12.07.2015 Views

Why do humans reason? Arguments for an argumentative theory

Why do humans reason? Arguments for an argumentative theory

Why do humans reason? Arguments for an argumentative theory

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

Commentary/Mercier & Sperber: <strong>Why</strong> <strong>do</strong> <strong>hum<strong>an</strong>s</strong> <strong>reason</strong>?Another example of valid <strong>reason</strong>ing failing to persuade comesfrom studies of dyadic learning in children. A common finding inthis literature (e.g., Ames & Murray 1982) is that when conservers<strong>an</strong>d nonconservers share their <strong>reason</strong>s <strong>for</strong> conservation problems,the <strong>for</strong>mer persuade the latter. But is this a case of <strong>reason</strong>triumph<strong>an</strong>t – or of less-confident students yielding to theirmore-confident peers? Suggesting this might be a victory <strong>for</strong> confidenceover <strong>reason</strong>, Levin <strong>an</strong>d Druy<strong>an</strong> (1993) found that confidencewas much higher among conservers th<strong>an</strong> nonconservers.Further, when problems were switched to science problemswith high rates of misconceptions, the competence/confidencecorrelation was flipped – <strong>an</strong>d children found the confidentincompetents more persuasive th<strong>an</strong> their better-<strong>reason</strong>ingpeers. (From this perspective, it’s easy to see why <strong>do</strong>gmatic creationistsw<strong>an</strong>t scientists to “teach the controversy.”)Could it be (as argued by M&S) that <strong>reason</strong>ing evolved tohelp people detect untrustworthy sources by flagging inconsistencyin their arguments? Developmental evidence suggeststhat this is unlikely because children detect trustworthinesslong be<strong>for</strong>e they detect argument inconsistency. For example,when Morris <strong>an</strong>d Hasson (2010) presented children with simulatedarguments of the simplest logical <strong>for</strong>m (e.g., Puppet 1claims “There is a sticker in the box!” <strong>an</strong>d Puppet 2 claims“There is no sticker in the box!”), nearly 100% of 4- <strong>an</strong>d 5-year-olds failed to detect <strong>an</strong> inconsistency between the twoclaims (Morris & Hasson 2010). At the same time, ability todetect a source as trustworthy emerges by 3 or 4 years of age(e.g., Jaswal & Neely 2006; Koenig et al. 2004). Given this, itc<strong>an</strong>not be that detecting trustworthiness requires the ability todetect argument inconsistency.Second, <strong>reason</strong>ed argumentation is expensive <strong>an</strong>d maycompete <strong>for</strong> limited cognitive resources with less expensive“hot” cognition. Recognizing <strong>an</strong>d generating valid arguments(that are not already believable) requires subst<strong>an</strong>tial cognitiveresources, including a heavy cost to working memory (Barrouilletet al. 2000). This cost increases dramatically with <strong>an</strong> increasein the number of premises <strong>an</strong>d introduction of qu<strong>an</strong>tifiers. Atthe same time, if the goal is persuasion, “hot” cognition (e.g.,appeals to emotionally laden examples) c<strong>an</strong> offer a less expensivealternative (Petty & Cacioppo 1996). Given that the cost ofgenerating <strong>an</strong>d comprehending logical arguments outweighsthose of “hot” cognition, without offering subst<strong>an</strong>tial benefits,a mut<strong>an</strong>t with <strong>an</strong> elevated ability <strong>for</strong> logical argument wouldhave no competitive adv<strong>an</strong>tage against her demagogic disput<strong>an</strong>ts.Thus, it is difficult to see how the <strong>argumentative</strong> contextwould provide the ideal environment <strong>for</strong> the evolution oflogical argument.Third, operator/receiver parity precludes benefits of sociallearning or knowledge tr<strong>an</strong>sfer. Although it is often tempting todraw <strong>an</strong>alogies between l<strong>an</strong>guage <strong>an</strong>d <strong>reason</strong>ing (e.g., Braine &O’Brien 1998), the difference between the two is profound.Unlike <strong>reason</strong>ing, l<strong>an</strong>guage proficiency is (more or less) universalin hum<strong>an</strong> adults. Consequently, in linguistic communication,more proficient l<strong>an</strong>guage users (operators) c<strong>an</strong> pull less proficientl<strong>an</strong>guage learners (receivers) along the path to greater proficiency.This is not the case with <strong>reason</strong>ed argumentation,however. Here, operator <strong>an</strong>d receiver characteristics are moresymmetrical: When a person who is receptive to invalid argumentsis put in the role of the operator, invalid argumentsfollow, <strong>an</strong>d when a person who produces invalid arguments isput in the role of the receiver, valid <strong>an</strong>d invalid arguments arenot discriminated. Consequently, communicating <strong>reason</strong>sacross individuals c<strong>an</strong>not, by itself, add <strong>an</strong>ything to argumentation.Indeed, one of the most striking findings in