13.07.2015 Views

Two Models of Thinking - Fordham University Faculty

Two Models of Thinking - Fordham University Faculty

Two Models of Thinking - Fordham University Faculty

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

<strong>Two</strong> <strong>Models</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>Thinking</strong>:Thomas Aquinas and John Duns ScotusGiorgio PiniSuppose I am thinking about what it is to be a cat. What sort <strong>of</strong>activity am I engaging in? What is it to think about something? ThomasAquinas and John Duns Scotus answered this question in two remarkablydifferent ways. Even though Scotus did not develop his theory <strong>of</strong> thinking indirect opposition to Aquinas, a comparison between their treatments will helpus focus on their distinctive strategies to deal with what they called “acts <strong>of</strong>thinking.” 1It will be convenient to break down the question “what is it to thinkabout something?” into the following three questions:(1) What sort <strong>of</strong> thing is an act <strong>of</strong> thinking?(2) What are the necessary and sufficient conditions for an act <strong>of</strong>thinking to occur?(3) What accounts for an act <strong>of</strong> thinking’s being about something?And specifically, what accounts for a certain act <strong>of</strong> thinking’s being about acertain thing as opposed to another, say about what it is to be a cat rather thanwhat it is to be a dog? 2These questions are clearly distinct. The first question concerns theontological status <strong>of</strong> an act <strong>of</strong> thinking. By contrast, the second question bearson the mechanisms <strong>of</strong> cognition. Finally, the third question concerns theintentionality <strong>of</strong> an act <strong>of</strong> thinking. It is a typical trait <strong>of</strong> later medieval theories<strong>of</strong> intellectual cognition to regard these three questions as closely connected.1 By “act <strong>of</strong> thinking,” I translate the following Latin expressions: actus intelligendi,actus cognoscendi, actualis cognitio, intellectio, notitia, notitia actualis, notitia actualis genita inintellectu. Both acts <strong>of</strong> thinking and their contents were being referred to as “concepts”(conceptus). Scotus called attention to this equivocal usage <strong>of</strong> the term “concept” in hisTheoremata, pars 3, def. 1, n. 1, OPh II, 609. Sometimes, the technical notion <strong>of</strong> intelligiblespecies was also referred to as a concept. All these items (i.e. acts <strong>of</strong> thinking, their contents, andintelligible species) are to some extent mental entities and, accordingly, concepts. But they shouldbe carefully distinguished from one another if any sense is to be made <strong>of</strong> later medieval theories<strong>of</strong> intellectual cognition. In order to avoid any confusion, I refrain from using the term “concept”as much as possible. When I do introduce that term (e.g. in order to refer to the product <strong>of</strong> an act<strong>of</strong> thinking in Aquinas’s second account <strong>of</strong> thinking), I will specify what sort <strong>of</strong> entity I take theterm “concept” to refer to.2 On the distinction between the general and the specific problem <strong>of</strong> intentionality, seeJ. E. Brower and S. Brower-Toland, “Aquinas on Mental Representation: Concept andIntentionality,” The Philosophical Review 117 (2008): 193–243, at 194.1


Specifically, the answer given to the first question was supposed to have abearing on the answers given to the other two questions.Interpreters <strong>of</strong> later medieval philosophy have recently devoted muchattention to the second and especially the third question, i.e. to the issue <strong>of</strong>the mechanisms <strong>of</strong> intellectual cognition and thought’s intentionality. Inparticular, much effort has been recently spent to investigate medievaltheories <strong>of</strong> mental representation. 3In comparison, the question regarding the ontological status <strong>of</strong> an act<strong>of</strong> thinking has attracted little attention. In this paper, it is my hope to showthat the contrast between Aquinas’s view that acts <strong>of</strong> thinking are actions andScotus’s alternative view that acts <strong>of</strong> thinking are mental qualities is muchmore than a negligible disagreement concerning an abstruse issue in cognitivepsychology. Rather, this difference should be regarded as a key point toevaluate those two thinkers’ respective accounts <strong>of</strong> thinking. 4I must make four provisos about the scope <strong>of</strong> this paper.First, my focus will be on human thinking. Accordingly, I will not takeinto account the way God and angels engage in thought.Second, my focus will be on simple acts <strong>of</strong> thinking or simplethoughts. It was a common view among later medieval thinkers that mythinking about cats counts as a simple act <strong>of</strong> thinking or “simpleapprehension” (simplex apprehensio). By such an act, I grasp what cats arebut I engage neither in predicating any property <strong>of</strong> cats nor in drawing any3 See R. Pasnau, Theories <strong>of</strong> Cognition in the Later Middle Ages (Cambridge: Cambridge<strong>University</strong> Press, 1997), 31–124; D. Perler, Theorien der Intentionalität im Mittelalter (Frankfurtam Main: Kostermann, 2002); D. Perler, Théories de l’intentionnalité au moyen âge (Paris: Vrin,2003); J. P. O’Callaghan, Thomist Realism and the Linguistic Turn. Toward a More Perfect Form <strong>of</strong>Existence (Notre Dame: <strong>University</strong> <strong>of</strong> Notre Dame Press, 2003); P. King, “RethinkingRepresentation in the Middle Ages: A Vade-Mecum to Medieval Theories <strong>of</strong> MentalRepresentation,” in Representation and Objects <strong>of</strong> Thoughts in Medieval Philosophy, ed. H.Lagerlund (Aldershot: Ashgate, 2007), 81–100; Brower and Brower-Toland, “Aquinas on MentalContent.”4 It is not my claim that Thomas Aquinas and Duns Scotus were the only supporters <strong>of</strong>their respective views. Because <strong>of</strong> the sophisticated treatments they devoted to this issue,however, they may be regarded as their two main proponents. Several thinkers seem to haveadopted the view that acts <strong>of</strong> thinking are actions, even though they rejected some or even most<strong>of</strong> the other aspects <strong>of</strong> Aquinas’s account <strong>of</strong> intellectual cognition (e.g. James <strong>of</strong> Viterbo, Peter <strong>of</strong>John Olivi, Thomas Wylton, and William <strong>of</strong> Ware). After Scotus, William Ockham was among thesupporters <strong>of</strong> the view that acts <strong>of</strong> thinking are mental qualities. See William Ockham,Quaestiones in tertium librum Sententiarum. Reportiatio, q. 7, OTh VI, 197–199; Panaccio,Ockham on Concepts, 21–23. By contrast, the Carmelite friar, Guido Terreni, who was familiarwith both Wylton’s version <strong>of</strong> the view that acts <strong>of</strong> thinking are actions and Scotus’s view that acts<strong>of</strong> thinking are qualities, adopted a mixed position, according to which an act <strong>of</strong> thinking hassome features <strong>of</strong> an action, some features <strong>of</strong> a passion, and some features <strong>of</strong> a quality. I wish tothank Cecilia Trifogli for letting me have a copy <strong>of</strong> the forthcoming paper, L. O. Nielsen and T.Trifogli, “Guido Terreni and His Debate with Thomas Wylton,” Documenti e studi sulla tradizionefilos<strong>of</strong>ica medievale 20 (2009).2


conclusion about cats. Accordingly, simple acts <strong>of</strong> thinking should becontrasted both to acts <strong>of</strong> “composition and division” (compositio et divisio),i.e. propositional acts such as the act <strong>of</strong> thinking that cats are graceful or thatthey do not fly, and to acts <strong>of</strong> reasoning (ratiocinatio, argumentatio), such asthe act <strong>of</strong> thinking that, since cats are animals and animals need to eat, catsneed to eat. 5 Since it was commonly assumed that I can engage in predicatingand reasoning only if I have some grasp <strong>of</strong> the thing <strong>of</strong> which I am predicatingsome property or about which I am drawing some conclusion, an account <strong>of</strong>simple acts <strong>of</strong> thinking was regarded as a prerequisite to any attempt <strong>of</strong>explaining predication and reasoning.Third, my focus will be on what were called “abstractive” as opposedto “intuitive” acts <strong>of</strong> thinking. Thus, I will be dealing with acts <strong>of</strong> thinking suchas my thinking about what it is to be a cat, i.e. about the necessary andsufficient conditions that something must satisfy in order to count as a cat,independently <strong>of</strong> whether anything satisfies such conditions. I will not bedealing with acts <strong>of</strong> thinking to which it makes a difference whether theirobjects actually exist or not, such as my act <strong>of</strong> thinking about my currentdesire for a glass <strong>of</strong> milk. Whether I have or do not have a desire for a class <strong>of</strong>milk makes a difference with regard to the identity <strong>of</strong> my act <strong>of</strong> thinking aboutthat desire as my current desire. By contrast, an act <strong>of</strong> thinking about theessential features <strong>of</strong> cats would be the same even if cats were extinct. 6Fourth, my focus will be on general acts <strong>of</strong> thinking, such as thoughtsabout what it is to be a cat, as opposed to singular thoughts, such as thoughtsabout this or that individual cat. 7This paper is divided into three main parts. First, I present the mainelements <strong>of</strong> Aristotle’s account <strong>of</strong> what it is to think. Second, I turn toAquinas’s interpretation <strong>of</strong> Aristotle’s account. Third and finally, I considerScotus’s account <strong>of</strong> what it is to think.5 See for example Aquinas In Peryerm., I, 1, 1,5; In An. Post. I, 1, 2, 4–5; In IV Meta.,lect. 4, n. 574; In IV Meta., lect. 17, n. 736. See R. W. Schmidt, The Domain <strong>of</strong> Logic according toSaint Thomas Aquinas (The Hague: Nijh<strong>of</strong>f, 1966), 53–57; R. Pasnau, Thomas Aquinas on HumanNature. A Philosophical Study <strong>of</strong> Summa theologiae Ia 75–89 (Cambridge: Cambridge <strong>University</strong>Press, 2002), 273; E. Stump, Aquinas (London and New York: Routledge, 2003), 265–266.Aristotle had distinguished two acts <strong>of</strong> the intellect in De anima III, 6, 430a26–b6.6 On the distinction between abstractive and intuitive cognition in Scotus, see S. J. Day,Intuitive Cognition. A Key to the Significance <strong>of</strong> the Later Scholastics (St. Bonaventure, NY:Franciscan Institute Publications, 1947), 39–139; K. H. Tachau, Vision and Certitude in the Age <strong>of</strong>Ockham. Optics, Epistemology and the Foundations <strong>of</strong> Semantics 1250–1345 (Leiden/NewYork/København/Köln: Brill, 1988), 68–75; S. D. Dumont, “The Scientific Character <strong>of</strong> Theologyand the Origin <strong>of</strong> Duns Scotus’ Distinction between Intuitive and Abstractive Cognition,”Speculum 64 (1989): 579–599; R. Pasnau, “Cognition,” in The Cambridge Companion to DunsScotus, ed. T. Williams (Cambridge; Cambridge <strong>University</strong> Press, 2003), 296–300.7 On singular thoughts in Scotus, see Peter King’s paper in this volume.3


1. Aristotle’s hylomorphic account <strong>of</strong> thinkingSince Aquinas’s account <strong>of</strong> thinking is a development <strong>of</strong> Aristotle’sviews on the same topic, it is necessary to start with a general outline <strong>of</strong>Aristotle’s treatment <strong>of</strong> what it is to think about something.Aristotle explained both perception and thought by applying to themhis hylomorphic analysis <strong>of</strong> change. According to Aristotle, in any change it ispossible to identify a subject or patient, which plays the role <strong>of</strong> matter, andtwo contrary states, i.e. the initial state, which is characterized by the absence<strong>of</strong> a certain form F, and the end-state, which is characterized by the presence<strong>of</strong> F. Something changes when it receives a certain form F from a certainagent. By receiving that form, the thing that is changed (i.e. the patient)actualizes a certain power or capacity (i.e. a “passive power”) that it had evenbefore being changed. For example, water becomes hot when it receives theform heat from fire. When water becomes hot, water’s power to be hot isactualized. The same process can also be described from the point <strong>of</strong> view <strong>of</strong>the agent. Fire’s heating water is the very same process as water’s becominghot. By heating the water, fire actualizes a certain power or capacity (i.e. an“active power”) that it had even before actually heating.The main point <strong>of</strong> Aristotle’s analysis <strong>of</strong> change is that change is aprocess <strong>of</strong> form giving (from the agent’s point <strong>of</strong> view) or form reception (fromthe patient’s point <strong>of</strong> view), where the form given and received actualizes boththe agent’s active power to give a form and the patient’s passive power toreceive a form. 8In the third book <strong>of</strong> his De anima, Aristotle applied this account <strong>of</strong>change to both perception and thought. He accordingly interpreted perceptionand thought as changes or processes in which a certain form is given by anagent and received in a patient. When I perceive hot, I receive the form heat.Similarly, when I think about cats, I receive the form felinity. Morespecifically, the form felinity is received in my intellect (the patient) from theobject, i.e. cats (the agent), through the intermediary <strong>of</strong> the senses andimagination. Just as in any other sort <strong>of</strong> change, when I perceive and think I8 Phys. III, 3; Gen. et Corr. I, 7. See U. Coope, “Aristotle’s Account <strong>of</strong> Agency inPhysics III 3,” Proceedings <strong>of</strong> the Boston Area Colloquium in Ancient Philosophy 20 (2004): 201–221; ead., “Aristotle on Action,” Proceedings <strong>of</strong> the Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 81(2007): 109–137.4


am informed by an agent, i.e. I receive the form <strong>of</strong> the agent in my senses andintellect, respectively. 9Even though both perception and thought are changes, Aristotleacknowledged that they are very special kinds <strong>of</strong> changes. The key differencebetween perception and thought, on the one hand, and ordinary kinds <strong>of</strong>changes such as heating, on the other hand, is that a kettle becomes hot whenit is heated, but I do not become what I perceive or what I think about when Iperceive or think about something. Aristotle accounted for this peculiarfeature <strong>of</strong> perception and thought by saying that, in both perception andthought, the form <strong>of</strong> the thing cognized is received in the cognizer without thematter. 10 This is usually taken to mean that the form <strong>of</strong> the thing cognized isreceived in the cognizer without a corresponding change in the cognizer’smatter. For example, when I see a red fox, my senses receive the form redness,but my matter does not become disposed to the form redness the way the fox’smatter is disposed towards it. Accordingly, the fox is red, but I do not becomered when I see a red fox. Similarly, when I think about cats, my intellectreceives the form felinity, but my matter does not become disposed towardsthe form felinity the way the matter <strong>of</strong> cats is.A last point should be considered in Aristotle’s account <strong>of</strong> perceptionand thought as changes. In both perception and thought, just as in any otherkind <strong>of</strong> change, the agent’s form is one and the same form as the patient’sform. When fire heats a kettle, the same form heat is both in the fire and in thekettle. Similarly, when I see red, the same form redness is both in the redobject and in my eye. And when I actually think about cats, the same formfelinity is both in cats and in my intellect. In the words <strong>of</strong> a contemporaryscholar, “forms are present in the world in two irreducible different ways, one<strong>of</strong> which is cognitive <strong>of</strong> the other.” 11Some problems arise, however, when one considers in what sense <strong>of</strong>“the same” the form in the thing cognized is the same as the form in thecognizer. For this claim can be interpreted in two different ways. First, the9 De anima II, 5, 416b33–34 and 418a3–6; II, 12, 424a17–24; III, 4, 429a13–18 and429b29–430a2. See M. F. Burnyeat, “Aquinas on ‘Spiritual Change’ in Perception,” in Ancientand Medieval Theories <strong>of</strong> Intentionality, ed. D. Perler (Leiden/Boston/Köln: Brill, 2001), 139–142;C. Shields, “Intentionality and Isomorphism in Aristotle,” Proceeding <strong>of</strong> the Boston AreaColloquium in Ancient Philosophy 11 (1995): 308–310; id., Aristotle (London/New York:Routledge, 2007), 293–305; id., “The Peculiar Motion <strong>of</strong> Aristotelian Souls,” Proceedings <strong>of</strong> theAristotelian Society. Supplementary Volume 81 (2007): 140, 145–150.10 De anima II, 5; II, 12, 424a17–24. There is some debate concerning the correctinterpretation <strong>of</strong> this passage and related ones. See R. Sorabji, “Intentionality and PhysiologicalProcesses: Aristotle’s Theory <strong>of</strong> Sense-Perception,” in Essays on Aristotle’s De Anima, eds. M. C.Nussbaum and A. O. Rorty (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1992), 217–218; Burnyeat, “Aquinas on‘Spiritual Change’,” 139–140. I follow Burnyeat’s interpretation.11 Burnyeat, “Aquinas on ‘Spiritual Change’,” 141.5


