12.07.2015 Views

Why do humans reason? Arguments for an argumentative theory

Why do humans reason? Arguments for an argumentative theory

Why do humans reason? Arguments for an argumentative theory

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

Commentary/Mercier & Sperber: <strong>Why</strong> <strong>do</strong> <strong>hum<strong>an</strong>s</strong> <strong>reason</strong>?Table 1 (Poletiek). Utilities of <strong>reason</strong>ing outcomes about H (the<strong>reason</strong>er’s subjective belief), assuming <strong>an</strong> epistemic motive (A), <strong>an</strong><strong>argumentative</strong> motive (B), <strong>an</strong>d both types of motives (C).their expectation of the outcome that ch<strong>an</strong>ged when they tested ahypothesis they did not believe to be true (falsification wasexpected). When testing their best guess, they expected a confirmingoutcome.Besides determining the truth, m<strong>an</strong>y considerations may affecthow we <strong>reason</strong> <strong>an</strong>d whether we <strong>reason</strong>. These considerations c<strong>an</strong>be modeled as a cost-benefit <strong>an</strong>alysis of making the right inference.In Wason’s (1960) task, students participating in the experimentmight not care much about making <strong>reason</strong>ing errors. Thekey seeker might per<strong>for</strong>m a negative test (looking <strong>for</strong> the keys insome place other th<strong>an</strong> the jacket) because the costs of a positiveone are too high: The jacket was left behind in a friend’s house<strong>an</strong>d the ef<strong>for</strong>t too great to walk back to check the jacket. Alternatively,we might be in a hurry <strong>an</strong>d have time to check just onelocation, enh<strong>an</strong>cing the benefits of good <strong>reason</strong>ing.To predict <strong>reason</strong>ing behavior, we need a model with utilitiesof <strong>reason</strong>ing outcomes. A suitable tool is signal-detection <strong>theory</strong>.Motives c<strong>an</strong> be expressed in the utilities of inference errors <strong>an</strong>din <strong>reason</strong>ing behavior predicted on the basis of the risk we areprepared to take with regard to particular erroneous inferences(Poletiek & Berndsen 2000). For example, as shown in Table 1,a pure epistemic motive would be modeled with (A) low utilitiesof making <strong>an</strong>y false inferences. A pure <strong>argumentative</strong> motivewould be expressed in (B) a very high willingness to make thefalse inference that our favorite hypothesis is true; <strong>an</strong>d (C)<strong>reason</strong>ing with both motives (searching <strong>for</strong> a valid inferencewithin both practical or <strong>argumentative</strong> constraints) is reflectedwith some in-between utilities with regard to making a false ora correct inference about our favorite hypothesis.In this m<strong>an</strong>ner, <strong>reason</strong>ing in a variety of contexts <strong>an</strong>d with avariety of goals c<strong>an</strong> be modeled, offering <strong>an</strong> eleg<strong>an</strong>t alternativeto the para<strong>do</strong>x of the ATR that we start up a <strong>reason</strong>ing trajectoryabout a prior belief if <strong>an</strong>d only if the end of the route leads us toinferring that belief again.When <strong>reason</strong>ing is persuasive but wrong<strong>do</strong>i:10.1017/S0140525X10002761Robert J. SternbergAH is trueInfer H 10 0Infer not-H 0 10Infer H 10 10Infer not-H 0 0Infer H 10 4Infer not-H 0 6BCNot-H is trueProvost <strong>an</strong>d Senior Vice President, Oklahoma State University, Stillwater, OK74078.Robert.sternberg@okstate.eduAbstract: Mercier <strong>an</strong>d Sperber (M&S) are correct that <strong>reason</strong>ing <strong>an</strong>dargumentation are closely related. But they are wrong in arguing thatthis relationship is one of evolutionary adaptation. In fact, persuasive<strong>reason</strong>ing that is not veridical c<strong>an</strong> be fatal to the individual <strong>an</strong>d to thepropagation of his or her genes, as well as to the hum<strong>an</strong> species as awhole.In the target article, Mercier & Sperber (M&S) brilli<strong>an</strong>tly show acrucial relationship between argumentation <strong>an</strong>d <strong>reason</strong>ing. Butthe relationship is not the one they claim to show.Consider two individuals facing <strong>an</strong> adaptive challenge. A threatof some kind is about to confront them. One of the individuals, A,recognizes the threat; the other, B, fails, <strong>for</strong> whatever <strong>reason</strong>, torecognize