing whereby meanings are<br />

enhanced, deepened <strong>and</strong> solidified in the sense of communion . . . . Here, as in so<br />

many other things, the great evil lies in separating instrumental <strong>and</strong> final<br />

functions. (LW 1: 159)<br />

As in poetry, proper non-instrumental use of language shows as well as says. We may<br />

create images with words. <strong>My</strong> insufficient discussion of <strong>Dewey</strong>’s consummatory<br />

“immanent meaning” implies a great evil of omission.<br />

I also wrong <strong>Wittgenstein</strong>. While we are mostly interested in his later work, the<br />

Tractatus already asserts that the richer meanings language seeks to communicate can<br />

only be shown, not said. At best, we may only point to them with words. “What we<br />

cannot speak about,” <strong>Wittgenstein</strong> (1922/ 2009) famously concludes, “we must pass<br />

over in silence” (§ 7). We get a clue as to what he is up to from his approving response<br />

3


to a poem sent to him by his friend Paul Engelmann: “And that is how it is: if only you<br />

do not try to utter what is unutterable then nothing gets lost. But the unutterable will be<br />

—unutterably—contained in what has been uttered” (Monk, 1990, 151). 4 One will never<br />

grasp the meaning of a poem if all one comprehends are its references. We may say the<br />

same of science, mathematics, logic, or any other intelligent activity theoretical or<br />

practical. Full underst<strong>and</strong>ing involves appreciating <strong>and</strong>, perhaps, enjoying inarticulate<br />

meanings that include linguistic reference, but go beyond it. We need a feel for the<br />

subject matter if we are to know what to do with it.<br />

<strong>Wittgenstein</strong>’s discussion of experience along with the distinction between<br />

“imponderable” <strong>and</strong> “documentary” evidence in Philosophical Investigations shares<br />

many similarities with <strong>Dewey</strong>’s distinction between “immanent” <strong>and</strong> “significant”<br />

meaning. <strong>Wittgenstein</strong> believes, “Imponderable evidence includes subtleties of glance,<br />

of gesture, of tone” (PI II § 228). Therefore, ”I may recognize a genuine loving look,<br />

distinguish it from a pretended one . . . . But I may be quite incapable of describing the<br />

difference. And this not because the languages I know have no words for it ” (228).<br />

With sufficient experience, almost everyone in all cultures learn to interpret someone’s<br />

mood by their facial gestures (See Ekman, 1973). It is easy to recognize fake smiles while<br />

few can say why. However, there is plenty of documentary (i.e., scientific) ev idence that<br />

fake smiles only involve the muscles around the mouth. <strong>Wittgenstein</strong> (1982) affirms:<br />

“An important fact here is that we learn certain things only through long experience<br />

<strong>and</strong> not from a course in school. How, for instance, does one develop the eye of a<br />

connoisseur?” (§ 925). His example is fine art. Most of us are connoisseurs of faces. Few<br />

4


ecome connoisseurs of fine art, but fundamentally there is little difference; both<br />

involve a felt consummatory appreciation of inarticulate meanings that can only be<br />

shown not said, yet the showing clearly has a determinate reference. 5<br />

<strong>Dewey</strong> rejects the traditional Western notion of language such as we find in John<br />

Locke (1690/ 1959) who argues:<br />

Besides articulate sounds, therefore, it was further necessary th at we should be<br />

able to use these sounds as signs of internal conceptions; <strong>and</strong> to make them st<strong>and</strong><br />

as marks for the ideas within his own mind, whereby they might be made known<br />

to others, <strong>and</strong> the thoughts of men’s minds be conveyed from one to another.<br />

(Book III, 3)<br />

Locke provides an instance of the picture theory of meaning that <strong>Wittgenstein</strong> himself<br />

held in the Tractatus. Locke’s position is similar mutatus mut<strong>and</strong>is to that of Rene<br />

Descartes, Ferdin<strong>and</strong> de Saussure, Edmund Husserl, St. Augustine as portrayed in<br />

<strong>Wittgenstein</strong>, <strong>and</strong> Jerry Foder’s Turing machine functionalism. What computers cannot<br />

do is process “immanent meaning” to achieve consummatory qualitative experience.<br />

They can only recursively churn out references as the next line of a program, but these<br />

will lack the emotional unity <strong>and</strong> practical interaction with events that comprise vital<br />

experience. A computer can no more properly interpret a poem than it can prove all the<br />

propositions of first order logic, although first order logic is formally complete. 6<br />

An untenable inner versus outer dualism, of which the dualisms of mind vs.<br />

body <strong>and</strong> knower vs. known are merely special cases, haunts most notions of language<br />

ancient, modern, or post-modern along with the correspondence theory of truth. <strong>Dewey</strong><br />

5


ejects all such dualisms along with correspondence. The notion that the mind should<br />

reflect external reality provides Richard Rorty (1979) with the title of Philosophy <strong>and</strong> the<br />

Mirror of Nature. There, he stridently challenges traditional philosophy of language <strong>and</strong><br />

epistemology.<br />

One of the most influential essays in analytic philosophy written by one of its<br />

most renowned proponents is W. V. O. Quine’s (1969) “Ontological Relativity.” It was<br />

the first annual <strong>Dewey</strong> lecture at Columbia University. What he says there goes a long<br />

way toward establishing the similarity between <strong>Wittgenstein</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>Dewey</strong>’s depiction of<br />

linguistic “use” <strong>and</strong> “context.” Quine finds: “Philosophically I am bound to <strong>Dewey</strong> by<br />

the naturalism that dominated his last three decades. With <strong>Dewey</strong> I hold that<br />

knowledge, mind, <strong>and</strong> meaning are part of the same world . . . . There is no place for a<br />

prior philosophy” (26). He further adds that, like <strong>Dewey</strong>, when discussing the<br />

philosophy of mind, he turns to linguistic meaning to comprehend higher mental<br />

functioning. <strong>Linguistic</strong>ally, he too wishes to avoid “pernicious mentalism” in semantics<br />

(27).<br />

In opposing mentalisms of all kind s, Quine cites <strong>Dewey</strong> in support of his own<br />

position: “Meaning . . . is not a psychic existence; it is primarily a property of behav ior”<br />

(27). Here is how Quine expresses his own opinion:<br />

Meanings are, first <strong>and</strong> foremost, meanings of language. Language is a social art<br />

which we all acquire on the evidence solely of other people’s overt behavior<br />

under publicly recognizable circumstances. Meanings, therefore, those very<br />

models of mental entities, end up as grist for the behaviorist’s mill. (26)<br />