cognitive developmentconcerns how greatly ch<strong>an</strong>ge in l<strong>an</strong>guage proficiencyoutpaces that of logical thinking, as well as how little <strong>reason</strong>edargumentation is affected by observing a more proficient <strong>reason</strong>er(as observed by Levin & Druy<strong>an</strong> 1993).The failures of everyday <strong>reason</strong>ing that we think would makethe <strong>argumentative</strong> context <strong>an</strong> inhospitable environment <strong>for</strong> theevolution of <strong>reason</strong>ing are seen in a str<strong>an</strong>ge light by M&S.According to them, these failures support their accountbecause they arise mostly outside <strong>an</strong> <strong>argumentative</strong> context.Yet, even if we were to stipulate this as true, superior <strong>reason</strong>ingin <strong>an</strong> <strong>argumentative</strong> context <strong>do</strong>es not support their claim aboutthe evolution of <strong>reason</strong>ing: It would imply that arguments facilitate<strong>reason</strong>ing, not that <strong>reason</strong>ing facilitates arguments. Yet, if<strong>reason</strong>ing is designed <strong>for</strong> arguments, as M&S contend, qualityof <strong>reason</strong>ing must facilitate or hinder quality of arguments,whereas the reverse is unnecessary. To take M&S’s <strong>an</strong>alogy, toshow that the structure of the foot is designed <strong>for</strong> walking, onemust show that a different structure would facilitate or impedewalking – not that process of walking strengthens the foot ofthe walker.In our view, the kind of argument that is optimally designed <strong>for</strong>social communication – that is, would have the largest effect onm<strong>an</strong>ipulating <strong>an</strong>other’s behavior – is not necessarily a <strong>reason</strong>edargument but <strong>an</strong> argument that is believable, emotive, easy togenerate on the fly, <strong>an</strong>d clear to others. Put simply, <strong>reason</strong>edargumentation is no more likely to have evolved <strong>for</strong> social communicationth<strong>an</strong> is the posture of the foot to have evolved <strong>for</strong>disco.What is argument <strong>for</strong>? An adaptationistapproach to argument <strong>an</strong>d debate<strong>do</strong>i:10.1017/S0140525X1000302XDavid PietraszewskiDepartment of Psychology, Yale University, New Haven, CT 06520-8205.david.pietraszewski@yale.eduAbstract: A consideration of selection pressures on the psychology ofargument suggests that fixing the truth value of claims is not theprimary criterion <strong>for</strong> argument generation or evaluation. Instead,argument psychology is designed to ch<strong>an</strong>ge representations in otherminds as a way to negotiate conflicts of interest <strong>an</strong>d as a way to signalsocial coordination.Mercier <strong>an</strong>d Sperber’s (M&S’s) <strong>an</strong>alysis of <strong>reason</strong>ing as designed<strong>for</strong> argumentation represents <strong>an</strong>other blow to certain long-heldassumptions about cognitive processes: That <strong>reason</strong>ing is theabstract application of a propositional calculus used to determinewhat is true. Instead, M&S suggest that <strong>reason</strong>ing is the output ofargumentation psychology, a suite of cognitive systems designedto h<strong>an</strong>dle incommensurate representations between people. Thisis courageous <strong>an</strong>d provocative because it suggests that enterprisessuch as science are h<strong>an</strong>dled by a psychology designed<strong>for</strong> argumentation. Insofar as <strong>reason</strong>ing c<strong>an</strong> be defined as <strong>an</strong>interestingly coherent natural category, M&S are likely correct.However, the argument c<strong>an</strong> be taken further. If <strong>reason</strong>ing is<strong>for</strong> argument, what is argument <strong>for</strong>? While M&S allude to this,there is some value in explicitly addressing the function of argumentbecause it directly speaks to how argumentation psychologyshould work.Consider the case of the evaluation of factual or policy claims.It is tempting to think that argument’s proper <strong>do</strong>main in suchcases is to determine the truth or accuracy of incommensuraterepresentations – a natural consequence of in<strong>for</strong>mation beingdistributed nonuni<strong>for</strong>mly across bodies – that some peoplehave access to in<strong>for</strong>mation that others <strong>do</strong> not, <strong>an</strong>d that, givenimperfect in<strong>for</strong>mation, each person is expected to prefer one’sown data <strong>an</strong>d conclusions <strong>an</strong>d be wary of others. On this view,even if <strong>reason</strong>ing is <strong>for</strong> argument, then the ultimate logic of argumentis the same as the classical view of <strong>reason</strong>ing – as a way ofdetermining truth – albeit in a way that diverges from a rationalview, by virtue of the division of in<strong>for</strong>mation access in the realworld.86 BEHAVIORAL AND BRAIN SCIENCES (2011) 34:2

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!