it. The two individuals argue over the existence of thethreat or, perhaps, its severity. Each argues compellingly <strong>for</strong> hisor her point of view. After all, with inductive <strong>reason</strong>ing base<strong>do</strong>n incomplete <strong>an</strong>d often ambiguous in<strong>for</strong>mation, arguments c<strong>an</strong>have inductive strength but not deductive certainty; <strong>an</strong>d theirinductive strength <strong>do</strong>es not necessarily correspond to their veridicality(as <strong>an</strong>yone will have observed who has seen a defense attorneygets off his guilty client scot free). A <strong>an</strong>d B both act on thebasis of their <strong>reason</strong>ing. A survives <strong>an</strong>d B dies (as a result of abear attack, a lightning strike, <strong>an</strong> automobile accident, a pl<strong>an</strong>ecrash, or whatever the threat in question happened to be).A <strong>an</strong>d B both used their <strong>reason</strong>ing in the service of argumentation,but <strong>reason</strong>ing was adaptive by virtue of the veridicality of itsconclusion, not by virtue of the persuasiveness of the arguments(which may or may not correspond to veridicality in real-worldambiguous situations with incomplete in<strong>for</strong>mation). So <strong>reason</strong>ingcould scarcely have evolved in the service of argumentation,because those wonderful arguers who did not perceive thingsveridically would have been less able to reproduce th<strong>an</strong> thosearguers who did perceive things veridically. The brilli<strong>an</strong>t <strong>reason</strong>erswho argued wrongly regarding threats had m<strong>an</strong>y more opportunitiesto perish be<strong>for</strong>e reproducing th<strong>an</strong> those <strong>reason</strong>ers,persuasive or not, who saw threats as they were.The same phenomenon occurs at a group level. Consider globalwarming. Global warming threatens the existence of hum<strong>an</strong> <strong>an</strong><strong>do</strong>ther life on the pl<strong>an</strong>et Earth, <strong>an</strong>d yet deniers, including scientists,put the life of all hum<strong>an</strong> org<strong>an</strong>isms on the pl<strong>an</strong>et – the replicationof the species’ genes <strong>an</strong>d hence the survival of the species– at risk. Reasoning is being used in the service of argumentation,but not always <strong>for</strong> evolutionarily adaptive purposes, at least withrespect to the genes of the individuals involved.The opening view of M&S that “<strong>reason</strong>ing should produce itsbest results when used in <strong>argumentative</strong> contexts, most notably ingroup discussions” (sect. 1.2, para. 11) is clearly wrong, as are thearguments that follow from it. The problem is that in this quotation,as throughout the article, there is <strong>an</strong> ambiguity regardingthe me<strong>an</strong>ing of “best results.” If <strong>reason</strong>ing is about persuasiveness,perhaps the authors are right. But if <strong>reason</strong>ing is about veridicality,they are wrong.J<strong>an</strong>is (1972) recognized the fallacy of the <strong>reason</strong>ing in his workon groupthink. He observed that groups of academically brilli<strong>an</strong>tgovernment officials could make horrible mistakes that wereactually compounded by their being in groups. More generally,the phenomenon is referred to as “group polarization” (Moscovici& Zavalloni 1969). People like Robert McNamara <strong>an</strong>d,more recently, Donald Rumsfeld, come to mind – people who,despite their academic brilli<strong>an</strong>ce, <strong>reason</strong>ed poorly, yet wereable to persuade m<strong>an</strong>y by their (false) arguments. St<strong>an</strong>ovich(1993; 2009) coined the irrational but often persuasive <strong>reason</strong>ingof IQ-smart people “dysrationalia” (<strong>for</strong> related ideas, see alsoSternberg 2002).In the short run, <strong>reason</strong>ing in the service of argument may wellbe adaptive. For example, a job c<strong>an</strong>didate who is persuasive isperhaps more likely to get the job th<strong>an</strong> one who is unpersuasive;a politici<strong>an</strong> who is persuasive is more likely to be elected or, atleast, to be believed. But as recent presidential <strong>an</strong>d other electionshave shown, persuasiveness (at least to the masses) c<strong>an</strong> beattained even by c<strong>an</strong>didates who c<strong>an</strong>not string together a88 BEHAVIORAL AND BRAIN SCIENCES (2011) 34:2

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!