form <strong>of</strong> the thing I am thinking about and the form in my intellect may beregarded as the same individual item, i.e. numerically one and the same form.Second, the form <strong>of</strong> the thing I am thinking about and the form in my intellectmay be regarded as two discrete individuals, which are the same in someimportant respects but are not numerically the same item. The way these twonumerically distinct individuals are one and the same is variously described as“formal” or “structural sameness.” 12 Both interpretations have had theirsupporters among Aristotle’s interpreters. The former interpretation wasfavored in antiquity by Porphyry, according to Avicenna’s testimony, and hasreceived support by several contemporary scholars. 13 The latter interpretationwas explicitly endorsed by Avicenna in opposition to Porphyry and has alsoreceived support in recent years. 14 It was the latter interpretation that wascommonly adopted in the later Middle Ages. Ever since Aristotle’s De animawas translated into Latin and became the object <strong>of</strong> study (roughly between thetwelfth and the thirteenth century), medieval thinkers agreed on readingAristotle as positing two numerically distinct items, one in the thing I amthinking about and the other one in my intellect. In the thirteenth century, theform existing in my intellect was commonly called “intelligible species” inorder to distinguish it from the form existing in the thing I am thinking about. 15In light <strong>of</strong> this short outline <strong>of</strong> Aristotle’s position, his answers to thethree questions concerning what it is to think about something can bereconstructed as follows. First, an act <strong>of</strong> thinking is an instance <strong>of</strong> change.More precisely, an act <strong>of</strong> thinking is a passion, i.e. the reception <strong>of</strong> a certainform in a subject, i.e. in the intellect, from a certain agent, i.e. from theobject. 16 Second, an act <strong>of</strong> thinking occurs when the causal process <strong>of</strong> formimpression and reception started at the level <strong>of</strong> the senses ends up in the12 For the distinction between these two readings, which Christopher Shields calls“stronger” and “weaker hypothesis,” see Shields, “Intentionality and Isomorphism,” 324–327.13 Avicenna, Liber de anima, pars V, c. 6, 136. Among contemporary interpreters whosympathize with this view, see L. A. Kosman, “Perceiving that We Perceive: On the Soul III, 2,”The Philosophical Review 84 (1975): 499–519; J. Owens, “Aristotle: Cognition a Way <strong>of</strong> Being,”Canadian Journal <strong>of</strong> Philosophy 6 (1976): 1–11, reprinted in id., Aristotle: The Collected Papers <strong>of</strong>Joseph Owens, ed. J. R. Catan (Albany: SUNY Press, 1981), 74–80; C. Kahn, “Aristotle on<strong>Thinking</strong>,” in Essays on Aristotle’s De anima, ed. Nussbaum and Rorty, 372–375. See also J.Owens, Cognition: An Epistemological Enquiry (Houston, TX: Center for Thomistic Studies, 1992),114.14 Avicenna, Liber de anima, pars V, c. 6, 134–135. See D. L. Black, “Conjunction andthe Identity <strong>of</strong> Knower and Known in Averroes,” American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly 73(1999), 162–163; M. Sebti, Avicenne. L’âme humaine (Paris: Presses universitaires de France,2000), 97–99. Among contemporary interpreters who sympathize with this view, see Shields,“Intentionality and Isomorphism,” 324–330.15 On the history <strong>of</strong> the notion <strong>of</strong> intelligible species, see L. Spruit, Species Intelligibilis.From Perception to Knowledge (Leiden/New York/Köln: Brill, 1994); G. Pini, “Il dibattito sullespecie intelligibili nel tredicesimo secolo,” Medioevo 29 (2004): 267–306.16 Aristotle, De anima III, 4, 429a13–15; b22–25.6


intellect. Third, an act <strong>of</strong> thinking is about something, and more specifically acertain act <strong>of</strong> thinking is about a certain thing, because the form received inthe intellect is the form <strong>of</strong> a certain thing, say the form <strong>of</strong> cats rather than <strong>of</strong>dogs (as I have mentioned, it is controversial whether the identity between theform in the intellect and the form <strong>of</strong> the object is numerical or specific).The strong point <strong>of</strong> Aristotle’s view that thinking is a passion is that itexplains the occurrence <strong>of</strong> thinking within the framework <strong>of</strong> naturalphilosophy. No special sort <strong>of</strong> entities are presupposed and no special sort <strong>of</strong>change is postulated. The same hylomorphic framework that explains changein general can be applied to thinking (as well as to perception). This approachhas the great advantage <strong>of</strong> dissolving the mystery concerning intentionality. Acertain thought is about a certain thing because it is the reception <strong>of</strong> the form<strong>of</strong> that thing, just as water is heated rather than cooled because it is the formheat rather than the form cold that is received in water.Aristotle’s account <strong>of</strong> thinking, however, faces some problems. I willmention two that are potentially fatal to the ultimate success <strong>of</strong> Aristotle’shylomorphic model in explaining thinking.First, the claim that to think is a kind <strong>of</strong> passion clashes with the basicintuition that to think is something I do rather than something that is done tome. In this respect, thought seems to be different from perception. It is not upto me to feel cold or hot, but it is up to me to think about something or notand to think about a certain thing rather than another, say about cats ratherthan dogs. I will call this the “activity problem.”Second, the view that to think about something is to undergo achange and more specifically to receive a form from the object provides agood account <strong>of</strong> learning, i.e. the passage from ignorance to dispositionalknowledge. When I am ignorant <strong>of</strong> what cats are, I have the power to acquirethe form felinity and to keep it stored in my memory. Just as in any otherchange, a certain state (i.e. ignorance, which is the privation <strong>of</strong> a certain form)is displaced by another state (i.e. dispositional knowledge, which is thepresence <strong>of</strong> a certain form). Problems arise, however, when one tries toaccount for the passage from dispositional to occurrent knowledge, i.e. to theactual occurrence <strong>of</strong> a thought. When I already know what cats are and Iactually think about cats, my occurrent and episodic thought about what catsare does not displace any previous state. I still retain the form felinity I haveacquired. Similarly, when I exercise my mathematical abilities, mydispositional knowledge <strong>of</strong> mathematics is not displaced by my occurrentknowledge. In Aristotelian terms, the hylomorphic explanation <strong>of</strong> thinking asform reception works well to account for the passage from a state <strong>of</strong> firstpotentiality to a state <strong>of</strong> second potentiality (or first actuality) with respect to7


knowledge. This explanation is not equally satisfactory when used to accountfor the passage from second potentiality (or first actuality) to a state <strong>of</strong> secondactuality with respect to knowledge. Thus, the hylomorphic model shows itslimits when applied to the crucial case <strong>of</strong> the occurrence <strong>of</strong> episodicthoughts. 17 I will call this “the problem <strong>of</strong> occurrent thoughts.”Aristotle left these two problems as a legacy to his medievalinterpreters. Aquinas’s and Scotus’s accounts <strong>of</strong> thinking can be regarded asalternative strategies to solve them.2. Aquinas’s model <strong>of</strong> thinking: thinking as actingBy and large, Aquinas adopted Aristotle’s account <strong>of</strong> thinking.Specifically, he embraced Aristotle’s insight that to think is a kind <strong>of</strong> changeand can accordingly be explained as the presence <strong>of</strong> a form in a patient.Something is heated when it receives the form heat. Similarly, I think aboutwhat it is to be a cat when the form felinity is received in my intellect. In thisrespect, sensory and intellectual acts <strong>of</strong> cognition are similar. Just as the formheat is the formal principle <strong>of</strong> heating in fire, i.e. what makes fire actuallyheat, in the same way a certain sensible form is the formal principle <strong>of</strong>sensation, i.e. what makes the sense actually sense the thing whose sensibleform it is. 18 Similarly, a certain form received in the intellect is what makes theintellect actually think about the thing whose form it is.Within this general framework, Aquinas had to face five questions.First, what is the relationship between the form in my intellect and the form <strong>of</strong>the thing I am thinking about, e.g. between the form felinity in my intellectand the form felinity as instantiated in extramental cats? Second, what sort <strong>of</strong>change is an act <strong>of</strong> thinking, a passion or an action? In other words, when Ithink about what it is to be a cat, does my intellect undergo a change or doesit cause a change? Third, if it is granted that an act <strong>of</strong> thinking is an action,what sort <strong>of</strong> action is it? Fourth, is the presence <strong>of</strong> a certain form in myintellect both necessary and sufficient for an act <strong>of</strong> thinking to occur? Fifth andfinally, what accounts for an act <strong>of</strong> thinking’s intentionality, i.e. for its beingabout what it is about?I will address each <strong>of</strong> these questions in turn.17 Aristotle faces this problem in De anima II, 5, 417b1–16. See Shields, “The PeculiarMotion,” 155–159; id., Aristotle, 299–300.18 ST I, q. 56, a. 2: “Et ita se habet obiectum unitum potentiae ad huiusmodi actionem,sicut forma quae est principium actionis in aliis agentibus: sicut enim calor est principium formalecalefactionis in igne, ita species rei visae est principium formale visionis in oculo.”8


2.1. The form in the intellect: the intelligible species as likenessWhat is the relationship between the form felinity present in myintellect when I think about what it is to be a cat and the form felinity as it isinstantiated in extramental cats?Aquinas followed Avicenna in rejecting the view that the form presentin my intellect is numerically the same as the form that plays the role <strong>of</strong> theorganizing principle <strong>of</strong> the thing I am thinking about. Rather, the form in myintellect and the form <strong>of</strong> the thing I am thinking about are two numericallydiscrete items. Following the standard usage <strong>of</strong> his time, Aquinas called theform in the intellect an “intelligible species.” He claimed that the relationshipholding between the intelligible species and the thing thought about is notnumerical identity but likeness (similitudo). Specifically, the intelligiblespecies is a likeness <strong>of</strong> the thing thought about. Thus, to cognize something isto have a likeness <strong>of</strong> that thing in the intellect, not to have that very thing inthe intellect:[…] That which is understood is within that which understandsthrough its likeness. And the saying that “what is actually understood is theactualized intellect” holds in this way: ins<strong>of</strong>ar as a likeness <strong>of</strong> the thingunderstood is the intellect’s form. (Similarly, a likeness <strong>of</strong> a sensible thing isthe form <strong>of</strong> the actualized sense.)19So far, Aquinas’s position is clear. There is considerable disagreement,however, concerning the way the claim that the intelligible species is alikeness should be understood. Some interpreters hold that the notion <strong>of</strong>likeness should be interpreted by virtue <strong>of</strong> what is variously described as arelation <strong>of</strong> “co-formality” or “formal identity” or “sharing <strong>of</strong> form.” 20 The ideais that the intelligible species is a likeness <strong>of</strong> the thing thought about becausethe intelligible species and the thing thought about are formally identical, i.e.they share the same general form. Thus, the same general form felinity can beinstantiated in two different kinds <strong>of</strong> individuals, i.e. individual cats in the19 ST I, q. 85, a. 2, ad 1: “ […] intellectum est in intelligente per suam similitudinem. Etper hunc modum dicitur quod intellectum in actu est intellectus in actu, inquantum similitudo reiintellectae est forma intellectus; sicut similitudo rei sensibilis est forma sensus in actu.” TheEnglish translation is taken from Thomas Aquinas, The Treatise on Human Nature. Summatheologiae 1a 75–89. Translated, with Introduction and Comentary, by Robert Pasnau(Indianapolis/Cambridge: Hackett Publishing Company, 2002), 164.20 G. Klima, “Aquinas’s Pro<strong>of</strong>s <strong>of</strong> the Immateriality <strong>of</strong> Intellect from the Universality <strong>of</strong>Thought,” Proceedings <strong>of</strong> the Society for Medieval Logic and Metaphysics 1 (2001): 19–28, onlineat http://faculty.fordham.edu/klima/SMLM/PSMLM1/PSMLM1.pdf; id., “Tradition andInnovation in Medieval Theories <strong>of</strong> Mental Representation,” Proceedings <strong>of</strong> the Society forMedieval Logic and Metaphysics 4 (2004): 4–11, on-line at http://faculty.fordham.edu/klima/SMLM/PSMLM4/PSMLM4.pdf; Stump, Aquinas, 273–275; King, “Rethinking Representation.”9


extramental world and individual intelligible species in the intellects <strong>of</strong> thosewho know what it is to be a cat. This interpretation has the great advantage <strong>of</strong>dissipating the mystery surrounding the notions <strong>of</strong> likeness, similitude andrepresentation. A certain quality in my intellect is a representation <strong>of</strong>extramental cats just because that quality and extramental cats areinstantiations <strong>of</strong> the same general form. Of course, there remains to beexplained why the form felinity is instantiated in individual cats in theextramental world whereas there is no cat in my intellect when the formfelinity is received there. This is thought to depend on the kind <strong>of</strong> subject theform is received in. When the form felinity is received in some specific matter,i.e. some specific flesh, bones, etc., it acts as the organizing principle <strong>of</strong> thatmatter. By contrast, when the same general form felinity is received in anintellect, an intelligible species, i.e. a likeness <strong>of</strong> a cat, is produced. In turn, itmay be claimed that the intellect is the sort <strong>of</strong> subject that receives formswithout becoming the thing whose form it receives because the intellect is animmaterial subject. 21Several passages in Aquinas’s writings lend support to thisinterpretation. From a general point <strong>of</strong> view, Aquinas held that two things arealike when they share the same form. Thus, he did not seem to assume therelationship <strong>of</strong> likeness as primitive. Rather, he reduced that relationship to thesharing <strong>of</strong> the same form. 22 More specifically, Aquinas referred to the form inthe intellect and the form <strong>of</strong> the thing thought about as the same forminstantiated in two subjects, just as the same color is present in differentshades in different subjects. 23 There is <strong>of</strong> course a fundamental difference21 Aquinas, Sent. II, d. 3, q. 1, a. 1, ad 3 (Mandonnet, 88–89); De ente, 4, 375.11–-375.23; CG II, 50, n. 1261 and n. 1264; CG II, 91, n. 177 (“immunitas materiae confert esseintelligibile”); ST I, q. 50, a. 2; De substantiis separatis, 7 (Leon. 40, D 52.19–44). See R. Pasnau,Theories <strong>of</strong> Cognition, 31–60; id., “What Is Cognition? A Reply to Some Critics,” AmericanCatholic Philosophical Quarterly 76 (2002): 483–490.22 See for example Sent. II, d. 15, q. 1, a. 2, ad 4: “Similia sunt quae in eadem formacommunicant.” Admittedly, Aquinas also held that there is another kind <strong>of</strong> likeness, according towhich two things are alike if they are related to different terms in the same way. For example, amayor can be said to be like a captain because the mayor is related to a city just as the captain isrelated to a ship. The mayor and the captain, however, share no common form, since the kind <strong>of</strong>authority that the mayor has over a city is different from the kind <strong>of</strong> authority that a captain hasover a ship. See Sent. I, d. 34, q. 3, a. 1, ad 2. This kind <strong>of</strong> likeness, however, does not seem to berelevant to the case <strong>of</strong> the species and the object <strong>of</strong> cognition, for in the latter case only two (andnot four) terms are involved, i.e. the species and the object.23 ST I, q. 84, a. 1: “Hoc autem [scil., quod forma cogniti ex necessitate sit incognoscente eo modo quo est in cognito] necessarium non est. Quia etiam in ipsis sensibilibusvidemus quod forma alio modo est in uno sensibilium quam in altero: puta cum in uno est albedointensior, in alio remissior, et in uno est albedo cum dulcedine, in alio sine dulcedine. Et per huncetiam modum forma sensibilis alio modo est in re quae est extra animam, et alio modo in sensu,qui suscipit formas sensibilium absque materia, sicut colorem auri sine auro. Et similiterintellectus species corporum, quae sunt materiales et mobiles, recipit immaterialiter et10


etween the case <strong>of</strong> the color and that <strong>of</strong> an intelligible species. While eachinstance <strong>of</strong> white is an individual quality belonging to the same species, i.e.the color white, an extramental cat and my intelligible species <strong>of</strong> a cat are nottwo individuals belonging to the same species cat. This, however, can beexplained by the fact that in order for an individual cat to exist, the formfelinity must be instantiated in a certain portion <strong>of</strong> matter. But this is preciselywhat does not happen when the form felinity is received in my intellect, sincemy intellect is immaterial. 24Other interpreters, however, hold that this interpretation <strong>of</strong> Aquinasends up committing him to several implausible claims. Accordingly, theseinterpreters argue that the notion <strong>of</strong> likeness or similitude should be assumedas primitive. That something represents something else cannot be explained interms <strong>of</strong> sharing the same form. Rather, this should be assumed as brute fact. 25Nothing <strong>of</strong> what follows, however, depends on which <strong>of</strong> these twointerpretations <strong>of</strong> Aquinas is favored. No matter whether the form in theintellect is the same or not as the form <strong>of</strong> the extramental thing that is beingcognized, it is clear that in order for somebody to have intellectual cognition<strong>of</strong> something it is necessary for her to have a form in her intellect. And it alsoclear that such a form comes to be present in her intellect in consequence <strong>of</strong> achange.2.2. Acts <strong>of</strong> thinking as actionsSo what kind <strong>of</strong> change is that by which the intelligible species comesto be present in the intellect?At times, Aquinas seemed to be endorsing Aristotle’s claim that tothink is to undergo a change. Thus, acts <strong>of</strong> thinking should be regarded asinstances <strong>of</strong> passions as opposed to actions. For example, when I think aboutwhat it is to be a cat, my intellect receives the form felinity from real cats. Inthat change, real cats play the role <strong>of</strong> agents while my intellect plays the role<strong>of</strong> a patient. Thus, my act <strong>of</strong> thinking is something that cats do to me, notsomething that I literally do. Cats impress their forms on my intellect, just asfire impresses the form heat on a kettle. Aquinas suggested that this is whatactually happens when he contrasted the way human beings cognize to divineand angelic cognition. Unlike God and angels, human beings receive theimmobiliter, secundum modum suum: nam receptum est in recipiente per modum recipientis.”See also De substantiis separatis, 7: “ […] sic enim intellectus intelligit rem secundum quod formaeius in ipso existit.”24 See above, note 21.25 C. Panaccio, “Aquinas on Intellectual Representation,” in Ancient and MedievalTheories <strong>of</strong> Intentionality, 185–200; Brower and Brower Toland, “Aquinas on MentalRepresentation.”11