6


He goes on to mention that once we underst<strong>and</strong> the use of language in its social context,<br />

we will realize there can be no private language. Again, h e cites <strong>Dewey</strong>: “ ‘Soliloquy,’<br />

he wrote, ‘is the product <strong>and</strong> reflex of converse with others’ “ (27). He cites yet another<br />

passage to enlarge the point: “Language is specifically a mode of interaction of at least<br />

two beings, a speaker <strong>and</strong> a hearer; it presup poses an organized group to which these<br />

creatures belong, <strong>and</strong> from whom they have acquired their habits of speech. It is<br />

therefore a relationship” (27). Quine acknowledges that his own stance owes much to<br />

<strong>Wittgenstein</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>Dewey</strong> before commenting: “Years later, <strong>Wittgenstein</strong> likewise<br />

rejected private language. When <strong>Dewey</strong> was writing in this naturalistic vein,<br />

<strong>Wittgenstein</strong> still held his copy theory of language” (27). Quine goes on to review the<br />

usual complaints against the uncritical semantics of the museum theory of meaning that<br />

<strong>Wittgenstein</strong> associates with his earlier self <strong>and</strong> Augustine in Philosophical Investigations.<br />

These criticisms readily extend, mutatis mut<strong>and</strong>is, to dualistic theories like that of Fodor<br />

<strong>and</strong> others already mentioned.<br />

Inspired by Quine <strong>and</strong> others, Richard Rorty (1979) famously combined them<br />

with <strong>Wittgenstein</strong>, <strong>Dewey</strong>, <strong>and</strong> Martin Heidegger to advance his own “epistemological<br />

behaviorism” conjoined with what he called “the linguistic turn.” 7 He takes on various<br />

versions of Descartes’ correspondence theory of truth, which assumes that we have<br />

truth when inner mental representations mirror the events <strong>and</strong> objects of nature.<br />

Relying on <strong>Dewey</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>Wittgenstein</strong> inspired arguments, Rorty eliminates not only the<br />

very idea of “the mind” as traditionally conceived, but also the entirety of epistemology<br />

7


as the pursuit of what <strong>Dewey</strong> calls “the quest for certainty.” 8<br />

Rorty specifically<br />

challenges Fodor (220 <strong>and</strong> elsewhere).<br />

Quine (1969) writes: “When we turn thus toward a naturalistic view of language<br />

<strong>and</strong> a behavioral view of meaning, what we give up is not just the museum figure of<br />

speech. We give up an assurance of determinacy” (28). He is correct. Quine uses<br />

<strong>Wittgenstein</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>Dewey</strong> to develop his own thesis of “ontological” indeterminacy,<br />

which goes far beyond the indeterminacy of ordinary translation:<br />

When . . . we recognize with <strong>Dewey</strong> that “meaning . . . is primarily a property of<br />

behavior,” we recognize that there are no meanings, nor likenesses nor<br />

distinctions of meaning, beyond what are implicit in people’s dispositions to<br />

overt behavior . . . . If by these st<strong>and</strong>ards there are indeterminate cases, so much<br />

the worse for the terminology of meaning <strong>and</strong> likeness of meaning. (29)<br />

In Quine’s “Ontological Relativity,” things turn out much the worse. The cor e of the<br />

argument derives from Quine’s example of an ostensive definition of “rabbit” in a<br />

hypothetical culture that uses “gavagai.” The ontological question is: Does it mean<br />

rabbit, “undetached rabbit part,” “rabbit stage,” or something else (30). The problem is<br />

that ostensive definition regardless of however much we come to agreement in action,<br />

fails to ultimately fix the meaning of “rabbit,” which may have an endless array of<br />

ontological assemblages. Identical twins raised in the same happy home may never be<br />

sure that they are in ontological agreement.<br />

With two such instances of internationally recognized philosophers such as<br />

Quine <strong>and</strong> Rorty not merely noting the similarity, but making extensive use of it to<br />

8


develop their own widely influential philosophical programs, it is remarkable that the<br />

resemblance between <strong>Wittgenstein</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>Dewey</strong> have not been more richly explored. 9 I<br />

do worry about their use of the word “behaviorism.” Quine <strong>and</strong> Rorty may somewhat<br />

misrepresent <strong>Dewey</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>Wittgenstein</strong>. <strong>Dewey</strong> worked out his ideas about language,<br />

intentionality, <strong>and</strong> mental functioning in collaboration with his long-time friend <strong>and</strong><br />

colleague George Herbert Mead. It might have helped if <strong>Dewey</strong> had used Mead’s<br />

phrase “social behaviorism” to describe linguistic activity. 10 However, a close reading of<br />

<strong>Dewey</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>Wittgenstein</strong> shows they more frequently use the word “action,” <strong>and</strong><br />

especially socially structured action. For instance, here is a typical <strong>Wittgenstein</strong>ian<br />

connection between words <strong>and</strong> a context of social action:<br />

We can also think of the whole process of using words . . . as one of those games<br />

by means of which children learn their native language. I shall . . . call the whole,<br />

consisting of language <strong>and</strong> the actions into which it is woven, the ‘language-<br />

game.’ (PI § 7)<br />

Examples like this one make it worth remembering that <strong>Wittgenstein</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>Dewey</strong> were<br />

former schoolteachers. The passage illustrates an instance of social learning. It is part of<br />

what we might call the pedagogical turn in the later <strong>Wittgenstein</strong> (see Macmillan, 1983).<br />

<strong>Wittgenstein</strong> frequently uses pedagogical examples, especially in On Certainty (1972),<br />

but we find many similar references in Philosophical Investigations (1953). Of course,<br />

<strong>Dewey</strong> was one of the most famous educators of the Twentieth-Century. In reference to<br />

Quine, it is useful to remember that <strong>Wittgenstein</strong> found “ostensive teaching of words”<br />

<strong>and</strong> training more fundamental than ostensive definition (PI § 6). <strong>Dewey</strong> simply says,<br />

9


“language is primarily a mode of action” (LW 1: 160). <strong>Dewey</strong> means social action of<br />

which teaching is a fine example. Elsewhere, <strong>Wittgenstein</strong> writes, “words are deeds”<br />

