03.09.2013 Views

Contents - Constitutional Court of Georgia

Contents - Constitutional Court of Georgia

Contents - Constitutional Court of Georgia

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

184<br />

Michael J. Glennon<br />

great a price to pay to justify power-sharing in determining the occurrence <strong>of</strong> aggression, and the<br />

interrelationship between security and criminal justice cannot be ignored.<br />

The second interpretation, yielding a framework <strong>of</strong> preemptive Security Council authority, would<br />

meet these difficulties by deeming the Council to have, in effect, “occupied the field” whenever it<br />

determines the existence <strong>of</strong> aggression. The ICC, under this interpretation, would automatically be<br />

required to defer to the decision <strong>of</strong> the Council whenever the Council makes an affirmative determination.<br />

When the Council makes no determination or a negative determination, on the other hand,<br />

the ICC would be free to act.<br />

In the real world, unfortunately, events would not likely follow that chronologically neat script,<br />

which seems to assume that the Security Council would act (or decline to act) first. The ICC, in reality,<br />

could always “get the jump” on the Council, and it would be naïve to assume that the ICC’s<br />

earlier decision could be ignored by a Council that would supposedly consider the matter de novo.<br />

If it did get around to considering the matter, the Council could in fact come to a determination opposite<br />

that earlier made by the ICC—resulting in precisely the conflict that the concurrent power<br />

model was supposed to avoid. An obvious remedy would be to permit the Council to act, but only<br />

within a given period <strong>of</strong> time, after which the ICC would be permitted to take up the question. But<br />

the workability <strong>of</strong> that cure is doubtful (what event would trigger the time period?) and, in any<br />

event, the whole scheme could be put in place only with an amendment to the Charter. It would<br />

hardly lie within the authority <strong>of</strong> the states party to the Rome Statute to restrict the Security Council<br />

to determining the existence <strong>of</strong> aggression only within a given time period.<br />

There is, however, a more serious flaw in the preemptive power argument: the assumption that<br />

inaction by the Security Council constitutes no decision on the underlying issue whether aggression<br />

has occurred. In fact, by remaining silent and declining to act, the Council could decide implicitly<br />

that the given conduct does not constitute aggression, or that whether the given conduct constitutes<br />

aggression is doubtful, or that other considerations counsel against a determination one way<br />

or the other. As Theodor Meron notes,<br />

[t]he Security Council may have legitimate reasons not to proceed through the routes <strong>of</strong> Article<br />

39 and Chapter VII. The Security Council could choose other avenues such as Chapter VI, which<br />

concerns the pacific settlement <strong>of</strong> disputes. Failure to act in a particular case need not be a pro<strong>of</strong><br />

<strong>of</strong> failure; it may be evidence <strong>of</strong> statesmanship. 190<br />

This is the most powerful reason for concluding that the third argument, for plenary Security<br />

Council power over aggression, is the most reasonable. The powers to determine or not determine<br />

the existence <strong>of</strong> aggression are opposite sides <strong>of</strong> the same coin; the authority to do one necessarily<br />

implies the other. Thus, as Meron has observed, “[t]he [Security] Council’s prerogative to determine<br />

the existence <strong>of</strong> an act <strong>of</strong> aggression under Article 39 . . . is exclusive.” 191 The Charter’s travaux<br />

190 Theodor Meron, Defining Aggression for the International Criminal <strong>Court</strong>, 25 SUFFOLK TRANSNAT’L L. REV. l, l3 (200l).<br />

191 Id. at l4; see also Schuster, supra note l0, at 39 (“[T]he current legal situation prescribes the absolute primacy <strong>of</strong> the Security Council<br />

when it comes to the question <strong>of</strong> aggression.”).

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!