forms <strong>of</strong> what they think about as a result <strong>of</strong> an action <strong>of</strong> those things on theirintellects:There is a difference on this point between the human mind, whichderives forms from things, and the divine or angelic minds, which do notdraw their cognition from things. In the mind which depends on things fromknowledge, the forms exist because <strong>of</strong> a certain action <strong>of</strong> things on the soul.But, since all action is through form, the forms in our minds first and mainly26refer to things which exist outside our soul according to their forms. (Italicsmine)This, however, should be taken as a very general description <strong>of</strong> whathappens when I think about something. Any time Aquinas provided a moredetailed account <strong>of</strong> what it is to think, he argued that the claim that to cognizeis to undergo a change is true, strictly speaking, only <strong>of</strong> sensory cognition. Bycontrast, as far as thinking is concerned, Aquinas took into account what Ihave labeled the “activity problem” in Aristotle. When I think aboutsomething, it seems that I am genuinely doing something and that I am notmerely the subject <strong>of</strong> a change happening to me. That was also a view thatAquinas had to adopt as a consequence <strong>of</strong> his endorsement <strong>of</strong> the claim(which he could read in Augustine and which he thought that Aristotle himselfhad subscribed to) that nothing material can act on what is immaterial.Accordingly, no material object can act on the intellect. 27Thus, Aquinas readjusted the Aristotelian account <strong>of</strong> intellectualcognition in order to make room for the intellect’s active role in the process <strong>of</strong>thinking. 28 He obtained this result by a threefold strategy. First, he argued that,26 De Ver., q. 10, a. 4: “Hoc autem differenter contingit in mente humana quae formasaccipit a rebus, et in divina vel angelica quae a rebus non accipiunt. In mente enim accipientescientiam a rebus, formae existunt per quandam actionem rerum in animam; omnis autem actioest per formam; unde formae quae sunt in mente nostra primo et principaliter respiciunt res extraanimam existentes quantum ad formas earum.” The English translation is from St. ThomasAquinas, Truth. Transl. by James V. McGlynn (Chicago: Henry Regnery Company, 1953), vol. 2,p. 19.27 See for example Augustine, In Genesi ad litteram, II, 16: “[…] non est putandumaliquid agere corpus in spiritum, tamquam spiritus corpori facienti, materiae vice subdatur. Omnimodo praestantior est qui facit, ea re qua aliquid facit.” For Aquinas’s endorsement <strong>of</strong> this claimand his conviction that Aristotle subscribed to that position, see ST I, q. 84, a. 6: “Intellectum veroposuit Aristoteles habere operationem absque communicatione corporis. Nihil autem corporeumimprimere potest in rem incorpoream. Et ideo ad causandam intellectualem operationem,secundum Aristotelem, non sufficit sola impressio sensibilium corporum, sed requirit aliquidnobilius, quia agens est honorabilius patiente, ut ipse dicit.”28 As a matter <strong>of</strong> fact, Aquinas thought that he was merely embracing Aristotle’sgenuine doctrine. It is clear, however, that he ended up holding a position that was not identicalwith Aristotle’s. It is also clear that Aquinas’s interpretation <strong>of</strong> Aristotle’s cognitive psychology washighly indebted to the late ancient tradition <strong>of</strong> Aristotelain commentators, specifically to12


even though the material object does not act on the intellect, the intellect doesnevertheless receive its form. Second, he granted that the object plays somecausal role in the act <strong>of</strong> thinking, even though he dramatically curtailed thatrole. Third, he distinguished between the intellect’s reception <strong>of</strong> the object’sform, on the one hand, and, on the other hand, the intellect’s act <strong>of</strong> thinkingproper.Concerning the first point, Aquinas held that the form <strong>of</strong> an object isimpressed on the intellect not by that object but by the intellect itself.Specifically, Aquinas distinguished between an active and a passive role theintellect plays in cognition. Both roles are played by numerically the sameintellect. In its active role, the intellect performs an operation called“abstraction,” which results in the production <strong>of</strong> a mental quality that has thesame form as the sensory impressions and the images caused by the object.That mental quality is nothing else than the intelligible species, Thus, theintelligible species is produced by the agent intellect, not by the object. It is,nevertheless, a representation <strong>of</strong> the object, because its form is the same asthat <strong>of</strong> the object (or is a representation <strong>of</strong> the form <strong>of</strong> the object), even thoughits way <strong>of</strong> existing is different, i.e. immaterial rather than material. Just like anyordinary action, the agent intellect’s production <strong>of</strong> the intelligible species canbe analyzed into the agent’s production <strong>of</strong> a form in a patient. The agentintellect plays the role <strong>of</strong> agent in that process. The form produced andreceived is the intelligible species. As to the patient, its role is played by theintellect itself, taken in its passive role, i.e. the so-called “possible intellect.” 29Concerning the second point, Aquinas held that the object, throughthe intermediary <strong>of</strong> its sensory image (the so-called “phantasm”), plays somecausal role in intellectual cognition. Admittedly, the image <strong>of</strong> an object is notthe sole or even the principal agent in the process <strong>of</strong> reception <strong>of</strong> that object’sform in the possible intellect. Rather, the agent intellect is the main agent inthat production. The image <strong>of</strong> the object, however, plays the role <strong>of</strong>“instrumental or secondary agent.” Even though the details <strong>of</strong> this view maynot be completely clear, Aquinas intended to reject the claim that the object,through the intermediary <strong>of</strong> its sensory image, plays a merely accessory andnon-causal role in the process <strong>of</strong> intellectual cognition. By contrast, theThemistius, as evidenced by notes to the Leonine edition <strong>of</strong> Aquinas’s commentary on Aristotle’sDe anima. 29 ST I, q. 79, a. 2–4; q. 85, a. 1. See Pasnau, Thomas Aquinas on Human Nature, 310–318; Stump, Aquinas, 263–264. On the role <strong>of</strong> the agent intellect in Aristotle and the controversialintepretation <strong>of</strong> De anima III, 5, see M. Frede, “La théorie aristotélicienne de l’intellect agent,” inCorps et âme. Sur le De anima d’Aristote, ed. G. Romeyer Dherbey and C. Viano (Paris: Vrin,1996), 377–390; M. F. Burnyeat, Aristotle’s Divine Intellect (Milwaukee: Marquette <strong>University</strong>Press, 2008).13


object’s sensory image is a real agent in the process <strong>of</strong> intellectual cognition,even though it cannot act without the agent intellect’s intervention. 30Subsequently, Aquinas preferred to refer to sensory images as something like(quodammodo) the matter on which the agent intellect performs its action. 31 Inboth cases, the object and its image can be described as a necessary but notsufficient cause <strong>of</strong> an intelligible species.Aquinas’s contention that the object plays a causal role in the act <strong>of</strong>thinking was the key move that allows him to explain an act <strong>of</strong> thinking’sintentionality. It is because an object, through its sensory image, has a causalrole in the process <strong>of</strong> intellectual cognition that the form received in theintellect is the form <strong>of</strong> a certain object. 32 Consequently, the act <strong>of</strong> thinkingtriggered by the reception <strong>of</strong> a certain form is an act <strong>of</strong> thinking about acertain object because it is the reception <strong>of</strong> form <strong>of</strong> that object that triggeredthat act <strong>of</strong> thinking.It is the third point in Aquinas’s strategy, however, that is particularlyworth noticing. Aquinas held that, once the possible intellect receives theform <strong>of</strong> a certain object from the agent intellect, the possible intellect becomesitself an agent.This point may be easily missed. Because the human intellect ispotential with respect to its operation <strong>of</strong> actually thinking about something, itmust be made actual by the reception <strong>of</strong> a form (i.e. an intelligible species).Before learning what it is to be a cat, I only have the capacity to think aboutcats. Thus, in order to actually think about what it is a cat, I must receive theform felinity in my possible intellect. According to Averroes’ interpretation <strong>of</strong>Aristotle, this is just what to think is. Once the possible intellect receives the30 De Ver., q. 10, a. 6, ad 7: “Ad septimum dicendum quod in receptione quaintellectus possibilis species rerum accipit a phantasmatibus, se habent phantasmata ut agensinstrumentale vel secundarium, intellectus vero agens ut agens principale et primum; et ideoeffectus actionis relinquitur in intellectu possibili secundum condicionem utriusque et nonsecundum condicionem alterius tantum; et ideo intellectus possibilis recipit formas ut intelligibilesactu ex virtute intellectus agentis, sed ut similitudines determinatarum rerum ex cognitionephantasmatum […].”31 ST I, q. 84, a. 6: “[…] ex parte phantasmatum intellectualis operatio a sensucausatur. Sed quia phantasmata non sufficiunt immutare intellectum possibilem, sed oportet quodfiant intelligibilia actu per intellectum agentem; non potest dici quod sensibilis cognitio sit totaliset perfecta causa intellectualis cognitionis, sed magis quodammodo est materia causae.” Aquinasrejected the view that senses and sensory images merely provide the intellect with an opportunityfor producing the intelligible species or obtaining them from something else (such as a separateintelligence). Rather, the senses and sensory images play a genuinely causal role in the production<strong>of</strong> an intelligible species. See ST I, q. 84, a. 4.32 See in particular the last clause <strong>of</strong> the text quoted above, at note 30.14


form abstracted by the agent intellect, an act <strong>of</strong> thinking occurs. According toAverroes, there is nothing more to thinking than abstraction. 33Aquinas, however, did not adopt this position. Even though thepossible intellect’s reception <strong>of</strong> a species is necessary for an act <strong>of</strong> thinking tooccur, nevertheless an act <strong>of</strong> thinking is not identical with the possibleintellect’s reception <strong>of</strong> a species. By contrast, Aquinas held that the reception<strong>of</strong> a species is necessary only because the human intellect is potential withregard to its act. By itself, however, to think about something is not to receivea species. It is a distinct event. 34Accordingly, it is necessary to distinguish two different actions carriedout by the intellect in the process <strong>of</strong> thinking. First, there is the agent intellect’sact <strong>of</strong> abstracting an intelligible species and <strong>of</strong> impressing it on the possibleintellect. In this process, the possible intellect plays the role <strong>of</strong> a patient.Second, there is the act <strong>of</strong> thinking proper. The act <strong>of</strong> thinking is performed bythe possible intellect once it has received the intelligible species. In the latterprocess, the possible intellect plays the role <strong>of</strong> an agent. These two processescan be compared to sense’s being changed by a sensory object and theimagination’s forming <strong>of</strong> a sensory image. In sensory cognition, these twoprocesses are carried out by two distinct powers, i.e. sense and imagination,respectively. By contrast, in intellectual cognition both processes are carriedout by the intellect. Nevertheless, they are two distinct actions. It is one thingfor the possible intellect to pass from a potential to an actual state thanks tothe reception <strong>of</strong> a form. It is another thing for the possible intellect, once it hasbeen made actual, to carry out its own operation. The possible intellect’s act<strong>of</strong> reception is a passion. The possible intellect’s act <strong>of</strong> thinking is an action. 3533 Averroes, Commentarium magnum in Aristotelis de anima libros, ed. F. StuartCrawford (Mediaeval Academy <strong>of</strong> America: Cambridge, Mass., 1953), 439: “Abstrahere enim nihilest aliud quam facere intentiones ymaginatas intellectas in actu postquam erant in potentia;intelligere autem nichil aliud est quam recipere has intentiones.” Some years after Aquinas,Godfrey <strong>of</strong> Fontaines quoted Averroes’ position with approval in his Quodl. V, q. 10 (PhB 3, 38–39). See J. F. Wippel, “The Role <strong>of</strong> the Phantasm in Godfrey <strong>of</strong> Fontaines’ Theory <strong>of</strong> Intellection,”in C. Wenin (ed.), L’homme et son univers au Moyen Age (Louvain-la-Neuve: Éditions de l’InstitutSupérieur de Philosophie, 1986), 573–582, at 579, note 19.34 ST I, q. 14, a. 2: “Ex hoc enim aliquid in actu sentimus vel intelligimus, quodintellectus noster vel sensus informatur in actu per speciem sensibilis vel intelligibilis. Etsecundum hoc tantum sensus vel intellectus aliud est a sensibili vel intelligibili, quia utrumque estin potentia.” See also ST I, q. 56, a. 2.35 ST I, q. 85, a. 2, ad 3: “In parte sensitiva invenitur duplex operatio. Una secundumsolam immutationem: et sic perficitur operatio sensus per hoc quod immutatur a sensibili. Aliaoperatio est formatio, secundum quod vis imaginativa format sibi aliquod idolum rei absentis, veletiam nunquam visae. Et utraque haec operatio [scil. immutatio et formatio] coniungitur inintellectu. Nam primo quidem consideratur passio intellectus possibilis secundum quodinformatur specie intelligibili. Qua quidem formatus, format secundo vel definitionem veldivisionem vel compositionem, quae per vocem significatur.”15


It may be useful to illustrate this distinction with a comparison.Consider a light bulb. When the light is on, it is possible to distinguish twoseparate processes. On the one hand, the light bulb receives electricity in itscircuits. On the other hand, that light bulb, once it has received electricity inits circuit, gives out light. Even though these two actions occursimultaneously, they should be considered as distinct. Each action has its owneffect. The first action’s effect is the illumination <strong>of</strong> the bulb. The secondaction’s effect is the bulb’s illuminating its environment. 36By this threefold strategy, Aquinas managed to keep the advantages <strong>of</strong>Aristotle’s account while making room for the intellect’s active role in the act<strong>of</strong> thinking. The act <strong>of</strong> thinking can still be interpreted as a change or process.In that process, the intellect plays the role <strong>of</strong> a patient. Both the object and theintellect, however, play the role <strong>of</strong> agents. Because the object, by virtue <strong>of</strong> itssensory image, performs a causal role in the act <strong>of</strong> thinking, an act <strong>of</strong> thinkingis about a certain thing. Specifically, an act <strong>of</strong> thinking is about the thingwhose sensory image plays the role <strong>of</strong> agent (in some way) <strong>of</strong> that act. Thus,the intentionality <strong>of</strong> an act <strong>of</strong> thinking is explained by the causal role that itsobject plays on that act. By contrast, it is because the intellect is active withregard to acts <strong>of</strong> thinking that my acts <strong>of</strong> thinking are something that I do, notsomething that is done to me. This is true at two levels. First, the intellectabstracts a mental quality form the sensory image <strong>of</strong> an object. Second, theintellect, made actual by that quality, performs the act <strong>of</strong> thinking as its ownproper activity.The elegance <strong>of</strong> Aquinas’s account <strong>of</strong> thinking resides in the claimthat numerically the same mental quality (i.e. the intelligible species) is bothwhat represents an extramental object and what actualizes the intellect’spower to think. 37 Because <strong>of</strong> this tw<strong>of</strong>old function <strong>of</strong> the intelligible species,the act <strong>of</strong> thinking is both an action performed by the intellect and an actabout something in the world.36The distinction between these two actions may be made apparent if we leave the firstaction untouched but we tamper with the second, for example by putting a sheet <strong>of</strong> opaque paperaround a bulb. The bulb is still illuminated but does not illuminate anymore.37 De Ver., q. 10, a. 4: “Dicendum, quod omnis cognitio est secundum aliquamformam quae est in cognoscente principium cognitionis. Forma autem huiusmodi dupliciter potestconsiderari: uno modo secundum esse quod habet in cognoscente, alio modo secundumrespectum quem habet ad rem cuius est similitudo. Secundum quidem primum respectum facitcognoscentem actu cognoscere, sed secundum respectum secundum determinat cognitionem adaliquod cognoscibile determinatum […].” Specifically concerning intellectual cognition, see ST I,q. 85, a. 2, ad 1: “ […] intellectum est in intelligente per suam similitudinem. Et per hunc modumdicitur quod intellectum in actu est intellectus in actu, inquantum similitudo rei intellectae estforma intellectus; sicut similitudo rei sensibilis est forma sensus in actu.” See also ST I, q. 85, a. 5;Sent. libri de anima, II, 24, pp. 168–169.16