(CV 46). The word “deed” is especially cordial for pragmatists (pragma in ancient Greek<br />

meant “deed”). Below, I will use words like action, activity, deed, operation, <strong>and</strong><br />

practice interchangeably with behavior. 11<br />

<strong>Wittgenstein</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>Dewey</strong> (Heidegger as well) assert the primacy of social practice<br />

as the context for linguistic practice. <strong>Wittgenstein</strong> maintains that “the term ‘language-<br />

game’ is meant to bring into prom inence the fact that the speaking of language is part of<br />

an activity, or of a form of life” (PI § 23). Meanwhile, <strong>Dewey</strong> insists, “we have to be able<br />

to re-state the whole social context which alone supplies the meaning” (LW 1: 160).<br />

Most philosophers are familiar with what we might call the builders' language-game<br />

early in the Investigations. In this game, language enables communication between a<br />

builder A <strong>and</strong> an assistant B. They are building with blocks, pillars, slabs, <strong>and</strong> beams. B<br />

has to pass the materials in the order in which A needs them (PI § 2). One possible<br />

move in this game involves the request: “Bring me a slab” (PI § 19 ff.). Now compare<br />

<strong>Wittgenstein</strong>’s slab game to the following example of what we might call <strong>Dewey</strong>’s<br />

flower game:<br />

A requests B to bring him something, to which A points, say a flower. There is an<br />

original mechanism by which B may react to A's movement in pointing. But<br />

natively such a reaction is to the movement, not to the pointing, not to the object<br />

pointed out. But B learns that the movement is a pointing; he responds to it not in<br />

itself, but as an index of something else. His response is transferred from A's<br />

10


direct movement to the object to which A points. Thus he does not merely execute<br />

the natural acts of looking or grasping which the movement might instigate on<br />

its own account. The motion of A attracts his gaze to the thing pointed to; then,<br />

instead of just transferring his response from A's movement to the native reaction<br />

he might make to the thing as stimulus, he responds in a way which is a function<br />

of A's relationship, actual <strong>and</strong> potential, to the thing. The characteristic thing<br />

about B's underst<strong>and</strong>ing of A's movement <strong>and</strong> sounds is that he responds to the<br />

thing from the st<strong>and</strong>point of A. He perceives the thing as it may function in A's<br />

experience, instead of just ego-centrically [sic]. . . . Such is the essence <strong>and</strong> import<br />

of communication, signs <strong>and</strong> meaning. Something is literally made common in at<br />

least two different centres of behavior. To underst<strong>and</strong> is to anticipate together, it<br />

is to make a cross-reference which, when acted upon, brings about a partaking in<br />

a common, inclusive, undertaking. (LW 1: 140-141)<br />

Notice the importance of coordinating action with regard to some object literally made<br />

common in action. It is a three-term relationship involving A <strong>and</strong> B taking each other’s<br />

attitude with regard to a third thing, the referent (e.g., a slab or flower). This functional<br />

coordination resonates with <strong>Wittgenstein</strong>’s slab game (see especially PI §§ 18-21).<br />

If there is a difference between <strong>Wittgenstein</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>Dewey</strong>, it is that <strong>Dewey</strong> is not<br />

only offering a philosophy of language, but also a theory whereas the later <strong>Wittgenstein</strong><br />

eschews theory <strong>and</strong> argumentation in terms of describing linguistic games. O ften, he<br />

presents them pedagogically in terms of how someone like A might teach a tyro like B<br />

how to use words correctly within a form of life. Significantly, we now have extensive<br />

11


empirical research supporting this “theory” of language (see Tomasello 1999, 2008a, <strong>and</strong><br />

2008b). 12 We also now know that having mirror neurons is immensely helpful in taking<br />

the attitude of the other for organisms such as ourselves <strong>and</strong> many other species. 13<br />

While decrying scientism <strong>and</strong> the pretense of even good science to completing the quest<br />

for certainty, <strong>Dewey</strong> nonetheless thought philosophy participated in both literature <strong>and</strong><br />

empirical science. 14 Meanwhile, <strong>Wittgenstein</strong> insists that philosophy is separate from<br />

science (see Tractatus § 4.111 <strong>and</strong> PI § 109).<br />

Many consider <strong>Wittgenstein</strong>’s remarks on private language, “form of life,” <strong>and</strong><br />

grammar, or conventional normative rules-governed linguistic activity, as the most<br />

prominent notions in the Investigations. They are all intimately connected. Let us<br />

compare some remarkably resonate passages in <strong>Dewey</strong> on similar themes. We begin<br />

with the argument against private language. For <strong>Wittgenstein</strong>, a private-language, in<br />

which “individual words . . . are to refer to what can only be known to the person<br />

speaking; to his immediate private sensations” is not a genuine, meaningful, rule-<br />

governed language (PI § 243). The signs in language can only function when there is a<br />

possibility of judging the correctness of their use; so, “the use of [a] word st<strong>and</strong>s in need<br />

of a justification which everybody underst<strong>and</strong>s” (PI § 261). Compare <strong>Wittgenstein</strong> to<br />

<strong>Dewey</strong>: “Primarily meaning is intent <strong>and</strong> intent is not personal in a private <strong>and</strong><br />

exclusive sense” (LW 1: 142). <strong>Dewey</strong> finds that if “we had not talked with others <strong>and</strong><br />

they with us, we should never talk to <strong>and</strong> with ourselves” (135). Indeed, for <strong>Dewey</strong>, to<br />

have a mind at all is to have meaning: “Through speech a person dramatically identifies<br />

himself with potential acts <strong>and</strong> deeds; he plays many roles, not in successive stages of<br />

12


life but in a contemporaneously enacted drama. Thus mind emerges” (135). We owe our<br />

minds <strong>and</strong> selves to others, our family, community, <strong>and</strong> public institutions.<br />

The following is a fine statement of the importance of forms of life for <strong>Dewey</strong>’s<br />

theory of language with a stunning bonus at the end:<br />

Language is specifically a mode of interaction of at least two beings, a speaker<br />

<strong>and</strong> a hearer; it presupposes an organized group to which these creatures belong,<br />

<strong>and</strong> from whom they have acquired their habits of speech. It is therefore a<br />

relationship, not a particularity. This consideration alone condemns traditional<br />

nominalism. (LW 1: 145)<br />

The added advantage is that participating in structured social relations requires a role<br />

for universals, however restricted (perhaps to only a linguistic community of two; for<br />

example, a builder <strong>and</strong> assistant). For <strong>Dewey</strong>, “every meaning is generic or universal; it<br />

is something common between speaker, hearer <strong>and</strong> the thing to which speech refers”<br />

(147). The following from <strong>Wittgenstein</strong> says something similar:<br />

And hence also ‘obeying a rule’ is a practice. And to think one is obeying a rule is<br />

not to obey a rule. Hence it is not possible to obey a rule ‘privately’: otherwise<br />

thinking one was obeying a rule would be the same thing as obeying it. (PI § 202)<br />

For his part, <strong>Dewey</strong> reminds us: “Meaning is objective as well as universal” (LW 1: 148).<br />

The universality <strong>and</strong> objectivity of meaning depends on its intersubjectivity. Remember<br />

that the builder A <strong>and</strong> assistant B must come to intersubjective agreement regarding the<br />

referent that coordinates their trans-action.<br />

13


<strong>Wittgenstein</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>Dewey</strong> concur on the conventional socially normative (i.e.,<br />

grammatical) nature of language, but are cautious about avoiding a common confusion.<br />

For them, linguistic conventions arise from (largely tacit) agreement in action <strong>and</strong> not<br />

convening a convention where we vote on meanings or some such. <strong>Dewey</strong> insists:<br />

The particular physical existence which has meaning is, in the case of speech, a<br />

conventional matter. But the convention or common consent which sets it apart<br />

as a means of recording <strong>and</strong> communicating meaning is that of agreement in<br />

action; of shared modes of responsive behavior <strong>and</strong> participation in their<br />

consequences. The physical sound or mark gets its meaning in <strong>and</strong> by conjoint<br />

community of functional use, not by any explicit convening in a "convention" or<br />

by passing resolutions that a certain sound or mark shall have a specified<br />

meaning. (LW 12: 52)<br />

Here is how <strong>Wittgenstein</strong> says something quite similar:<br />

“So you are saying that human agreement decides what is true <strong>and</strong> what is<br />

false?" -- It is what human beings say that is true <strong>and</strong> false; <strong>and</strong> they agree in the<br />

language they use. That is not agreement in opinions but in form of life. (PI §241;<br />

see also PI II p. 226) 15<br />

It is an important point. For instance, Jacques Derrida (1974) follows Ferdin<strong>and</strong> de<br />

Saussure (1916/ 1972) in exploring the arbitrariness of language; however, he also<br />

follows him in ignoring the forms of life whence language emerges <strong>and</strong> that acts to<br />

considerably constrain “undecidable” deconstructive possibilities. Saussure <strong>and</strong><br />

Derrida sometimes seem to think language resembles a constitutional convention.<br />

14


<strong>Dewey</strong> remarks: “For a meaning is a method of action, a way of using things as a<br />

means to a shared consummation . . . . Meanings are rules for using <strong>and</strong> interpreting<br />

things; interpretation being always an imputation of potentiality for some consequence”<br />

(LW 1: 147). At first, the following long passage from Investigations appears to contradict<br />

<strong>Dewey</strong>:<br />

This was our paradox: no course of action could be determined by a rule, because<br />

every course of action can be made out to accord with the rule. The answer was:<br />

if everything can be made out to accord with the rule, then it can also be made<br />

out to conflict with it. And so there would be neither accord nor conflict. . . .<br />

What this shews is that there is a way of grasping a rule which is not an<br />

interpretation, but which is exhibited in what we call “obeying the rule” <strong>and</strong><br />

“going against it” in actual cases. (PI § 201)<br />

Let us begin to resolve the seeming conflict by quoting the following passage that leads<br />

up to the one just cited:<br />

“But how can a rule shew me what I have to do at this point? Whatever I do is, on<br />

some interpretation, in accord with the rule."— That is not what we ought to say,<br />

but rather: any interpretation still hangs in the air along with what it interprets,<br />

<strong>and</strong> cannot give it any support. Interpretations by themselves do not determine<br />

meaning. "Then can whatever I do be brought into accord with the rule?"— Let<br />

me ask this: what has the expression of a rule—say a sign-post— got to do with<br />

my actions? What sort of connexion is there here?— Well, perhaps this one: I<br />

have been trained to react to this sign in a particular way, <strong>and</strong> now I do so react<br />

15


to it. But that is only to give a causal connexion; to tell how it has come about<br />

that we now go by the sign-post; not what this going-by-the sign really consists<br />

in. On the contrary; I have further indicated that a person goes by a sign -post<br />

only in so far as there exists a regular use of sign-posts, a custom. (PI § 198)<br />

<strong>Wittgenstein</strong> explicitly states that an isolated interpretation alone does not decide<br />

meaning while <strong>Dewey</strong> seems to say it does. 16 But, look again. <strong>Wittgenstein</strong> is saying<br />

shared practice is more important to rule following than interpretation, although it has<br />

a place. Meanwhile, <strong>Dewey</strong> argues that while meanings are rules for using <strong>and</strong><br />

interpreting things; it is primarily a “method of action,” that is, customary practice (i.e.,<br />

organized deeds, actions, <strong>and</strong> not just r<strong>and</strong>om behavior). <strong>Wittgenstein</strong>’s emphasis on<br />

custom helps connect him to <strong>Dewey</strong>. <strong>Wittgenstein</strong> writes: “To obey a rule, to make a<br />

report, to give an order, to play a game of chess, are customs (uses, institutions)” (PI §<br />

199; italics in original). We grasp a rule beyond the limits of explicit interpretation when<br />

we follow the cultural customs (norms, grammar, etc.) that apply to a contextually<br />

dependent practice. <strong>Wittgenstein</strong> wants us to “make a radical break with the idea that<br />

language always functions in one way, always serves the same purpose: to convey<br />

thoughts – which may be about houses, pains, good <strong>and</strong> evil, or anything else you<br />

please “(PI § 304). Communicating thoughts <strong>and</strong> desires, even if that is fully possible,<br />

only contributes to coordinating human action. The coordination itself is what is most<br />

crucial. Think of a sign-post, such as a stop sign. Rules coordinate action (public<br />

practice) around objects (laws, institutions, <strong>and</strong> such) within a form of life. However, it<br />

is not primarily about agreement in communicating an opinion, an interpretation, or<br />

16


even following a rule correctly. More fundamentally, it is about agreement in action<br />

within a customary form of life whence we may subsequently communicate opinion<br />