2.3. Acts <strong>of</strong> thinking as self-contained actions: Aquinas’s two accountsSo Aquinas could reconcile the main elements <strong>of</strong> Aristotle’s accountwith his key insight that acts <strong>of</strong> thinking are actions carried out by theintellect. To think is not a change the intellect undergoes but a change theintellect effects. Aristotle’s description <strong>of</strong> the intellect as a passive power canbe maintained, but only if it is interpreted in a very specific way. The intellectis a passive power only in the sense that, by its essence, it is not actual, i.e. itis capable <strong>of</strong> thinking but does not actually think. In order to actually think,the intellect must be made actual. This happens only when the intellectreceives a form. 38 It is the intellect itself, however, that makes itself actual byabstracting a form from the sensory image <strong>of</strong> an object and by impressing it onitself. What is more, once the intellect has impressed on itself the form <strong>of</strong> anobject, it becomes an agent in the process <strong>of</strong> thinking. Thus, to think issomething I do, not something that is being done to me, even though, in orderfor me to carry out an act <strong>of</strong> thinking, I must receive some information aboutwhat I am thinking about via the senses and the imagination.Specifically, Aquinas held that the act <strong>of</strong> thinking is a self-containedor immanent action. Like Aristotle, Aquinas distinguished between two kinds<strong>of</strong> actions. Some actions produce a result distinct from the exercise <strong>of</strong> theaction itself. They are accordingly called “transitive actions.” For example,fire’s action <strong>of</strong> heating produce the form heat, which is distinct from the action<strong>of</strong> heating and is received in a patient such as a kettle. Other actions,however, do not produce any result distinct from their mere exercise. They areaccordingly called “immanent” or “self-contained actions.” 39 Aquinas heldthat cognitive and appetitive acts, such as sensing, imagining, thinking andwilling, are self-contained actions, which he also called “activities”38 ST I, q. 79, a. 2. See also Sent. I, d. 3, q. 1, a. 1.39 Aristotle Meta. IX, 8, 1050a23–b6. See Aquinas, CG III, 2: “Actio vero quandoquequidem terminatur ad aliquod factum, sicut aedificatio ad domum, sanatio ad sanitatem:quandoque autem non, sicut intelligere et sentire. Et si quidem actio terminatur ad aliquodfactum, impetus agentis tendit per actionem in illud factum: si autem non terminatur ad aliquodfactum, impetus agentis tendit in ipsam actionem.” Aquinas drew this distinction between twokinds <strong>of</strong> actions in many passages <strong>of</strong> his works. See for example Super I Sent., d. 40, q. 1, a. 1, ad1; De Ver., q. 8, a. 6; q. 14, a. 3; De Pot., q. 3, a. 15; q. 8, a. 1; CG II, 23, n. 993; ST I, q. 18, a. 3,ad 1; q. 23, a. 2, ad 1; q. 27, a. 1; q. 27, a. 3; q. 27, a. 5; q. 28, a. 4; q. 54, a. 1, ad 3; q. 54, a. 2;q. 56, a. 1; q. 85, a. 2; ST I-II, q. 3, a. 2, ad 3; De unitate intellectus, 3; In Meta. IX, lect. 8, nn.1862–1865; In Meta. VI, lect. 1, n. 1152; IX, lect. 2, n. 1788; XI, lect. 7, n. 2253. On Aristotle’sdistinction, see Makin’s commentary in Aristotle, Metaphysics. Book Θ. Translated with anIntroduction and Commentary by S. Makin (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 2006), 200–204. OnAquinas’s use <strong>of</strong> Aristotle’s distinction see B. Lonergan, Verbum: Word and Idea in Aquinas(Toronto: Toronto <strong>University</strong> Press, 1997 4 ), 128–133; Pasnau, Thomas Aquinas on Human Nature,352.17


(operationes). 40 He actually held that only cognitive and appetitive acts areself-contained actions. All natural actions are transitive. 41Aquinas, however, gave two alternative analyses <strong>of</strong> self-containedactions. In his first account, a self-contained action is an action that consistsmerely in an agent’s exercise <strong>of</strong> an activity that produces no result distinctfrom the activity itself. In his second account, a self-contained action is anagent’s exercise <strong>of</strong> an activity that does produce an effect distinct from theactivity itself. Contrary to what happens in transitive actions, however, theeffect <strong>of</strong> a self-contained action remains within the agent and is received in nopatient.Accordingly, Aquinas gave two alternative analyses <strong>of</strong> acts <strong>of</strong>thinking as actions. In his first analysis, an act <strong>of</strong> thinking is an action that hasno end product distinct from the act <strong>of</strong> thinking itself. Thus, the term <strong>of</strong> thataction is not distinct from its principle; what makes an intellect actual is alsothe term <strong>of</strong> the intellect’s act. 42 In his second analysis, an act <strong>of</strong> thinking is anaction that results in the production <strong>of</strong> an internal term distinct from both theact and the form that makes the intellect actual. Specifically, the intellectproduces a concept, and that concept must be distinguished both from theintellect’s act <strong>of</strong> thinking and from the intelligible species received in theintellect. The species is the formal principle <strong>of</strong> an act <strong>of</strong> thinking. This meansthat the species is the form that makes the possible intellect actually thinkabout something. By contrast, the concept (which Aquinas called“conception” and “inner word”) is the term <strong>of</strong> an act <strong>of</strong> thinking, i.e. what the40 Aristotle himself had considered perception and thought as activities and hadcontrasted them to changes in a strict sense, because in activities there is no progress and no newform is acquired. See Aristotle, Meta. IX, 6, 1048b18–35 (a passage that was unknown tomedieval interpreters) and Nicomacheans Ethics X, 3–5. See J. L. Ackrill, “Aristotle’s Distinctionbetween Energeia and Kinesis,” in New Essays on Plato and Aristotle, ed. R. Bambrough (Londonand New York: Routledge, 1965), 121–141; M. F. Burnyeat, “Kinesis vs. Energeia: A Much-ReadPassage in (but not <strong>of</strong>) Aristotle’s Metaphysics,” Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 34 (2008):219–292. 41 CG II, 23, n. 993.42 CG I 53, first draft, printed as Appendix II, A in Liber de Veritate Catholicae Fideicontra errores Infidelium seu Summa contra Gentiles, vol. 1, ed. C. Pera, P. Marc, and P.Caramello (Torino/Roma: Marietti, 1961). I quote the relevant passage here below, at note 52. Seealso ST I, q. 56, a. 2: “Sed in actione quae manet in agente, oportet ad hoc quod procedat actio,quod obiectum uniatur agenti: sicut oportet quod sensibile uniatur sensui, ad hoc quod sentiatactu. Et ita se habet obiectum unitum potentiae ad huiusmodi actionem, sicut forma quae estprincipium actionis in aliis agentibus: sicut enim calor est principium formale calefactionis inigne, ita species rei visae est principium formale visionis in oculo.” The same point is made in STI, q. 85, a. 2. On the three successive drafts <strong>of</strong> CG I, 53, see L.-B. Geiger, “Les rédactionssuccessives de Contra Gentiles I, 53, d’après l’autographe,” in Saint Thomas d’Aquin aujourd’hui(Paris: Desclée de Brouwer, 1963), 221–240.18


intellect produces when it performs the action triggered by the reception <strong>of</strong>the species. 432.4. Dispositional versus occurrent knowledgeSo far, I have presented Aquinas’s position as if the abstraction/reception <strong>of</strong> a species were both necessary and sufficient for an act <strong>of</strong> thinkingto occur. Granted that the act <strong>of</strong> abstraciton and the act <strong>of</strong> thinking triggeredby the reception <strong>of</strong> a species are two distinct acts, Aquinas seems indeed attimes to suggest that an act <strong>of</strong> thinking occurs if an only if a species isabstracted and received. 44 This cannot be the case, however. For Aquinas wasalso aware <strong>of</strong> what I have called Aristotle’s “problem <strong>of</strong> occurrent thought.” Ifthe presence <strong>of</strong> a form in the intellect were sufficient for an act <strong>of</strong> thinking tooccur, one <strong>of</strong> the following two undesirable scenarios would obtain: eitherany time I think about something I carry out a new act <strong>of</strong> abstraction and Iacquire a new intelligible species or I always think about all the things <strong>of</strong>which I have a species in my intellect. Both situations, however, areunacceptable for Aquinas. He rejected the first option in his confutation <strong>of</strong>Avicenna’s position. Avicenna held that, when I do not actually think aboutsomething, I have no intelligible species <strong>of</strong> that thing in my intellect. Bycontrast, Aquinas claimed that once I have learned something, I keep anintelligible species <strong>of</strong> that thing stored in my intellect even though I am notactually thinking about it. Thus, according to Aquinas, the difference between43 CG I, 53 (third and definitive draft); CG IV, 11; ST I, q. 27, a. 1; q. 28, a. 4, ad 1; q.34, a. 1; q. 85, a. 2, ad 3; De Pot., q. 8, a. 1; q. 9, a. 5; Quodl. V, a. 2; Super Evang. Ioan., I, 1;De spirit. creat., 9. Some elements <strong>of</strong> this account were already present in De Ver., q. 4, a. 2.Aquinas developed his second analysis <strong>of</strong> acts <strong>of</strong> thinking mostly because <strong>of</strong> theological reasonsconnected with the evolution <strong>of</strong> his understanding <strong>of</strong> the Trinity. But he explicitly applied his newanalysis to human thinking. The second account was supposed to replace the first one, but as amatter <strong>of</strong> fact Aquinas still referred to his first account in ST. On Aquinas’s evolution in thisrespect, see See H. Paissac. Théologie du Verbe. Saint Augustin et Saint Thomas (Paris: LesÉditions du Cerf, 1951); R. Gauthier, Saint Thomas d’Aquin. Somme contre les gentils.Introductoin par René-Antoine Gauthier (Paris: Éditions universitaires, 1993), 105–108; A. F. vanGunten, “In principio erat Verbum. Une evolution de saint Thomas en théologie trinitaire,” inOrdo Sapientiae et Amoris. Hommage au Pr<strong>of</strong>esseur Jean-Pierre Torrell OP à l’occasion de son 65 eanniversaire, ed. C.-J. Pinto de Oliveira (Fribourg, Suisse: Éditions universitaires, 1993), 119–141.On Aquinas’s first account, see J. Chênevert, “Le verbum dans le Commentaire sur les Sentencesde Saint Thomas d’Aquin,” Sciences ecclésiastiques 13 (1961): 191–233, 359–390. These twodifferent accounts are not usually distinguished in the most recent literature concerning Aquinas’stheory <strong>of</strong> intellectual cognition. Only the second account is usually taken into consideration. SeePanaccio, “Aquinas on Intellectual Representation,” 190–196; id., “From Mental Word to MentalLanguage,” Philosophical Topics 20 (1992): 125–147, esp. 126–129; id., Le discours intérieur dePlaton à Guillaume d’Ockham (Paris: Éditions du Seuil, 1999), 177–192; Pasnau, Theories <strong>of</strong>Cognition, 256–271; id., Thomas Aquinas on Human Nature, 327–328; Stump, Aquinas, 266–168. I will deal more in detail with Aquinas’s two accounts <strong>of</strong> the act <strong>of</strong> thinking in a separatepaper.44 See for example ST I, q. 14, a. 2, quoted above, note 34.19


eing in a state <strong>of</strong> ignorance and being in a state <strong>of</strong> knowledge with respect tosomething is a difference in the furniture <strong>of</strong> our intellect. 45This, however, does not mean that I always think about all I know.Aquinas held that there is a difference between dispositional and occurrentknowledge, or, in Aristotelian terms, between knowing something in firstactuality and knowing something in second actuality. 46 Accordingly, Aquinashad to reject the view that the presence <strong>of</strong> an intelligible species in theintellect is sufficient for an act <strong>of</strong> thinking to occur. But then, what else isrequired in addition to the abstraction/reception <strong>of</strong> a species in order for anact <strong>of</strong> thinking to occur?In order to account for the passage from dispositional to occurrentknowledge, Aquinas introduced the view that an intelligible species can berelated to the intellect in three ways. First, a species can be in the intellectonly potentially. In that case, I am ignorant <strong>of</strong> what something is, but I amable to learn what it is. Second, a species can be in the intellect in completeactuality, i.e. when I actually think about something. Third and crucially, aspecies can be present in the intellect in an intermediate way, which is neitherentirely potential nor entirely actual. In that case, I know what something isbut I do not think about it. Because a species can be present in thisintermediate way, I keep some knowledge <strong>of</strong> the things I have learned eventhough I do not always think about all the things I know:An intelligible species is sometimes present only potentially in theintellect, and then the intellect is said to be in potentiality. Sometimes it isthere inasmuch as the act is entirely complete, and then the intellect isactually thinking. Sometimes it stands midway between potentiality andactuality, and then the intellect is said to have a disposition. It is in this waythat the intellect preserves species, even when it is not actually thinking.4745 See De Ver., q. 10, a. 2; ST I, q. 79, a. 6; CG, II, 74; Quodl. III, q. 9, a. 1; Quodl. XII,q. 9, a. 1. See also De Ver., q. 19, a. 1; ST I-II, q. 67, a. 2. The position Aquinas rejected is foundin Avicenna, Liber de anima, pars 5, c. 6, 128–131. On Avicenna, see H. A. Davidson, Alfarabi,Avicenna, and Averroes on Intellect. Their Cosmologies, Theories <strong>of</strong> the Active Intellect, andTheories <strong>of</strong> Human Intellect (New York/Oxford: Oxford <strong>University</strong> Press, 1992), 83–94.46 See for example De malo, q. 1, a. 5: “Actus autem est duplex, scilicet primus, qui esthabitus uel forma, et secundus, qui est operatio, sicut scientia et considerare. Actu autem primoinherente adhuc est potentia ad actum secundum, sicut sciens nondum actu considerat setconsiderare potest.” The form that makes the possible intellect actual can be considered potentialwith respect to the intellect’s action. See Sent. IV, d. 49, q. 3, a. 2: “Ultimum autem etperfectissimum quod est in unoquoque est sua operatio; unde omnis forma inhaerens comparaturad operationem quodammodo ut potentia ad actum; propter quod forma dicitur actus primus, utscientia; et operatio actus secundus, ut considerare, ut patet in II de Anima.” For Aristotle, seeabove, n. 17.47 ST I, q. 79, a. 6, ad 3: “Ad tertium dicendum quod species intelligibilis aliquando estin intellectu in potentia tantum: et tunc dicitur intellectus esse in potentia. Aliquando autemsecundum ultimam completionem actus: et tunc intelligit actu. Aliquando medio modo se habet20


Aquinas never gave a detailed description <strong>of</strong> how the passage fromdispositional to occurrent knowledge takes place. It is very likely that theintelligible species is brought to the state <strong>of</strong> complete actuality by whatAquinas called the intellect’s “turning back towards the sensory images”(conversio ad phantasmata). By turning back to the sensory image from whicha certain intelligible species has been abstracted, the intellect revitalizes thatspecies, which until then was lying dormant in the intellect itself. 48 Thus, theprocess <strong>of</strong> thinking is cognate to the process <strong>of</strong> learning something. When theintellect learns something, it acquires a certain form for the first time. Bycontrast, when the intellect thinks about something, it re-acquire in fullactuality a form that had been partially forgotten and that was in a state <strong>of</strong>incomplete actuality. This act <strong>of</strong> re-acquisition is effected through theintellect’s turning back towards the sensory image, which in turn is triggeredby an act <strong>of</strong> the will, which Aquinas calls by the Augustinian term <strong>of</strong>“attention” (intentio). 49 Thus, I actually think about what it is to be a cat if andonly if I decide to focus on the sensory image <strong>of</strong> a cat and in that way I bringback to my mind what I already know about cats.This explanation <strong>of</strong> the passage from dispositional to occurrentknowledge can be applied to both <strong>of</strong> the accounts <strong>of</strong> an act <strong>of</strong> thinking as aself-contained action that I have distinguished above. According to Aquinas’sfirst account, once the intelligible species is present in the possible intellect inits full actuality, the intellect itself performs an act <strong>of</strong> thinking whose innerterm is coincident with the species itself. By contrast, according to Aquinas’ssecond account, once the intelligible species is present in the possibleintellect in its full actuality, the intellect performs an act <strong>of</strong> thinking whoseinter potentiam et actum: et tunc dicitur esse intellectus in habitu. Et secundum hunc modumintellectus conservat species, etiam quando actu non intelligit.” The Enligh Translation is fromThomas Aquinas, The Treatise on Human Nature, trans. Pasnau, 92. See also De Ver., q. 10, a. 2,ad 4; De Ver., q. 19, a. 1; CG II, 74, n. 16; Quodl. III, q. 9, a. 1; Sent. libri de anima, III, cap. II, p.208.48 De Ver., q. 10, a. 2, ad 7: “Nulla potentia potest aliquid cognoscere nisi convertendose ad obiectum suum […]; unde […] quantumcumque aliquam speciem intelligibilem apud seintellectus habeat, numquam tamen actu aliquid considerat secundum illam speciem nisiconvertendo se ad phantasmata.” See also Quodl. XII, q. 9, a. 1: “[…] et non solum propter hoc[scil. corpus] phantasmata indigemus, sed ad utendum huiusmodi species.” And more in generalST I, q. 84, a. 7. See Pasnau, Theories <strong>of</strong> Cognition, 135–136; id., Thomas Aquinas on HumanNature, 284–295.49 De Ver., q. 13, a. 3: “[…] ad actum alicuius cognititivae potentiae requiriturintentio;” CG I, 55: “Vis cognoscitiva non cognoscit aliquid actu nisi adsit intentio: unde etphantasmata in organo conservata interdum non actu imaginamur, quia intentio non fertur ad ea.”See also Sent. I, d. 3, q. 5, a. 5: “Ad talem enim cognitionem non sufficiet praesentia rei quolibetmodo; sed oportet ut sit ibi in ratione obiecti, et exigitur intentio cognoscentis.” See Pasnau,Theories <strong>of</strong> Cognition, 134–135. For Augustine’s notion <strong>of</strong> attention, see Augustine, De Trin., XI,2.2–3.21


inner term is a concept produced by that very act. That concept is producedby the intellect only as long as the intellect actually thinks. When the intellectdoes not perform its action and the species recedes to a dormant state, noconcept is produced and present in the intellect. 50The main problem with the claim that an intelligible species can bepossessed in complete or incomplete actuality is that it sounds like an ad hocmove to account for the passage from dispositional to occurrent knowledge. Initself, the view that a form can be possessed in incomplete actuality isobscure. A form is just what makes something actual. In this case, anintelligible species is what brings the possible intellect to a state <strong>of</strong> actuality.So how can what makes something actual be possessed in incompleteactuality? There seems to be the risk <strong>of</strong> an infinite regress.2.5. Aquinas on the intentionality <strong>of</strong> acts <strong>of</strong> thinkingBoth in his first and in his second analysis <strong>of</strong> acts <strong>of</strong> thinking as selfcontainedactions, Aquinas held that the burden <strong>of</strong> intentionality is carried bythe intelligible species. Thus, a certain act <strong>of</strong> thinking is about a certain objectnot because that act is related to that object but because it is preceded andmade possible by the abstraction/reception <strong>of</strong> the intelligible species <strong>of</strong> thatobject. For example, my act <strong>of</strong> thinking about what it is to be a cat is aboutthe essence <strong>of</strong> cats not because that act is related to that essence but becausethere is the intelligible species <strong>of</strong> cats in my possible intellect and that speciesmakes possible my intellect’s act <strong>of</strong> thinking.So intentional acts in general and acts <strong>of</strong> thinking in particular areacts that are not related to the things they are about. Aquinas was forced tothis paradoxical position by his view that intentional acts in general and acts<strong>of</strong> thinking in particular are actions, and more specifically self-containedactions. According to his first account, self-contained actions are actionswhose term coincide with the form that triggers them. Thus, an act <strong>of</strong> thinkingis related only to an intelligible species, not to an extramental thing.According to Aquinas’s second account, self-contained actions are actionsthat produce their own inner term. Thus, an act <strong>of</strong> thinking is related to theconcept it produces, not to the extramental thing it is supposed to be about. In50 De Pot., q. 8, a. 1: “[Conceptio] [d]iffert autem a specie intelligibili: nam speciesintelligibilis, qua fit intellectus in actu, consideratur ut principium actionis intellectus, cum omneagens agat secundum quod est in actu; actu autem fit per aliquam formam, quam oportet esseactionis principium. Differt autem ab actione intellectus: quia praedicta conceptio consideratur utterminus actionis, et quasi quoddam per ipsam constitutum.” Aquinas explicitly held that theconcept or inner word is present only when an act <strong>of</strong> thinking occurs in ST I, q. 93, a. 7: “Verbumautem in anima nostra sine actuali cognitione esse non potest, ut Augustinus dicit 14 De Trin.”22


neither accounts is there room for a relation between an act <strong>of</strong> thinking andthe extramental thing it is about . 51But then, why is a certain act <strong>of</strong> thinking about a certain object? Whyis my act <strong>of</strong> thinking about what it is a cat about the essence <strong>of</strong> cats?According to Aquinas’s first account, the intentionality <strong>of</strong> an act <strong>of</strong>thinking is due to that act <strong>of</strong> thinking’s being triggered by a likeness <strong>of</strong> acertain thing, i.e. by the intelligible species <strong>of</strong> a certain thing. It is theintelligible species, however, and not the act <strong>of</strong> thinking that is related to theextramental thing that is being thought about by virtue <strong>of</strong> that act <strong>of</strong> thinking.Thus, it is in some way improper to say that a certain act <strong>of</strong> thinking is aboutsomething. Rather, it would be more precise to say that the intellect becomesassimilated to a certain thing because it receives the form <strong>of</strong> that thing (i.e. anintelligible species) and the form <strong>of</strong> that thing is what activates the intellect,i.e. what makes it actually think. 52According to Aquinas’s second account <strong>of</strong> acts <strong>of</strong> thinking as actionswith internal terms, the intentionality <strong>of</strong> an act <strong>of</strong> thinking is explained in aneven more complicated way. A certain act <strong>of</strong> thinking is about a certain thingbecause the concept such an act produces is a likeness <strong>of</strong> its agent, i.e. <strong>of</strong> theintellect. Now any effect is a likeness <strong>of</strong> its cause ins<strong>of</strong>ar as that causeproduces that effect. A cause produces an effect ins<strong>of</strong>ar as that cause is actual.And what makes a cause actual is its form, whether essential or, as in thiscase, accidental. Since the intellect is made actual by an intelligible speciesand since that species is a likeness <strong>of</strong> an extramental object, the conceptproduced by the intellect, which is directly a likeness <strong>of</strong> the intellect, isindirectly a likeness <strong>of</strong> the extramental object. Thus, my act <strong>of</strong> thinking aboutwhat it is to be a cat is about the essence <strong>of</strong> cats because the concept51 The view that is being presupposed here is that an action is a relative item, and that,like any relative item, an action has a foundation (the form present in the agent) and a term atwhich it is directed (the form received in a patient or, more properly, the patient informed by thatform). For example, the action <strong>of</strong> heating is grounded on the form heat present in fire and directedat the form heat present in the kettle heated by fire or, more properly, the hot kettle. Similarly, anact <strong>of</strong> thinking is grounded on the intelligible species that actualizes the intellect and either has noterm distinct from that species (according to Aquinas’s first account) or is directed at the concept itproduces (according to Aquinas’s second account). On subjects and terms <strong>of</strong> relations, see M. G.Henninger, Relations. Medieval Theories 1250–1325 (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1989), 4–6.52 CG I, 53, first draft: “Harum igitur potentiarum operatio non terminatur ad resexteriores neque sicut ad principium agendi neque sicut ad subiectum patiens, sed ad easterminatur sola relatio potentiae operantis, quae quidem relatio consequitur formam operantis perquam operatur: sicut imaginatio per formam relictam a sensu habet operationem propriam inimaginatione consistentem, ad rem vero exteriorem quam imaginatur habet relationem performam qua informatur, et ex hac relatione contingit quod imaginando cognoscit remimaginatam. Et similiter intellectus per formam intelligibilem qua intelligit, refertur quadamsimilitudinis relatione ad rem extra quam intelligendo cognoscit. Unde et dicitur quod scientia estassimilatio scientis ad rem scitam.”23


produced by my act <strong>of</strong> thinking is a likeness <strong>of</strong> my intellectnmade actual bythe intelligible species <strong>of</strong> cats, which in turn is a likeness <strong>of</strong> cats:And this [i.e. that a concept is a likeness <strong>of</strong> the thing thought about]happens because the effect is like its cause in respect <strong>of</strong> its form, and the form<strong>of</strong> the intellect is the thing understood. Wherefore the word that originatesfrom the intellect is the likeness <strong>of</strong> the thing understood […].53Thus, the term <strong>of</strong> my act <strong>of</strong> thinking is not an extramental thing, butthe concept produced by my act <strong>of</strong> thinking. It follows that what I am thinkingabout when I am thinking about what it is to be a cat is primarily the concept<strong>of</strong> what it is to be a cat that my intellect forms. Only secondarily is my act <strong>of</strong>thinking about the essence <strong>of</strong> cats. And the reason why my act <strong>of</strong> thinking is atleast indirectly an act <strong>of</strong> thinking about what it is to be a cat is that such an actwas triggered by the reception <strong>of</strong> the form felinity in my intellect. In turn, therelation between the concept produced by my intellect and the extramentalthing it represents is a relation <strong>of</strong> final causality: the thing is the end at whichmy concept is directed. 54 Aquinas also described the relation between theconcept my intellect forms and the thing it represents as a containmentrelation: the concept is that “in which” (in quo) I understand the extramentalthing. For example, my concept <strong>of</strong> what it is to be a cat is that “in which” Ithink about what it is to be a cat. Admittedly, it is not easy to make sense <strong>of</strong>this containment relationship. What Aquinas seems to be saying is that I thinkabout what it is to be a cat by thinking about the definitional account I form inmy intellect <strong>of</strong> what it is to be a cat. 55 As Aquinas also stated, the concept myintellect forms <strong>of</strong> what it is to be a cat is the tool by which I think about whatit is to be a cat. 5653 De Pot., q. 8, a. 1: “Et hoc ideo contingit, quia effectus similatur causae secundumsuam formam: forma autem intellectus est res intellecta. Et ideo verbum quod oritur ab intellectu,est similitudo rei intellectae.” The English translation is from Thomas Aquinas, On the Power <strong>of</strong>God. Literally Translated by the English Dominican Fathers (Burn Oates & Washbourne LTD.:London, 1932), vol. 3, 71.54 De Pot., q. 9, a. 5: “Hoc ergo est primo et per se intellectum, quod intellectus inseipso concipit de re intellecta.” See also De spir. creat., 9: “Intellectum autem, sive res intellecta,se habet ut constitutum vel formatum per operationem intellectus: sive hoc sit quidditas simplex,sive sit compositio et divisio propositionis.” For the extramental thing as the end at which aconcept is directed, see De Pot. q. 8, a. 1: “ […] et iterum conceptio intellectus ordinatur ad remintellectam sicut ad finem: propter hoc enim intellectus conceptionem rei in se format ut remintellectam cognoscat.”55 Super Evang. Ioan., I, 1: “Istud ergo sic expressum, scilicet formatum in anima,dicitur verbum interius; et ideo comparatur ad intellectum, non sicut quo intellectus intelligit, sedsicut in quo intelligit; quia in ipso expresso et formato videt naturam rei intellectae.”56 Quodl. V, a. 2, ad 1: “Ad primum ergo dicendum quod intellectus intelligit aliquiddupliciter: uno modo formaliter, et sic intelligit specie intelligibili qua fit in actu; alio modo sicut24


***Based on what I have said, these are Aquinas’s answers to the threequestions I have mentioned at the beginning <strong>of</strong> this paper:(1) An act <strong>of</strong> thinking is an item in the category <strong>of</strong> action. To thinkabout something is to do something. More specifically, an act <strong>of</strong> thinking is aself-contained action. But Aquinas had two accounts <strong>of</strong> self-contained actions.According to his first account, Aquinas held that such an action does notproduce anything. Thus, to think is a process that does not issue in any resultdistinct from itself. According to his second account, Aquinas held that suchan action does produce a term, but that term is not received in a patientdistinct from the agent itself. Thus, to think is a process <strong>of</strong> concept-formation.(2) The mere presence <strong>of</strong> a form (called “intelligible species”) in thepossible intellect is a necessary but not a sufficient condition for an act <strong>of</strong>thinking to occur. In addition, that form must be present in complete actuality.This passage to complete actuality is probably effected by the intellect’sturning back to a sensory image. The intellect’s act <strong>of</strong> turning back to asensory image is in turn triggered by an act <strong>of</strong> will.(3) An act <strong>of</strong> thinking is about a certain thing because it is triggered bya certain form present in complete actuality in the possible intellect. By itself,an act <strong>of</strong> thinking is not related to its object. Rather, a certain act is about acertain object only because the intellect has been activated by a certain form.As I have mentioned, there are two particularly problematic aspectscommon to both formulations <strong>of</strong> Aquinas’s account <strong>of</strong> thinking (i.e. as an actthat produced nothing and as an act that produces an internal term). First,Aquinas had a hard time to account for the difference between dispositionaland occurrent knowledge. The notion <strong>of</strong> a species present in the intellectaccording to different degrees <strong>of</strong> actuality is clearly problematic. Second,Aquinas’s explanation <strong>of</strong> the intentionality <strong>of</strong> acts <strong>of</strong> thinking was remarkablyconvoluted. The very idea that an act <strong>of</strong> thinking is not directly related to itsobject is at first sight implausible. Both problems are consequences <strong>of</strong>Aquinas’s assumption that acts <strong>of</strong> thinking are actions. Accordingly, it doesnot come as a surprise that Scotus rejected that very assumption andapproached the whole issue from a different perspective.instrumento quo utitur ad aliud intelligendum, et hoc modo intellectus uerbo intelligit, quiaformat verbum ad hoc quod intelligat rem.”25


3. Scotus’s model <strong>of</strong> thinking: thinking as a qualityScotus laid the foundations <strong>of</strong> his account <strong>of</strong> thinking some forty yearsafter Aquinas had developed his most mature views on the subject. In theeventful period between Aquinas and Scotus, several thinkers subjectedAquinas’s treatment to careful scrutiny and sometimes harsh criticism. Amongthe elements that were most <strong>of</strong>ten criticized were Aquinas’s account <strong>of</strong>abstraction and his analysis <strong>of</strong> the act <strong>of</strong> thinking as an act <strong>of</strong> conceptformation. Concerning the agent intellect’s act <strong>of</strong> abstraction, thinkers asdiverse as Henry <strong>of</strong> Ghent, 57 Godfrey <strong>of</strong> Fontaines 58 and Peter John Olivi 59eventually argued that the agent intellect’s act <strong>of</strong> abstraction does not result inthe production <strong>of</strong> an intelligible species in the possible intellect. ConcerningAquinas’s view that an act <strong>of</strong> thinking results in the production <strong>of</strong> a concept,Henry <strong>of</strong> Ghent 60 and William <strong>of</strong> Ware conceded that a concept is actuallyproduced when an act <strong>of</strong> thinking occurs but disagreed with Aquinas’sspecific analysis <strong>of</strong> how a concept is produced. Specifically, William <strong>of</strong>Ware’s criticism <strong>of</strong> Aquinas’s second account <strong>of</strong> acts <strong>of</strong> thinking as selfcontainedactions is particularly interesting as an anticipation <strong>of</strong> Scotus’sposition. Ware argued that Aquinas’s view that self-contained actions producesomething (i.e. a concept) was both unprecedented and in contrast withAristotle’s position. He also held that while transitive actions require anobject, self-contained actions do not. And most interestingly, he argued thatAquinas posited an unnecessary intermediate entity between an act <strong>of</strong>thinking and the extramental thing that act is about. Thus, William <strong>of</strong> Ware,just as Peter John Olivi, rejected the very idea that when an act <strong>of</strong> thinkingoccurs anything apart from that act <strong>of</strong> thinking is produced. 6157 Henry <strong>of</strong> Ghent, Quodl. V, q. 14, ff, 174Y, 176O–177R. See Martin Pickavé’s paperin this volume. See in general T. V. Nys, De psychologia cognitionis humanae secundumHenricum Gandavensem (Rome: Gregorian <strong>University</strong>, 1947).58 Godfrey <strong>of</strong> Fontaines, Quodl. IX, q. 19 (PhB IV, 271–275). In general on Godfrey’sviews on abstraction, see Quodl. V, q. 10 (PhB III, 3540). See Wippel, “The Role <strong>of</strong> the Phantasmin Godfrey <strong>of</strong> Fontaines’ Theory <strong>of</strong> Intellection,” 573–582.59 Peter John Olivi, Quaestiones in secundum librum Sententiarum, q. 74, 106–135.See Pasnau, Theories <strong>of</strong> Cognition, 236–247.60 Henry <strong>of</strong> Ghent, Summa quaestionum ordinariarum, art. 58, q. 1, vol. 2, 124H–L.See S. P. Marrone, The Light <strong>of</strong> Thy Countenance: Science and Knowledge <strong>of</strong> God in theThirteenth Century (Leiden and Boston: Brill, 2001), 270–298; G. Pini, “Henry <strong>of</strong> Ghent’sDoctrine <strong>of</strong> Verbum in Its Theological Context,” in Henry <strong>of</strong> Ghent and the Transformation <strong>of</strong>Scholastic Thought: Studies in Memory <strong>of</strong> Jos Decorte (Leuven: Leuven <strong>University</strong> Press, 2003),307–326. 61 William <strong>of</strong> Ware, Sent. I, d. 27, q. 3, 258*–263*. It should be noticed that William <strong>of</strong>Ware is <strong>of</strong>ten thought to have been one <strong>of</strong> Scotus’s teachers. On Peter John Olivi, see Pasnau,Theories <strong>of</strong> Cognition, 271–276; id., “Petri Johannis Olivi Tractatus de Verbo,” Franciscan Studies53 (1993): 121–153, at 141–142.26