<strong>and</strong> interpretation or formulate rules.<br />

<strong>Dewey</strong> too makes many references to customs, often with accompanying<br />

comments about embodied habits, which does differentiate him some from<br />

<strong>Wittgenstein</strong>. We acquire our habits from our habitat, which includes habits of social<br />

convention such as rule following <strong>and</strong> language, by participating in the norm-governed<br />

customary practices of our community. Social practices occupy us from birth if not<br />

before:<br />

We often fancy that institutions, social custom, collective habit, have been<br />

formed by the consolidation of individual habits. In the main this supposition is<br />

false to fact . . . . But to a larger extent customs persist because individuals form<br />

their personal habits under conditions set by prior customs. (MW 14: 42)<br />

Customs have us as experienced necessities that condition our habits of conduct long<br />

before we reflectively have them. For better <strong>and</strong> worse, unconscious embodied cognitive<br />

habits of practice often take over where explicit cognitive reasoning, rule following, <strong>and</strong><br />

interpretation fail. While we may interpret <strong>and</strong> follow rules many different ways in the<br />

context of a socially organized practice (i.e., form of life), the epideictic rhetoric of those<br />

already initiated in the practice such as the builder A in the builder’s game will only<br />

approve a very narrow range of interpretations. In driver’s training, we learn the rules<br />

of the road including how to habitually react to the various sign -posts we will<br />

encounter along the way. Successful ostensive teaching <strong>and</strong> training tell us “how it has<br />

17


come about that we now go by the sign-post; not what this going-by-the sign really<br />

consists in” (op. cit.). If our practice is not socially satisfactory, those empowered to<br />

enforce the laws may pursue <strong>and</strong> punish infractions. The institutional social practice<br />

called courts will decide the correct interpretation. Those who cannot acquire the habits<br />

of some customary practice will find themselves more or less ostracized from the<br />

society or repeatedly punished by it. 17<br />

So far, we still have only a partial connection between <strong>Wittgenstein</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>Dewey</strong><br />

regarding customs <strong>and</strong> practice. I believe a <strong>Dewey</strong>an underst<strong>and</strong>ing of habits helps us<br />

better underst<strong>and</strong> what <strong>Wittgenstein</strong> is up to in his discussion of customs. For <strong>Dewey</strong>,<br />

“habits are arts,” that is they “involve skill of sensory <strong>and</strong> motor organs, cunning or<br />

craft, <strong>and</strong> objective materials” (15). Habits are embodied know how:<br />

But after all, this practical work done by habit <strong>and</strong> instinct in securing prompt<br />

<strong>and</strong> exact adjustment to the environment is not knowledge, except by cou rtesy.<br />

Or, if we choose to call it knowledge—<strong>and</strong> no one has the right to issue an ukase<br />

to the contrary—then other things also called knowledge, knowledge of <strong>and</strong> about<br />

things, knowledge that things are thus <strong>and</strong> so, knowledge that involves reflection<br />

<strong>and</strong> conscious appreciation, remains of a different sort . . . . For it is a<br />

commonplace that the more suavely efficient a habit the more unconsciously it<br />

operates. (MW 14: 124-125)<br />

What we have here is the distinction between “knowing that” <strong>and</strong> “knowing how.”<br />

Habits are the means of knowing how, which is why <strong>Dewey</strong> declares: “Concrete habits<br />

do all the perceiving, recognizing, imagining, recalling, judging, conceiving <strong>and</strong><br />

18


easoning that is done . . . . Yet habit does not, of itself, know, for it does not of itself<br />

stop to think, observe or remember” (124). Since habits can conceive <strong>and</strong> judge, they<br />

provide the know how, techne, cunning, <strong>and</strong> craft of practice.<br />

As far as I know, <strong>Wittgenstein</strong> has little if anything to say about habits, although<br />

he does say a lot about training. 18 Hence, he does say things such as: “To underst<strong>and</strong> a<br />

language means to be a master of a technique” (§ 199). We may know how to perform the<br />

various techniques of a practice, know how to use the blocks, pillars, slabs, <strong>and</strong> beams<br />

of a builders’ game, yet lack statable knowledge that certain things <strong>and</strong> relations are thus<br />

as so. As your assistant, I may habitually bring you a slab every time you ask for it<br />

without underst<strong>and</strong>ing what I am doing much less being able to state it, although you<br />

may as a master builder. Due to such observations, <strong>Wittgenstein</strong> writes: “We may say:<br />

only someone who already knows how to do something with it [the King in chess] can<br />

significantly ask a name” (§ 31). Statable knowledge, “knowing that,” often depends on<br />

a prior “knowing how” within a cultural practice. It is exceedingly common for people<br />

to know how to do something, but not be able to state how they do it. We can also know<br />

how to play games properly without being able to state their rules. 19<br />

Because primordially language is something we make <strong>and</strong> use in a context to<br />

mediate social practices, <strong>Dewey</strong> frequently calls one component of his philosophy of<br />

language <strong>and</strong> logic (i.e., organum) instrumentalism. Here is an example:<br />

"Utensils" were discussed . . . in connection with the useful arts <strong>and</strong> knowledge,<br />

<strong>and</strong> their indispensable relation with science pointed out. But at every point<br />

appliances <strong>and</strong> application, utensils <strong>and</strong> uses, are bound up with directions,<br />

19


suggestions <strong>and</strong> records made possible by speech; what has been said about the<br />

role of tools is subject to a condition supplied by language, the tool of tools. (LW<br />

1: 134)<br />

<strong>Wittgenstein</strong> too has plenty to say about tools in his variants on the builder’s game (PI<br />

§§ 11, 14, 15, 41, 42, <strong>and</strong> elsewhere). He explicitly states: “Language is an instrument. Its<br />

concepts are instruments” (PI § 569). Indeed, since a competent practitioner must<br />

embody the skilled habits of the practice, we may feel confident that <strong>Wittgenstein</strong><br />

would agree with <strong>Dewey</strong> when he remarks:<br />

Yet till we underst<strong>and</strong> operations of the self as the tool of tools, the means in all<br />

use of means, specifying its differential activities in their distinctive<br />

consequences in varying qualities of what is experienced, science is incomplete<br />

<strong>and</strong> the use made of it is at the m ercy of an unknown factor, so that the ultimate<br />

<strong>and</strong> important consequence is in so far a matter of accident. (LW 1: 189-190)<br />

Intending to deflate the bloated claims of philosophical idealism <strong>and</strong> rationalism,<br />

<strong>Dewey</strong> insisted that all reasoning was practical means-ends reasoning. The pretense of<br />

pure reason is simply a misleading elitist hypostatization of abstractions drawn from<br />

the various practices. He remarks: “There is nothing novel nor heterodox in the notion<br />

that thinking is instrumental. The very word is redolent of an Organum —whether<br />

novum or veterum.” (MW 10: 367). Similarly, <strong>Wittgenstein</strong> urges: “Look at the word ‘to<br />

think’ as a tool” (PI § 53). Language <strong>and</strong> logic contribute to the practical arts of making<br />

meaning <strong>and</strong> using the meanings made to make other things with forms of life. Of<br />