None <strong>of</strong> these authors, however, questioned the fundamentalassumption that acts <strong>of</strong> thinking are actions.Scotus was familiar with most <strong>of</strong> these criticisms <strong>of</strong> Aquinas’sposition. The main difficulty in reconstructing Scotus’s answers to the threequestions I have posed at the beginning <strong>of</strong> this paper is that he never gave acomprehensive treatment <strong>of</strong> what it is to think about something. Rather, hepreferred to position himself in the contemporary debate about specific issuessuch as the necessity <strong>of</strong> an intelligible species or the relationship between anact <strong>of</strong> thinking and its object. A further difficulty is that Scotus’s views evolvedfrom his first to his last works. As a consequence <strong>of</strong> these two difficulties,Scotus’s basic moves in his treatment <strong>of</strong> intellectual cognition may get lost inthe details and consequently be missed by his interpreters. This is a pity, forScotus’s originality seems to lie more in his general strategy to approach thequestion <strong>of</strong> what it is to think rather than in his detailed treatments <strong>of</strong> specifictopics, for which he is most <strong>of</strong>ten indebted to other thinkers.Scotus’s casual references to the mechanisms <strong>of</strong> intellectual cognitionin his early writings betray a rather crude understanding <strong>of</strong> the nature <strong>of</strong> an act<strong>of</strong> thinking. He initially held that any cognitive act is an action and he evenseemed to have identified acts <strong>of</strong> thinking and intelligible species. 62In just a few years, however, Scotus developed a sophisticatedposition on intellectual cognition. The main elements <strong>of</strong> this position can begathered from his writings dating from the years 1301–05, i.e. his Ordinatio,Reportatio I-A and Quodlibet. In those writings, Scotus made threecharacteristic moves. First, he distinguished between two actions, both <strong>of</strong>which are ordinarily necessary for an act <strong>of</strong> thinking to occur. The first actionis the agent intellect’s act <strong>of</strong> abstraction and production <strong>of</strong> an intelligiblespecies. The second action is the process by which an act <strong>of</strong> thinking isproduced. Second, Scotus distinguished the act <strong>of</strong> thinking from the processby which an act <strong>of</strong> thinking is produced and he consequently argued that anact <strong>of</strong> thinking is a quality rather than an action. Third, he accounted for theintentionality <strong>of</strong> acts <strong>of</strong> thinking by introducing a special relation holdingbetween acts <strong>of</strong> thinking and their objects.I will consider each <strong>of</strong> these three aspects in turn.62 Scotus, Quaest. super Meta., V, q. 12–13, n. 98, OPh III, 638: “[…] cognitio est ingenere actionis […];” Quaestiones in duos libros Perihermeneias: In librum primum, q. 1, n. 14,OPh II, 139: “Ad cuius evidentiam sciendum quod tria se habent secundum ordinem. Primum estspecies intelligibilis, secundum quam intellectus est in actu, quae species est in intellectu sicutactus proprius in propria materia sua. Nam, sicut Commentator ait III De anima, sic se habetintellectus ad species intelligibiles, sicut materia prima se habet ad formas individuales quasrecipit. Secundum est quod est ratio rei quod est ‘quod quid est’ rei […]. Tertium est resparticulariter exsistens sub condicionibus individualibus.”27


3.1 <strong>Two</strong> actions: abstraction and the production <strong>of</strong> an act <strong>of</strong> thinkingScotus distinguished between two actions that must ordinarily takeplace in order for an act <strong>of</strong> thinking to occur. 63 The first action is the agentintellect’s abstraction <strong>of</strong> a form, the so-called “intelligible species,” from asensory image present in the imagination. This action is identical with thepossible intellect’s reception <strong>of</strong> the intelligible species, as the agent intellect’sproduction <strong>of</strong> a species and the possible intellect’s reception <strong>of</strong> a species arejust two descriptions <strong>of</strong> one and the same process. Against Henry <strong>of</strong> Ghentand Godfrey <strong>of</strong> Fontaines, Scotus argued that the agent intellect’s act <strong>of</strong>abstraction is an act <strong>of</strong> producing a form in the possible intellect, becausesuch a form must be present in the intellect prior to the occurrence <strong>of</strong> an act<strong>of</strong> thinking. 64 Scotus’s argument for this claim was based on the assumption(which Scotus took to be self-evident) that the object <strong>of</strong> an act <strong>of</strong> thinking mustbe present to the intellect prior to the occurrence <strong>of</strong> that act <strong>of</strong> thinking as wellas on the further assumption that the object <strong>of</strong> an act <strong>of</strong> thinking (as far asabstractive cognition is concerned) is a universal, i.e. something like “what itis to be a cat” as opposed to “what it is to be this particular cat.” Given thesetwo assumptions, Scotus argued that only a form present in the intellect priorto the occurrence <strong>of</strong> an act <strong>of</strong> thinking could account for the presence <strong>of</strong> theobject prior to the occurrence <strong>of</strong> an act <strong>of</strong> thinking. 65 Since the form present inthe intellect prior to the occurrence <strong>of</strong> an act <strong>of</strong> thinking is the intelligiblespecies produced by the agent intellect, it follows that the agent intellect’sabstraction <strong>of</strong> a species is a pre-requisite for the occurrence <strong>of</strong> an act <strong>of</strong>thinking and must be distinguished from it. 66Scotus regarded the agent intellect’s act <strong>of</strong> abstraction as a real action,i.e. a process that ends up in the production <strong>of</strong> a real quality, the intelligible63 I say “ordinarily” because God can bypass both actions and produce an act <strong>of</strong>thinking immediately in my intellect, as I indicate below. Also, notice that here I am consideringacts <strong>of</strong> abstractive cognition.64 Ord. I, d. 3, p. 3, q. 1, Vat. III, 201–244; Lect. I, d. 3, p. 3, q. 1, Vat. XVI, 325–348;Rep. I-A, d. 3, q. 4 and q. 5, eds. Wolter and Bychkov, 207–220 and 221–232.65 Ord. I, d. 3, p. 3, q. 1, nn. 349–350, Vat III, 210–211. For Scotus’s argument thatonly a form present in the intellect can account for the presence <strong>of</strong> the object as a universal priorto the act <strong>of</strong> thinking, see Ord. I, d. 3, p. 3, q. 1, nn. 352–358, Vat. III, 211–216; Lect. I, d. 3, p. 3,q. 1, nn. 266–273, Vat. XVI, 331–334; Rep. I-A, d. 3, q. 4, nn. 95–97, eds. Wolter and Bychknov,210–211. See King, “Rethinking Representation.”66 Scotus contrasted the agent intellect’s act <strong>of</strong> abstraction to the act <strong>of</strong> thinking properin Ord. I, d. 3, p. 3, q. 1, n. 359–360, Vat. III, 216–218; Rep. I-A, d. 3, q. 4, n. 103, eds. Wolterand Bychknov, 212–213; Quodl., q. 15, n. 14, Vivès XXVI, 145. See also Lect. I, d. 3, p. 3, q. 1, n.275, Vat. XVI, 335.28


species. 67 That real quality, however, is also a representation <strong>of</strong> an extramentalthing, i.e. it has an intentional content. It is that intentional content present inthe intelligible species that contributes to the production <strong>of</strong> an act <strong>of</strong>thinking. 68 For example, my agent intellect abstracts from the sensory image <strong>of</strong>cats the form felinity. That form is a real item present in my mind but it alsopossesses an implicit representational power, i.e. the power to make me thinkabout what it is to be a cat. An example may at least partially clarify whatScotus had in mind. A photo, say the photo <strong>of</strong> a cat, has certain physicalproperties, e.g. it is made <strong>of</strong> paper, ink, etc. To somebody looking at it,however, that photo also conveys a very specific representational content. It isthe photo <strong>of</strong> a cat. That the photo is ordinarily interpreted as the photo <strong>of</strong> a catis not due to a further physical property added to the photo. Rather, this is dueto that very physical object’s power to be interpreted as a representation <strong>of</strong> acat. This power to be interpreted as a representation <strong>of</strong> something else is whatScotus (borrowing the term probably from Henry <strong>of</strong> Ghent) called “objectivebeing” or “being present as something cognizable and represented” or assomething “shining through the intelligible species.” 69 The details <strong>of</strong> thisview—which is quite different from what Aquinas had held—are complicatedand controversial. Suffice it to say that the agent intellect produces a form, andby that production it also makes a certain content potentially present in thepossible intellect.The agent intellect’s production <strong>of</strong> a form representing a certainobject, however, is not sufficient for an act <strong>of</strong> thinking about that object tooccur. I may have as much information about cats as I can gather, but this isnot sufficient for me to perform an act <strong>of</strong> thinking about what it is to be a cat.In addition to the presence <strong>of</strong> the form felinity in my intellect, Scotus arguedthat a separate intervention <strong>of</strong> the intellect is necessary in order for an act <strong>of</strong>67 Ord. I, d. 3, p. 3, q. 1, n. 359, Vat. III, 216: “. . . intellectus agens est mere potentiaactiva . . . ergo potest habere actionem realem. Omnis actio realis habet aliquem terminusrealem.” See also Rep. I-A, d. 3, q. 4, n. 103, eds. Wolter and Bychkov, 212–213.68 Ord. I, d. 3, p. 3, q. 1, n. 386, Vat. III, 235: “Ad quartum dico quod intellectus nontantum patitur realiter ab obiecto reali, imprimente talem speciem realem, sed etiam ab illoobiecto ut relucet in specie patitur passione intentionali: et illa secunda passio est ‘receptiointellectionis’ – quae est ab intelligibili in quantum intelligibile, relucens in specie intelligibili – etillud ‘pati’ est ‘intelligere’ […].”69 See for example Quaest. super Meta. VII, q. 18, n. 44, OPh IV, 348; Ord. I, d. 36, q.unica, nn. 44–46, Vat. VI, 288–289; Ord. I, d. 3, p. 3, q. 1, n. 382, 386, Vat. III, 232, 235. PeterKing has argued that Scotus gradually became dissatisfied with the interpretation <strong>of</strong> mental orintentional existence as a kind <strong>of</strong> diminished existence. See King, “Scotus on Mental Content,”84–85. For Henry <strong>of</strong> Ghent’s use <strong>of</strong> the notion <strong>of</strong> objectively inhering in a cognizer, see SeeHenry <strong>of</strong> Ghent, Quodl. V, q. 14, f. 175rD: “[…] ut secundum hoc omnis cognitio sit (ed.: sic)secundum hoc quod cognitum secundum essentiam cogniti sit in cognoscente, et hoc non ut insubiecto cui inhaeret formaliter sed ut in concipiente obiective.”29


thinking about what it is to be a cat to occur. 70 Both the species and theintellect must act as efficient causes in order for an act <strong>of</strong> thinking about acertain thing to occur. Scotus argued that the species and the intellectcollaborate in the production <strong>of</strong> an act <strong>of</strong> thinking in a special way, which helikened to the collaboration <strong>of</strong> a man and a woman in the generation <strong>of</strong> achild. 71What should be stressed is Scotus’s clear distinction between twoactions involved in the production <strong>of</strong> an act <strong>of</strong> thinking, i.e. the act <strong>of</strong>abstraction and the production <strong>of</strong> an act <strong>of</strong> thinking. 72 These are two distinctcausal processes, and more specifically two actions, which are identified bydistinct agents and distinct terms. The act <strong>of</strong> abstraction is caused by the agentintellect and the sensory image (the so-called “phantasm”). Its term is a mentalquality, i.e. the intelligible species. By contrast, the formation <strong>of</strong> an act <strong>of</strong>thinking is caused by the intelligible species and the intellect after theabstraction <strong>of</strong> the species. The product <strong>of</strong> that second process is the act <strong>of</strong>thinking proper. As I will show, Scotus argued that the act <strong>of</strong> thinking is amental quality, too.By clearly distinguishing between two actions involved in the act <strong>of</strong>thinking and by claiming that the intellect must play the role <strong>of</strong> an efficientcause not just in the act <strong>of</strong> abstraction but also in the production <strong>of</strong> an act <strong>of</strong>thinking, Scotus managed to lay the foundation for the distinction betweendispositional and occurrent knowledge. Only when the second process occursdoes an act <strong>of</strong> occurrent knowledge occur, i.e. do I actually think aboutsomething. When only the process <strong>of</strong> abstraction and reception <strong>of</strong> a formoccurs, some information is memorized and stored in the intellect, but noactual thought follows. This is the situation I experience when I know what itis to be a cat but I do not think about it.3.2. Acts <strong>of</strong> thinking as qualitiesScotus’s most characteristic insight, however, is not his distinctionbetween the two actions involved in the production <strong>of</strong> an act <strong>of</strong> thinking. As I70 Ord. I, d. 3, p. 3, q. 2, Vat. III, 245–330; Lect. I, d. 3, p. 3, q. 2–3, Vat. XVI, 349–395;Quodl., q. 15, nn. 7–9, Vivès XXVI, 137–141. It is clear that the act <strong>of</strong> thinking is distinct from theact <strong>of</strong> abstraction carried out by the agent intellect. It is an open question, however, whether theact <strong>of</strong> thinking itself is performed by the agent intellect, the possible intellect or both the agentand the possible intellect. Scotus considered each <strong>of</strong> these possibilities in Quodl., q. 15, nn. 13–20, Vivès XXVI, 141–153.71 Scotus argued that the intellect plays the main role as an efficient cause <strong>of</strong> an act <strong>of</strong>thinking. He never held, however, that the intellect could produce an act <strong>of</strong> thinking without thecollaboration <strong>of</strong> the form <strong>of</strong> the object. See Ord. I, d. 3, p. 3, q. 3, Vat. III, 330–338; Quodl., q.15, n. 10, Vivès XXVI, 142–143.72 See above, note 66.30


have shown above, Aquinas had already distinguished the act <strong>of</strong> abstractionfrom the act <strong>of</strong> thinking proper. Admittedly, Aquinas had held that, once anact <strong>of</strong> abstraction is complete and once an intelligible species is present in theintellect in full actuality, an act <strong>of</strong> thinking necessarily follows, i.e. theintellect is necessarily activated and cannot refrain from actually thinkingabout something. By contrast, Scotus clearly distinguished between theintellect’s being made actual by the reception <strong>of</strong> a species and the intellect’sacting as an efficient cause in the production <strong>of</strong> an act <strong>of</strong> thinking. This is not,however, the main difference between Aquinas’s and Scotus’s accounts <strong>of</strong>thinking. Rather, Scotus’s most typical claim was that both the act <strong>of</strong>abstraction and the successive act carried out by the intellect and the speciestogether must be distinguished from the act <strong>of</strong> thinking. That second processresults in an act <strong>of</strong> thinking but is not itself an act <strong>of</strong> thinking. 73The distinction between an act <strong>of</strong> thinking and the process consistingin the joint action <strong>of</strong> the intellect and an intelligible species is a consequence<strong>of</strong> Scotus’s general claim that acts <strong>of</strong> thinking are neither actions nor passions.Scotus’s argument for that claim was that actions and passions are necessarilyrelated to the term they bring about. For example, fire’s action <strong>of</strong> heating isnecessarily related to what it produces, e.g. a hot kettle. Similarly, a kettle’spassion <strong>of</strong> being heated is necessarily related to its term, i.e. that kettle’s beinghot. By definition, an action produces something and a passion entails theproduction <strong>of</strong> something. There can be no action or passion if a term is notproduced by that very action or passion. Scotus, however, remarked that anact <strong>of</strong> thinking produces nothing at all apart from itself. Rather, an act <strong>of</strong>thinking is an ultimate end, which is carried out for the sake <strong>of</strong> itself and notfor the sake <strong>of</strong> anything else. It is true that sometimes something is producedby acts <strong>of</strong> thinking, i.e. a habit. For example, if I repeatedly think about what itis to be a cat, it becomes easy for me to entertain that act because I get used toperforming it. This, however, is an accidental result <strong>of</strong> my act <strong>of</strong> thinking. Acertain act <strong>of</strong> thinking is essentially the same act even though it does notproduce any habit (as with acts <strong>of</strong> thinking that are performed onlyoccationally.) In any case, it is clear that an act <strong>of</strong> thinking does not produceits object, because what I think about is presupposed, not produced, by myact <strong>of</strong> thinking about it. 7473 More precisely, an act <strong>of</strong> thinking is what Scotus calls the “formal term” <strong>of</strong> theprocess carried out by the intellect and the species together. The proper term <strong>of</strong> that process is thewhole constituted by the intellect thinking about something or an individual person thinkingabout something. See Rep. I-A, d. 3, q. 6, nn. 183–184, eds. Wolter and Bychkov, 239.74 Rep. I-A, d. 3, q. 6, n. 171, eds. Wolter and Bychkov, 235–236: “Item, de actione etpassione probatur idem [scil., quod intellectio non est actio vel passio]: nam actio et passionecessario sunt alicuius termini accipientis esse per actionem et passionem; quia non est31


So what sort <strong>of</strong> thing is an act <strong>of</strong> thinking, if it is neither an action nora passion? Assuming that all things belong to one <strong>of</strong> the ten Aristoteliancategories, Scotus proceeded by process <strong>of</strong> elimination. 75 Apart from actionsand passions, he held that there are only two plausible candidates. First, anact <strong>of</strong> thinking may be a relation. Second, an act <strong>of</strong> thinking may be a quality.Scotus had three arguments to demonstrate that in an act <strong>of</strong> thinkingthere is a non-relative feature that cannot be reduced to a relation, and that, asa consequence, an act <strong>of</strong> thinking is not a relation.Scotus’s first argument was based on the view that an act <strong>of</strong> thinkingis the ultimate perfection <strong>of</strong> a human being. According to Scotus, however,the ultimate perfection <strong>of</strong> a human being could not be a relation. Therefore,an act <strong>of</strong> thinking is not a relation. The claim that an act <strong>of</strong> thinking is theultimate perfection <strong>of</strong> a human being was commonly agreed on. The basicidea was that the activity <strong>of</strong> thinking is what a human being is made for andwhat satisfies our deepest needs. We were born in order to think. This isconfirmed by the fact that human nature will be perfected in the final unionwith God in the beatific vision, which is (at least partially) an intellectual act,and thus may be considered as a very special act <strong>of</strong> thinking. 76 Strangelyenough, Scotus did not spend much time to support the minor premise <strong>of</strong> thisargument, according to which the ultimate perfection <strong>of</strong> a human beingcannot be a relative item. Presumably, Scotus’s point was based on the remarkthat a relative item is identified by its term and is consequently essentiallydependent on that term’s existence. For example, the relation <strong>of</strong> paternity isgrounded in a father and directed at a child. If no child is generated, there isno relation <strong>of</strong> paternity. But then, if a human being’s ultimate perfection werea relation, a human being’s ultimate perfection would be essentiallydependent on something else, i.e. its term. Thus, the ultimate perfection <strong>of</strong> ahuman being would not be ultimate, because it would in turn depend on theintelligibile quod sit calefactio et quod nullius ulterioris termini, scilicet quod nihil accipiatcalorem per eam; sed operationes sunt termini ultimi quibus nihil ulterius accipit esse, quia suntfines, I Ethicorum et IX Metaphysicae. Obiectum vero operationis ad quod terminatur operationon accipit esse per eam, sed praesupponitur operationi, quia sunt fines operantis, ut dictum est;ergo etc.” See also Ord., d. 27, q. 1–3, n. 55, Vat. VI, 86: “[…] intellectio non est actio productivaalicuius termini: tunc enim incompossibile esset intelligere eam esse, et non esse termini, sicutincompossibile est intelligere calefactionem esse et non esse calorem ad quem sit calefaction.Non est autem impossibile intelligere intellectionem in se, non intelligendo quod sit alicuiustermini ut producti per ipsam.”75 Quodl. q. 13, n. 25, Vivès XXV, 570–571; Rep. I-A, q. 6, nn. 169–237, eds. Wolterand Bychkov, 234–237.76 See for example Aquinas, Sent. I, d. 35, q. 1, a. 5, ad 4; Sent IV, d. 49, q. 3, a. 2; DePot., q. 5, a. 5, ad 14; De malo, q. 1, a. 5; ST I-II, q. 3, a. 2; ST I-II, q. 49, a. 3, ad 1.32


existence <strong>of</strong> its term. Scotus held that this argument applied to actions andpassions as well. 77Scotus’s second and third arguments are possibly more interesting.Scotus’s second argument that in any act <strong>of</strong> thinking there is anirreducible non-relative feature is based on the view that two things becomenewly related to each other if and only if a new non-relative item is acquiredby either or both <strong>of</strong> them. For example, a chair becomes similar in color to awall only if the chair is colored like the wall or the wall is colored like thechair or both the chair and the wall are colored in the same way. Now, an act<strong>of</strong> thinking can occur without the reception <strong>of</strong> a new form either in theintellect or in the thing thought about. For example, suppose that I alreadyknow what it is to be a cat; I do not have to acquire any new information inorder to actually think about what it is to be a cat. My intellect must acquire anew form only when it is in essential potency with respect to the knowledge<strong>of</strong> what it is to be a cat, i.e. when I am ignorant <strong>of</strong> what it is to be a cat. Bycontrast, when I know what it is to be a cat but I do not think about cats, myintellect is in a state <strong>of</strong> accidental potency, i.e. it can perform an act <strong>of</strong>thinking about what it is to be a cat without acquiring any new form.Similarly, cats do not acquire a new form when I think about what it is to be acat. Since a new act <strong>of</strong> thinking can be brought about without the acquisition<strong>of</strong> a new form in the intellect, it follows that acts <strong>of</strong> thinking are not relations:The main conclusion [namely, that in all intellection and, in general,for any activity we are speaking <strong>of</strong> here, there is some non-relative entity] isproved secondarily in this fashion: A relation proper is not new unless therebe in either the subject or the term some prior absolute entity that is new. Butan activity can be new without any other prior absolute being present ineither the operator himself or in the term <strong>of</strong> the activity. Therefore the activityis not precisely a relation proper. Hence [it is something non-relative]… Pro<strong>of</strong><strong>of</strong> the first part <strong>of</strong> the minor: A subject which passes from accidental potencyto act does not receive a new form prior to the activity itself; otherwise itwould have been in essential, not accidental, potency. The second part <strong>of</strong> theminor is manifest, for it is obvious that something visible does not acquireanything absolute by the fact that it is actually seen; neither does anintelligible object, and the same is true <strong>of</strong> other activities.7877 Scotus, Quodl., q. 13, nn. 3–4, Vivès XXV, 508–509; Rep. I-A, d. 3, q. 6, n. 169, eds.Wolter and Bychkov, 234–235.78 Scotus, Quodl., q. 13, n. 4, Vivès XXV, 509: “Secundo probatur conclusio principalis[scil., quod in omni intellectione et generaliter operatione quacumque de qua loquimur, estaliqua entitas absoluta] sic. Relatio proprie dicta non est nova sine novitate alicuius absolutiprioris, et hoc in subiecto vel in termino. Operatio autem potest esse nova sine novitatecuiuscumque alterius prioris absoluti in ipso operante, sine etiam cuiuscumque alterius absolutinovitate in termino. Igitur operatio non est praecise relatio proprie accipiendo relationem. Igituretc. […] Minor probatur quantum ad primam partem, quia illud quod exit de potentia accidentali33


This is a remarkable argument. It is based on the key fact that thepassage from dispositional to occurrent knowledge takes place without theacquisition <strong>of</strong> any new form in the intellect. The apparent technicality <strong>of</strong>Scotus’s point should not obscure the novelty <strong>of</strong> his position. Scotus wasfocusing on the weak point <strong>of</strong> the Aristotelian account <strong>of</strong> thinking as a changeor process. As scholars <strong>of</strong> Aristotle have noticed, the passage fromdispositional to occurrent knowledge (which I labeled “the problem <strong>of</strong>occurrent thought”) constituted the breaking point <strong>of</strong> the view that thinking isa change since at least Aristotle’s times. As I have showed above, Aquinas hadstruggled to find a solution to this problem. He introduced the suspect notion<strong>of</strong> a species being present in the intellect in incomplete actuality just for thatreason. By contrast, Scotus took the peculiar character <strong>of</strong> the passage fromdispositional to occurrent knowledge (a “change” without the acquisition <strong>of</strong> anew form) as the starting point to investigate the nature <strong>of</strong> an act <strong>of</strong> thinking.Scotus’s third argument in support <strong>of</strong> his claim that an act <strong>of</strong> thinkingis not a relation was based on the fact that an act <strong>of</strong> thinking is itself related toits object. For example, my act <strong>of</strong> thinking about what it is to be a cat isrelated to what it is to be a cat, i.e. (according to Scotus) the essence <strong>of</strong> cats.Now it was a common assumption that only a non-relative item can be relatedto something else, because only a non-relative item can play the role <strong>of</strong> thefoundation <strong>of</strong> a relation. For example, the relation <strong>of</strong> paternity holdingbetween a father and his child is grounded in a non-relative feature pertainingto the father, i.e., presumably, his power to procreate. The father’s power toprocreate must be interpreted as a non-relative item in order to exclude thepossibility <strong>of</strong> an infinite regress. Acts <strong>of</strong> thinking, however, are related to theirobjects. It follows that they are not relations. 79Scotus’s arguments that acts <strong>of</strong> thinking are neither relations noractions or passions are remarkable especially because they reveal hiscommitment to two claims that Aquinas had been forced to reject. In hisargument that acts <strong>of</strong> thinking are not actions or passions, Scotus assumed thatacts <strong>of</strong> thinking do not produce anything (unless, accidentally, a habit). Thisassumption is intuitively uncontroversial. Unlike actions such as building orad actum non recipit aliquam formam novam priorem ipsa operatione, quia tunc non fuisset priusin potentia accidentali sed essentiali. Secunda pars minoris est manifesta. Patet enim quod nihilasbolutum advenit visibili quando videtur actu nec intelligibili quando intelligitur actu, etconsimiliter de aliis.” The English translation is taken, with a few modifications, from John DunsScotus, God and Creatures. The Quodlibetal Questions, translated with an Introduction, Notesand Glossary by F. Alluntis and A. B. Wolter (Princeton and London: Princeton <strong>University</strong> Press,1975), 286–287.79 Quodl., q. 13, n. 5, Vivès XXV, 509; Rep. I-A, d. 3, q. 6, n. 170, eds. Wolter andBychkov, 235.34


painting, acts <strong>of</strong> thinking do not issue in a result separate from their veryexercise. Aquinas, however, had rejected precisely that claim in his secondaccount <strong>of</strong> acts <strong>of</strong> thinking as self-contained actions with internal termsproduced by those very acts. Similarly, in his third argument that acts <strong>of</strong>thinking are not relations, Scotus assumed that acts <strong>of</strong> thinking areimmediately related to their objects. Again, this assumption is intuitivelynoncontroversial. My act <strong>of</strong> thinking about what it is to be a cat is about whatit is to be a cat, so it is related to it. As I have shown, however, Aquinas hadrejected precisely that claim in both <strong>of</strong> his accounts <strong>of</strong> thinking as a selfcontainedaction.Scotus’s general strategy can be easily perceived behind thetechnicality <strong>of</strong> his arguments. Aquinas’s commitment to the view that acts <strong>of</strong>thinking are actions forced him to embrace some implausible conclusions, i.e.that acts <strong>of</strong> thinking are not related to their objects or that they produce theirown terms. By contrast, Scotus took the implausibility <strong>of</strong> these conclusions asevidence that Aquinas’s approach was wrong-headed. In order to avoid thoseimplausible positions, the claim that acts <strong>of</strong> thinking are relative items andmore specifically that they are actions should be rejected.Since acts <strong>of</strong> thinking are neither relations nor actions or passions,Scotus concluded that they are qualities. Specifically, he argued that they arein the first <strong>of</strong> the four species <strong>of</strong> qualities Aristotle had distinguished in theeighth chapter <strong>of</strong> his Categories. Since Aristotle sorted out the qualitiesbelonging to the first species into habits such as virtues and more fleetingconditions such as heat, cold, disease and health, it seems likely that Scotusregarded acts <strong>of</strong> thinking as those fleeting dispositions (diatheseis, affectiones),which can be easily acquired or lost. 80Scotus seems to have been aware <strong>of</strong> the novelty <strong>of</strong> this claim.According to Aquinas and to the standard Aristotelian theory, acts <strong>of</strong> thinkingare actions similar to fire’s action <strong>of</strong> heating. By contrast, Scotus likened theact <strong>of</strong> thinking to heat, not to the action <strong>of</strong> heating or the passion <strong>of</strong> beingheated. This position clashed with the intuition that to think is something that Iperform, i.e. something I do. By contrast, according to Scotus what I performis the action that results in an act <strong>of</strong> thinking. By itself, however, an act <strong>of</strong>80 Rep. I-A, d. 3, q. 6, nn. 175–176, eds. Wolter and Bychkov, 237: “Restat ergonecessario concedere quod istae operationes sint qualitates, cum non sint nihil nec in aliquogenere, sicut superius est probatum. Sed non sunt de secunda specie qualitatis, quia non suntnaturalis potentia vel impotentia; nec de tertia vel quarta specie, quia istae tantum conveniuntcorporalibus […]. Relinquitur ergo quod operationes sunt in prima specie qualitatis, etuniversaliter omnis perfectio naturae spiritualis, si non sit substantia eius—sive sit in fieri, sive sitpermanens et in facto esse—est in prima specie qualitatis.” See also Quodl., q. 13, n. 15, VivèsXXV, 570–571. For Aristotle’s text, see Cat. 8, 8b26–9a4.35


thinking is not something I perform, but something I have, just as I have thequality heat or the quality cold. This claim is striking, because at first sightthere seems to be little in common between a quality such as heat or cold andan act <strong>of</strong> thinking, whereas there seems to be much in common between anaction such as heating and cooling and an act <strong>of</strong> thinking.Scotus admitted that acts <strong>of</strong> thinking belong to a special sort <strong>of</strong>qualities called “activities” (operationes). In calling acts <strong>of</strong> thinking“activities,” Scotus was just following Aristotle and was in agreement withAquinas. There is, however, a fundamental difference between Scotus andAquinas. As I have indicated above, Aquinas regarded activities as genuineactions, albeit self-contained and not transitive. Scotus, by contrast, held thatactivities are not actions but qualities. He recognized, however, that activitiesmight be confused with actions such as heating, on the one hand, and withsome other impermanent qualities such as light, on the other hand. In order toclafity this issue, Scotus listed three conditions that should be taken intoaccount when identifying something as an action, an impermanent quality oran activity.The first condition is that <strong>of</strong> being impermanent or in fieri, i.e. <strong>of</strong>existing only as long as an agent carries out its action. For example, the action<strong>of</strong> heating exists only as long as fire carries it out. Also, light exists only aslong as a source <strong>of</strong> a light source performs the action <strong>of</strong> illuminating.Similarly, an act <strong>of</strong> thinking exists only as long as its causes (ordinarily, anintellect and an intelligible species) carry out their action <strong>of</strong> producing it. Assoon as the agent ceases to perform its action, the action <strong>of</strong> heating, thequality <strong>of</strong> being illuminated and the act <strong>of</strong> thinking cease to exist.The second condition is that <strong>of</strong> having a term about which (circaquem) the action or quality occurs. This term is the object <strong>of</strong> the action orquality. For example, fire’s act <strong>of</strong> heating is directed at or about a kettle.Similarly, my act <strong>of</strong> thinking about what it is to be a cat is directed at or aboutwhat it is to be a cat.The third condition is that <strong>of</strong> having a term towards which (ad quem)the action is directed. This term is produced by that action. For example, fire’sact <strong>of</strong> heating produced a hot kettle.Only items belonging to the category <strong>of</strong> action satisfy all threeconditions. Actions are impermanent or in fieri, have a term about which theyare performed and produce something. By contrast, impermanent qualitiessuch as light only satisfy the first condition. Light exists only as long as a lightsource illuminates. But light does not necessarily require a subject in which tobe received and light produces nothing. Finally, acts <strong>of</strong> thinking satisfy boththe first and the second condition, but not the third. First, acts <strong>of</strong> thinking36