20


course, as we said at the beginning, for <strong>Dewey</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>Wittgenstein</strong>, language <strong>and</strong> logic are<br />

more than tools, but that is a topic for another time.<br />

Bibliography<br />

Citations of the works of <strong>Dewey</strong> are to the critical edition published by Southern Illinois<br />

University Press. Volume <strong>and</strong> page numbers follow the initials of the series.<br />

Abbreviations for the volumes used are:<br />

EW The Early Works (1882-1898)<br />

MW The Middle Works (1899-1924)<br />

LW The Later Works (1925-1953)<br />

Black, M. (1962). <strong>Dewey</strong>'s Philosophy of Language. The Journal of Philosophy, Vol. 59, No.<br />

19, 505-523.<br />

Crocker, T. (1998). <strong>Wittgenstein</strong>’s Practices <strong>and</strong> Peirce’s Habits: Agreement in Human<br />

Activity. History of Philosophy Quarterly. Vol. 15, No. 4.<br />

Dreyfus, H. (1992). What Computers Still Can’t Do: A Critique of Artificial Reason.<br />

Cambridge, Mass.: The MIT Press.<br />

Derrida, J. (1974). Of Grammatology, trans. Gayatri Chakravorty Spivak. Baltimore: Johns<br />

Hopkins Press.<br />

Ekman, P. (1973). Darwin <strong>and</strong> Facial Expression: A Century of Research in Review. New<br />

York: Academic Press.<br />

Klagge, J. (2011). <strong>Wittgenstein</strong> in Exile. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.<br />

Locke, J. (1690/ 1959). An Essay Concerning Human Underst<strong>and</strong>ing: Volume II. New York:<br />

Dover.<br />

21


Medina, M. (2004). In Defense of Pragmatic Contextualism: <strong>Wittgenstein</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>Dewey</strong> On<br />

Meaning <strong>and</strong> Agreement. The Philosophical Forum, Vol. XXXV, No. 3, 341-369.<br />

Macmillan, C. J. B. (1983). "On Certainty" <strong>and</strong> Indoctrination. Synthese, Vol. 56, No. 3,<br />

363-372.<br />

Mead, G. H. (1934/ 1967). Mind, Self, <strong>and</strong> Society: From the St<strong>and</strong>point of a Social<br />

Behaviorist. Charles W. Morris (ed.). Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.<br />

Monk, R. (1990). Ludwig <strong>Wittgenstein</strong>: The Duty of Genius. New York, N. Y.: Penguin<br />

Books.<br />

Provine, R. (2005). Yawning. American Scientist. Vol. 93, 532-539.<br />

Putnam, Hilary (2002). The Collapse of the Fact/Value Dichotomy. Cambridge, Mass.:<br />

Harvard University Press.<br />

Quine, W. V. (1969). Ontological relativity. In W. V. Quine, Ontological Relativity <strong>and</strong><br />

Other Essays (26-68). New York: Columbia University Press.<br />

Richard Rorty (1961). "Pragmatism, Categories, <strong>and</strong> Language." Philosophical Review.<br />

Vol. 70, No. 2.<br />

Rorty, R. (1979). Philosophy <strong>and</strong> the mirror of nature. Princeton, N. J.: Princeton University<br />

Press.<br />

Rorty, R. (1982). "Pragmatism, Relativism, <strong>and</strong> Irrationalism." Consequences of Pragmatism,<br />

Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.<br />

Saussure, F. (1916/ 1972). Course in General <strong>Linguistic</strong>s. Chicago, Ill.: Open Court.<br />

Scarry, E. (1985). The Body in Pain: The Making <strong>and</strong> Unmaking of the World. Oxford: Oxford<br />

University Press.<br />

22


Tomasello, M. (1999). The Cultural Origins of Human Cognition. Cambridge, Mass.:<br />

Harvard University Press.<br />

Tomasello, M. (2008a). Cooperation <strong>and</strong> Communication in the 2nd Year of Life. Child<br />

Development Perspectives, Vol. 1, No. 1, 8-12.<br />

Tomasello, M. (2008b). Origins of Human Communication. Cambridge, Mass.: The MIT<br />

Press.<br />

<strong>Wittgenstein</strong>, Ludwig (1922/ 2009). Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus. New York, N.Y.:<br />

Rutledge.<br />

<strong>Wittgenstein</strong>, L. (1953). Philosophical Investigations. New York: The Macmillan Company.<br />

PI in the text.<br />

<strong>Wittgenstein</strong>, L. (1972). On Certainty. New York: Harper & Row.<br />

<strong>Wittgenstein</strong>, L. (1978). Remarks on the Foundations of Mathematics. Oxford: Basil<br />

Blackwell.<br />

<strong>Wittgenstein</strong>, L. (1980). Culture <strong>and</strong> Value. Oxford: Blackwell.<br />

<strong>Wittgenstein</strong>, L. (1982). Last Writings On The Philosophy Of Psychology. Chicago:<br />

University of Chicago Press.<br />

1<br />

In his Introduction to <strong>Dewey</strong>'s The Quest for Certainty, Stephen Toulmin remarks<br />

"Viewing <strong>Wittgenstein</strong> as a pragmatist of a sophisticated kind can certainly be helpful”<br />

(LW 4: xiii). Toulmin, who studied with <strong>Wittgenstein</strong> in 1940 <strong>and</strong> again in 1946-1947,<br />

draws many favorable comparisons between <strong>Wittgenstein</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>Dewey</strong> in his<br />

introduction.<br />

2<br />

<strong>Dewey</strong> alludes to the etymological sense of philosophy in many places including the<br />

ensuing:<br />

Philosophy is love of wisdom, of wisdom which is not knowledge <strong>and</strong> which<br />

nevertheless cannot be without knowledge. The need of an organ on of criticism<br />

which uses knowledge of relations among events to appraise the casual,<br />

23


immediate goods that obtain among men is not a fact of philosophy, but of<br />

nature <strong>and</strong> life (LW 1: 305-306).<br />

It is not easy to find anything so bold <strong>and</strong> broad in <strong>Wittgenstein</strong>, although I sense its<br />

presence. He is a far more encompassing philosopher than many of his followers<br />

appreciate.<br />

Oftentimes in the Tractatus <strong>Wittgenstein</strong> seems to think that all there is to<br />

philosophy is the logical clarification of propositions, which function as pictures of<br />

reality. If a proposition is incapable of picturing reality, it is nonsense. Logic itself<br />

cannot discover empirical truths only distinguish sense from nonsense. There is much<br />

more that we may show, but never say. Once we complete the task of the logical<br />

clarification of propositions, there is no more work for philosophy to perform.<br />

Therefore, the earlier <strong>Wittgenstein</strong> thought he had brought philosophy to an end with<br />

the publication of the Tractatus. After the critiques of Frank Ramsey <strong>and</strong> others,<br />

<strong>Wittgenstein</strong> ab<strong>and</strong>oned this position. It increased the scope of what he considered<br />

philosophy.<br />

Many analytic philosophers <strong>and</strong> those in the ordinary language tradition read<br />

the Philosophical Investigations as clarifying philosophical (i.e., not empirical) problems<br />

<strong>and</strong> thereby relieving us from the bewitchment of language that, among other things,<br />

leads us to assume that words always have a reference. They assume we may establish<br />

normative logico-grammatical conceptual truths constitutive of any empirical<br />

propositional truth within a language game. Often, they confine themselves to<br />

investigating the proper rule-governed use of language. While no doubt correct as far as<br />

it goes, such a reading of the later <strong>Wittgenstein</strong> results in a logico-grammatical<br />

transcendentalism that underst<strong>and</strong>s the role of philosophy in much the same way as the<br />

Tractatus. Some accept this formal transcendentalism <strong>and</strong> combine it with an almost<br />

mystical transcendentalism about the meanings that transcend the limits of langua ge.<br />

<strong>Dewey</strong>ans reject all form versus content dualisms <strong>and</strong> all forms of transcendental (e.g.,<br />

Kant) or transcendent (e.g., Plato) philosophy. However, they do agree that there is a<br />

great deal that transcends conceptual containment (e.g., the New Engl<strong>and</strong><br />

Transcendentalists). We only need to exp<strong>and</strong> the scope of philosophy to include extralinguistic<br />

underst<strong>and</strong>ing <strong>and</strong> appreciation to bring <strong>Wittgenstein</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>Dewey</strong> into<br />

agreement.<br />

For <strong>Dewey</strong>, all sentient beings have completely anoetic experiences that<br />

transcend the limits of language. Further, there is “immanent meaning” or what he<br />

more frequently calls “sense” meaning, that assumes but surpasses linguistic reference.<br />

<strong>Dewey</strong> thought we could not fully underst<strong>and</strong> the meaning of a proposition without<br />

appreciating it qualitatively, emotionally, <strong>and</strong> in embodied (habitual) action. <strong>Dewey</strong><br />

asserts: “A universe of experience is the precondition of a universe of discourse.<br />

Without its controlling presence, there is no way to determine the relevancy, weight or<br />

coherence of any designated [conceptual] distinction or relation” (LW 12: 74).<br />

“Experience” is <strong>Dewey</strong>’s word for all that occurs when any sentient creature such as<br />

ourselves trans-acts with other events in the universe. When we experience, we<br />

experience existence whence we m ay construct meaning <strong>and</strong> knowledge. We must<br />

24


carefully distinguish existence from the essences we make from it. No one creates ex<br />

nihilo. Beyond the bounds of such constructions many aspects of life are such that we<br />

may artistically show them to each other, but otherwise must remain eternally silent.<br />

We may approach such aspects of existence linguistically through poetry <strong>and</strong><br />

nonlinguistically through other arts.<br />

<strong>Dewey</strong> finds that philosophy participates in both the actualities disclosed by<br />

empirical science <strong>and</strong> the possibilities disclosed by literature (including poetry) <strong>and</strong> all<br />

the other arts (LW 1: 304-305). <strong>Dewey</strong> took the stance that “science itself is but a central<br />

art auxiliary to the generation <strong>and</strong> utilization of other arts” by which he meant that<br />

science is the art of constructing tentative, falsifiable, <strong>and</strong> contingent warranted<br />

linguistic assertions (judgments) that the other arts may use to create their artifacts (LW<br />

10: 33). <strong>Wittgenstein</strong> underst<strong>and</strong>s the task of philosophy as something apart from<br />

science. It is what James C. Klagge (2011) calls “<strong>Wittgenstein</strong>’s insulation thesis” (85). As<br />

Klagge shows, it is largely unsustainable when we examine <strong>Wittgenstein</strong>’s own<br />

statements in a broader context (see chapter 7). However, as Klagge also shows,<br />

<strong>Wittgenstein</strong>’s primary targets are not so much science as reductive, materialistic, <strong>and</strong><br />

mechanistic scientism. <strong>Dewey</strong> too rejected reductive, materialistic, <strong>and</strong> mechanistic<br />

scientism. His alternative was to develop an emergent, organic, naturalism that defied<br />

materialistic reductionism.<br />

Both <strong>Wittgenstein</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>Dewey</strong> seem to agree that philosophy is a form of<br />

criticism. <strong>Dewey</strong> was clear that for him philosophy is cultural criticism. Such wisdom<br />

requires artistic creativity as well as aesthetic appreciation. We may also r ead<br />

<strong>Wittgenstein</strong> as a cultural critic, although most of his interpreters confine his<br />

contribution to epistemological or, at best, logico-grammatical clarification. In footnote<br />

twenty, I suggest a reading of <strong>Wittgenstein</strong> that depends on the primacy of practice that<br />

if correct would bring him much closer to <strong>Dewey</strong>an pragmatism by dissolving the<br />

logical form versus empirical content dualism.<br />

3 For the classical pragmatists, habits are embodied universals in that they are<br />

generalized responses to a class of stimuli. A large part of becoming a rational being<br />

involves making our habits conscious, correcting them, <strong>and</strong> rendering them under our<br />

control. If we can make them conscious, we can perhaps even state them linguistically.<br />

When we cannot, they comprise the basis of tacit knowledge of the kind needed for<br />

good laboratory work, mathematical proofs, <strong>and</strong> music composition.<br />

4 The poem is Ludwig Uhl<strong>and</strong>’s “Count Eberhard’s Hawthorn.” Emphasis in original.<br />

5 Ultimately, such matters as these involve exploring <strong>Wittgenstein</strong>’s remarks on private<br />

language to a greater depth than we will delve into here. It also involves his many<br />

reflections on underst<strong>and</strong>ing others <strong>and</strong> our selves (e.g., pain language), which we will<br />

also largely ignore. <strong>Dewey</strong> too has much to say about these topics.<br />

6 <strong>Dewey</strong> directs our attention to the role of intelligent “intuition” of the kind that only<br />

comes from having an appreciative “feel” for the subject matter with which we are<br />

practically trans-acting:<br />

The expert in thought is one who has skill in making experiments to introduce an<br />

old meaning into different situations <strong>and</strong> who has a sensitive ear for detecting<br />

25


esultant harmonies <strong>and</strong> discords. The most "deductive" thought in actual<br />

occurrence is a series of trials, observations <strong>and</strong> selections. In one sense of the<br />

ambiguous word intuition, it is a "series of intuitions," <strong>and</strong> logic is ex post facto,<br />

expressing a wit that formulates economically the congruities <strong>and</strong> incongruities<br />

that have manifested themselves. Any "syllogism " which is such ab initio is<br />

performed better by a machine that manipulates symbols automatically than by<br />

any "thinker." (LW 1: 153)<br />

The expert in thought is a connoisseur not just a calculator. For something very similar<br />

from a Heideggerian perspective, see Hubert Dreyfus (1992).<br />

7 I agree with Rorty (1961) when he declares: "The closer one brings pragmatism to the<br />

writing of the later <strong>Wittgenstein</strong> <strong>and</strong> of those influenced by him, the more light they<br />

shed on each other” (198-199)<br />

8 We will not explore it here, but the arguments of <strong>Dewey</strong> in The Quest for Certainty<br />

greatly resemble those in <strong>Wittgenstein</strong>’s On Certainty.<br />

9 Hilary Putnam (2002) makes very extensive use of <strong>Dewey</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>Wittgenstein</strong> as well,<br />

but we will not take him up in the present <strong>paper</strong>. One exceptionally useful work is Jose<br />

Medina (2004). For a comparison that seriously misreads <strong>Dewey</strong>, see Black (1962).<br />

10 See Mead (1934/ 1967). In his essay, “Conduct <strong>and</strong> Experience,” <strong>Dewey</strong> uses the word<br />

“conduct” to specifically differentiate his position from that of the psychological<br />

behaviorists. The word conduct referred to any intelligent series of trans-actions, not<br />

just linguistic trans-actions.<br />

11 <strong>Wittgenstein</strong> asks of himself, “Are you not really a behaviourist in disguise? Aren’t<br />

you at bottom really saying that everything except human behaviour is a fiction?” (PI §<br />

307). The answer is no, he is not! Consider: “But you will surely admit there is a<br />

difference between pain-behaviour accompanied by pain <strong>and</strong> pain behaviour without<br />

pain” (PI § 304). When he famously insists: “An ‘inner process’ st<strong>and</strong>s in need of<br />

outward criteria,” I take him as merely making the sound point that we cannot<br />

intelligently infer someone else’s psychological state without some evidence either<br />

“imponderable” or “documentary.” <strong>Dewey</strong> would entirely agree (PI § 580). For those<br />

that have them, the inner states themselves are immediate, qualitative experience.<br />

<strong>Dewey</strong> writes: “Immediacy of existence is ineffable. But there is nothing mystical about<br />

such ineffability; it expresses the fact that of direct existence it is futile to say anything to<br />

one's self <strong>and</strong> impossible to say anything to another” (LW 1: 74). We cannot speak of<br />

immediate existence, whether pain or pleasure or anything else, so we must remain<br />

linguistically silent, although we may gesticulate. Of pain, we might join <strong>Wittgenstein</strong><br />

in saying: “It is not something, but not a nothing either! The conclusion was only that a<br />

nothing would serve just as well as something about which nothing could be said ” (PI §<br />

304).<br />

12 Tomasello specifically refers to <strong>Wittgenstein</strong> in his work. This does not imply that<br />

<strong>Wittgenstein</strong> offers us a disguised theory, but that others may use rich depictions of<br />

language games <strong>and</strong> forms of life to construct their own theories.<br />

26


13<br />

Your mirror neurons fire in much the same way as the neurons of someone you watch<br />

gesturing. For instance, try yawning very openly at a social affair <strong>and</strong> notice how many<br />

also yawn (see Provine, 2005).<br />

14<br />

For <strong>Dewey</strong>, “Philosophic discourse partakes both of scientific <strong>and</strong> literary discourse”<br />

(LW 1: 304).<br />

15<br />

Elsewhere, <strong>Wittgenstein</strong> (1978) writes: “If there did not exist an agreement in what we<br />

call 'red', etc. etc., language would stop" (§ 70).<br />

16 We will soon see that <strong>Dewey</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>Wittgenstein</strong> are both arguing against Lockean ideas<br />

as rules determining how to use language.<br />

17 Those wishing to introduce a theory of power into <strong>Wittgenstein</strong> or <strong>Dewey</strong> would do<br />

well to start about here.<br />

18 For a <strong>paper</strong> that connects Charles Saunders Peirce’s philosophy of habits to<br />

<strong>Wittgenstein</strong>, see Crocker (1998). Crocker explicitly calls attention to the fact that<br />

<strong>Wittgenstein</strong> himself read <strong>and</strong> was influenced by William James <strong>and</strong> that Ramsey read<br />

Peirce extensively. What Crocker says in his <strong>paper</strong> easily conveys to Peirce’s former<br />

student, <strong>Dewey</strong>.<br />

19 What I call “the primacy of practice” offers a way out of the form versus content<br />

dualism that many <strong>Wittgenstein</strong>ians commit when they assume conceptual truth<br />

precedes, constitutes, <strong>and</strong> is normative for empirical truth. Determining the actual<br />

logico-grammatical structure (or norms) of any actual form of life is itself an empirical<br />

inquiry of the kind that, for example, linguistic anthropologists might perform. While<br />

such inquiry has its own logico-grammatical structure, auto-ethnography can render<br />

such structures reflectively conscious to the inquirer. What we have is a virtuous<br />

hermeneutic circle. Conceptual truths <strong>and</strong> empirical truths are simply different<br />

moments in a mutually dependent process. It resembles theory <strong>and</strong> value-ladenness in<br />

inquiry. Such an approach is an apt illustration of pragmatist anti-foundationalism.<br />

Among other forms of foundationalism, it eschews all forms of transcendent Platonism<br />

as well as all shapes of Kantian transcendentalism while preserving a place for<br />

transcending the limits of language in the sense of, say, the New Engl<strong>and</strong><br />

transcendentalists.<br />

27

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!