exists only as long as the intellect and a species in the intellect perform theirconcurrent action <strong>of</strong> producing such an act. When either I have noinformation about cats or I have completely forgotten everything about cats, Ido not and cannot think about what it is to be a cat. Also, when I know whatit is to be a cat but I do not turn my intellect towards that information, no act<strong>of</strong> thinking about what it is to be a cat occurs. Second, just like actions, acts <strong>of</strong>thinking are necessarily about an object. Unlike actions, however, activitiessuch as acts <strong>of</strong> thinking produce nothing (unless, accidentally, a habit). 81Admittedly, Aristotle had called activities such as thinking selfcontainedactions and he contrasted them to transitive actions such asbuilding and heating. Scotus, however, stated that this should not beinterpreted as a distinction between two kinds <strong>of</strong> actions (self-contained andtransitive, respectively). Rather, Aristotle’s claim should be regarded as adistinction between two senses <strong>of</strong> the word “action.” In the first sense, theword “action” refers to genuine items belonging to the category <strong>of</strong> action,such as building and heating. In the second sense, the word “action” refers toactivities such as thinking and perceiving, which, although they may beconfused with actions, are nevertheless items in the category <strong>of</strong> quality. Selfcontainedactions, accordingly, are qualities, not actions. 823.3. Scotus on the intentionality <strong>of</strong> acts <strong>of</strong> thinkingStill, it may be suspected that Scotus’s claim that acts <strong>of</strong> thinking arenot actions but qualities amounts to little more than a local disagreement withAquinas and other thinkers concerning a negligible issue. That this is not thecase, however, may be appreciated when the issue <strong>of</strong> the intentionality <strong>of</strong> acts<strong>of</strong> thinking is taken into account.Since acts <strong>of</strong> thinking are in themselves non-relative items, Scotuscould contend that they are directly related to their objects. Remember thatthis is what Aquinas could not claim. According to Aquinas, acts <strong>of</strong> thinkingare actions that either are not related to their objects or are directly related tothe concepts they produced but not to the external things they are supposed tobe about. This was a consequence <strong>of</strong> Aquinas’s view that acts <strong>of</strong> thinking areself-contained actions. A self-contained action is directed at either nothingapart from itself (in Aquinas’s first account) or its own product (in Aquinas’s81 Quodl. q. 13, n. 27, Vivès XXV, 575; Rep. I-A, d. 3, q. 6, n. 191, eds. Wolter andBychkov, 241–242. For a previous attempt to distinguish activities from actions and impermanentqualities, see Ord. I, d. 3, p. 3, q. 4, nn. 601–603, Vat. III, 354–356.82 Quodl. q. 13, n. 26, Vivès XXV, 571, and especially n. 27, Vivès XXV, 575: “Et itaista distinctio actionis sic intellecta in transeuntem et immanentem non est generis in species, sedvocis in significationes. Nam actio transiens est vera actio de genere actionis, actio immanens estqualitas, sed aequivoce dicitur actio propter conditiones praedictas.”37


second account). In neither case is there any room for a self-contained actionto be directed at something external. As a consequence, the link between anact <strong>of</strong> thinking and its object was at best indirect, according to Aquinas. Thekey feature that explained intentionality was not something pertaining to anact <strong>of</strong> thinking. Rather, intentionality was explained by the form whosepresence in the intellect triggered an act <strong>of</strong> thinking. In other words, theintelligible species and the agent intellect’s act <strong>of</strong> abstraction were responsiblefor intentionality. Thus, acts <strong>of</strong> thinking did not play any role in accounting forintentionality. For example, my act <strong>of</strong> thinking about what it is to be a cat isabout the essence <strong>of</strong> cats, according to Aquinas, because it is produced by theintellect when the form felinity is abstracted by the agent intellect andreceived in the possible intellect. Consequently, Aquinas held thatintentionality is explained by the causal story linking an object to the intellectby way <strong>of</strong> form abstraction and form reception. That causal relation goes fromthe extramental thing to the intellect, not the other way around.By contrast, Scotus linked acts <strong>of</strong> thinking directly to their objects, i.e.to extramental things. He could achieve that result because he regarded acts<strong>of</strong> thinking as qualities, i.e. non-relative items, which can play the role <strong>of</strong>direct foundations for relations directed at extramental things. 83But there is more. Not only did Scotus hold that the intentionality <strong>of</strong>acts <strong>of</strong> thinking is accounted for by a feature pertaining to those actsthemselves, i.e. by their being related to their objects. At least in a couple <strong>of</strong>passages, Scotus even argued that the intentionality <strong>of</strong> acts <strong>of</strong> thinking isexplained only by their relation to their objects. Specifically, the presence <strong>of</strong> acertain form in the intellect prior to an act <strong>of</strong> thinking does not play anyessential role in explaining the intentionality <strong>of</strong> that act. The presence <strong>of</strong> acertain species in my intellect is neither a necessary nor a sufficient conditionfor a certain act’s being about a certain thing. For example, my act <strong>of</strong> thinkingabout what it is a cat is about the essence <strong>of</strong> cats because it is directly relatedto the essence <strong>of</strong> cats, not because my intellect has previously received theform felinity. Scotus admitted that in most cases my intellect must havereceived such a form prior to the actual occurrence <strong>of</strong> a thought. The priorreception <strong>of</strong> a form, however, is necessary only in order to account for theuniversality <strong>of</strong> a thought (e.g. for the fact that I think about what it is to be a83 Rep. I-A, d. 3, q. 6, n. 170, eds. Wolter and Bychkov, 235: “Minor [scil., quodintellectio et omnis operatio est ad aliquid] patet per Philosophum, V Metaphysicae, dicentemoperationem [pro: scientiam?] dici relative ad obiectum, ut mensuratum ad mensuram, quiaobiectum est mensura operationis; unde si scientia dicatur ad aliquid, multo magis operatio etactus scientiae quae immediatius respiciunt obiectum quam habitus; immo habitus non respicitobiectum nisi mediante actu.” Scotus analyzed the act <strong>of</strong> thinking’s role as the foundation <strong>of</strong> arelation directed at its object in Quodl., q. 13, nn. 6–7 and nn. 11–14, Vivès XXV, 525–541.38


cat rather than about what it is to be this or that individual cat). The presence<strong>of</strong> that form, however, does not play an essential role in explaining why myact is about what it is about.Scotus demonstrated this point by a straightforward argument. Sinceacts <strong>of</strong> thinking are non-relative items, they can be created immediately byGod. Thus, God can create my act <strong>of</strong> thinking about what it is a cat eventhough I have no form felinity in my intellect. Nevertheless, my act <strong>of</strong> thinkingwould still be about cats, not about God, even if God and not cats were thecause <strong>of</strong> my act <strong>of</strong> thinking about cats. 84The upshot <strong>of</strong> all this is that according to Scotus intentionality is arelation holding between an act <strong>of</strong> thinking and its object, which cannot beaccounted for by the causal story linking the object to the intellect but shouldrather be assumed as a primitive relation linking an act <strong>of</strong> thinking to itsobject.So what sort <strong>of</strong> relation is intentionality, according to Scotus? Here itis necessary to distinguish two separate issues. First, one must consider thenature <strong>of</strong> the relation linking an act <strong>of</strong> thinking to its object. Second, one mustfocus on the relationship between the intentional relation itself and an act <strong>of</strong>thinking.Concerning the first issue, Scotus was willing to consider theintentional relation holding between an act <strong>of</strong> thinking and its object as arelation <strong>of</strong> likeness (similitudo). Unlike Aquinas, however, he stressed thatsuch a likeness cannot be accounted for as the sharing <strong>of</strong> a common form. Anact <strong>of</strong> thinking is a likeness <strong>of</strong> its object not because it has the same form <strong>of</strong> itsobject but because it is an “imitation” (imitatio) <strong>of</strong> its object, just as somethingmodeled against a certain idea is an imitation <strong>of</strong> that idea. 85 Admittedly, thisamounts to little more than saying that the intentional relation holdingbetween an act <strong>of</strong> thinking and its object is a sui generis relation, whichshould be assumed as primitive. Acts <strong>of</strong> thinking are about their objects justbecause <strong>of</strong> the kind <strong>of</strong> things they are. Scotus also stressed that such a relationcannot be reduced to any the four Aristotelian cause. An object is not theformal, material, efficient or final cause <strong>of</strong> the act <strong>of</strong> thinking that is about thatobject. 86 Consequently, intentionality must be assumed as a primitive relationthat cannot be explained in terms <strong>of</strong> the causal relations considered within theframework <strong>of</strong> natural philosophy.84 Ord. I, d. 3, p. 3, q. 2, nn. 477–479, Vat. III, 285–286. See also Lect. I, d. 3, p. 3, n.392, Vat. XVI, 377.85 Quodl., q. 13, n. 12, Vivès XXV, 526.86 Aquinas maintained that the object is the final cause <strong>of</strong> the act <strong>of</strong> thinking. Seeabove, note 54.39


Scotus, however, attempted to give a more positive description <strong>of</strong> theintentional relation holding between an act <strong>of</strong> thinking and its object. Aristotlehad already mentioned a class <strong>of</strong> relations involving “the measure and themeasured” 87 . He had illustrated that class <strong>of</strong> relations by making reference tothe relation holding between something known (playing the role <strong>of</strong> themeasure) and knowledge (playing the role <strong>of</strong> the measured). 88 The idea wasthat, if an object o acquires a relation R to a knower k, no real change occursin o. This implies that the relation R holding between o and k is not real. Theexplanation for this is that the relation R is not founded on any real feature <strong>of</strong>o that o lacked when it was not related to k by R and that o acquired when itbecame related to k by R. Thus, when I know a certain thing, that thing doesnot acquire any real feature and does not undergo any real change. Bycontrast, if a knower k acquires a relation R i to an object o, some real changeoccurs in o. This implies that the relation R i holding between k and o is real.The explanation for this is that the relation R i is founded on a real feature <strong>of</strong> k,which k lacked when it was not related to o by R i and acquired when itbecame related to o by R i .These relations were called “non-mutual,” because one <strong>of</strong> them is realand the other one is not. By contrast, mutual relations are either both real orboth non-real. For example, the relation holding between a father and a son ismutual, because there is a corresponding real relation holding between theson and the father.Aristotle had developed this framework to account for the relationholding between dispositional knowledge and its objects. Scotus applied it tothe relation holding between occurrent knowledge and its objects, i.e. acts <strong>of</strong>thinking and what they are about. When I think about something, no realfeature is acquired by the object <strong>of</strong> my act <strong>of</strong> thinking; by contrast, I acquire areal feature, i.e. an act <strong>of</strong> thinking, which is a quality present in the mind butnevertheless real. I possess that mental quality only as long as I actually thinkabout a certain thing. Thus, to think makes a difference to me but not to what Iam thinking about. The intentional relation linking my act <strong>of</strong> thinking to what Iam thinking about is a non-mutual relation <strong>of</strong> the same kind as the relationlinking knowledge to what is known and what is measured to what measuresit.87 Quodl., q. 13, nn. 11–12 (Vivès XXV, 525–526). In that passage, Scotus distinguishedthe measure/measured relation from another kind <strong>of</strong> relation, which he called “relatioattingentiae.” He clarified, however, that the relatio attingentiae pertains only to acts <strong>of</strong> intuitivecognition. See ibid., n. 14 (Vivès XXV, 540). Since I focus on abstractive cognition, I do not takethe relatio attingentiae into account.88 Meta. V, 15, 1021a26–b3; Meta. X, 1, 1053a31–b3; Cat. 7, 6b1–6. See Henninger,Relations, 6–8.40


Concerning the second issue, as I have said, Scotus held that theintentional relation holding between an act <strong>of</strong> thinking and its object is arelation founded in an act <strong>of</strong> thinking and directed at its object as its term.Since acts <strong>of</strong> thinking are non-relative items, the intentional relation holdingbetween an act and its object cannot be part <strong>of</strong> the essence <strong>of</strong> an act <strong>of</strong>thinking. Thus, the link between an act <strong>of</strong> thinking and its object is not anessential property <strong>of</strong> an act <strong>of</strong> thinking. As a consequence, if an act <strong>of</strong> thinkingis an item belonging to just one category (as it is likely to be), it follows that anact <strong>of</strong> thinking and its relation to its object are two distinct items belonging totwo distinct categories:From this it follows that either the act <strong>of</strong> thinking is not somethingper se one pertaining to a single genus, or else it does not include per se thetwo elements which were proved to concur in it [scil., an absolute and arelative element]. But the first article […] seems to establish that the absoluteelement is included essentially. Consequently, the act does not appear to beessentially relative in the sense <strong>of</strong> including the relation per se.89Accordingly, Scotus held that, if we were able to define acts <strong>of</strong>thinking in precise terms, there would be no need to include in theirdefinitions any mention <strong>of</strong> their objects. Thus, it would be possible to definemy act <strong>of</strong> thinking about what it is to be a cat without mentioning cats at all.As a matter <strong>of</strong> fact, however, this is not the case. We are not able to provideprecise definitions <strong>of</strong> acts <strong>of</strong> thinking, and as a consequence we end upidentifying acts <strong>of</strong> thinking thanks to their objects. 90Scotus, however, stated that the intentional relation holding betweenan act <strong>of</strong> thinking and its object, even though it is not part <strong>of</strong> the essence <strong>of</strong>that act <strong>of</strong> thinking, pertains to that act <strong>of</strong> thinking necessarily. Thus, it isimpossible for a certain act <strong>of</strong> thinking to exist and not to be about the objectis it about. For example, my act <strong>of</strong> thinking about what it is to be a cat isnecessarily about the essence <strong>of</strong> cats, even though at least in principle it maybe defined without ever mentioning the essence <strong>of</strong> cats. The relation betweenan act <strong>of</strong> thinking and its object can be described as an asymmetric relation <strong>of</strong>89 Quodl., q. 13, n. 24, Vivès XXV, 569: “Ex his sequitur quod actus cognoscendi velnon est aliquid per se unum unius generis vel non per se includit illa duo, quae probata suntconcurrere [scil., aliquid absolutum et relatio]. Videtur autem probatum in primo articulo quodessentialiter includat absolutum […]. Igitur videtur quod actus talis non sit essentialiter relativus,sicut per se includens relationem.” The English translation is taken, with some modifications, fromJohn Duns Scotus, God and Creatures, trans. Alluntis and Wolter, 303–304.90 Quodl., q. 13, n. 30, Vivès XXV, 577. Scotus also considered an alternative view,according to which the definition <strong>of</strong> an act <strong>of</strong> thinking must include a reference to its object as tosomething extrinsic but nevertheless necessary. See ibid., n. 31, Vivès XXV, 577–578.41


mensurability (i.e., the act <strong>of</strong> thinking is measured by its object) ordependence (i.e. the act <strong>of</strong> thinking depends on its object). 91The claim that some feature may pertain to a certain subjectnecessarily but not essentially may sound surprising. Nevertheless, it was astandard Aristotelian view. For example, properties such as the ability to laughwere thought to pertain necessarily but not essentially to human beings. If youare a human being, necessarily you are able to laugh. But if I have to definewhat a human being is, I do not have to include the ability to laugh among theessential features <strong>of</strong> human beings. Just as the ability to laugh in humanbeings, the intentional relation to an object is not part <strong>of</strong> what an act <strong>of</strong>thinking is, but it necessarily pertains to it. In this respect, the relation betweenan act <strong>of</strong> thinking and its object seems to be akin to the relation between acreature and God. Even though the relation between a creature and God is notpart <strong>of</strong> the essence <strong>of</strong> a creature, no creature could exist if it did not dependon God. Therefore, that dependence relation pertains to a creature necessarilybut not essentially. Similarly, the relation to an object is not part <strong>of</strong> theessence <strong>of</strong> an act <strong>of</strong> thinking is. Without that measure or dependence relation,however, no act <strong>of</strong> thinking could exist. Therefore, the relation to a certainobject pertains to a certain act <strong>of</strong> thinking necessarily but not essentially. 92***Scotus’s answer to the three questions I have mentioned at thebeginning <strong>of</strong> this paper should now be clear.(1) An act <strong>of</strong> thinking is a quality. It is, admittedly, a special kind, i.e.an impermanent quality that requires the constant action <strong>of</strong> its causes to bekept into existence. And it is a quality that is about something, i.e. its object.Nevertheless, a quality it is, not an action. Thus, an act <strong>of</strong> thinking is notsomething that I do but something that I have. In the current order <strong>of</strong> things,my intellect and a form present in my intellect do perform the process thatresults in an act <strong>of</strong> thinking. God, however, may bypass both my intellect andthe form present in my intellect and create an act <strong>of</strong> thinking directly in myintellect.91 Quodl., q. 13, n. 13, Vivès XXV, 539–540. A further complication is that the object<strong>of</strong> an act <strong>of</strong> abstractive cognition does not have to exist. For example, I may be thinking aboutwhat it is to be a cat even though cats may be extinct. For that reason, Scotus described therelation between an act <strong>of</strong> thinking and its object as a real potential relation.92 On Scotus’s position on the relation between creatures and God, see Scotus, Ord. II,d. 1, q. 4–5, nn. 260–75, Vat. VII, 128–36; Lect. II, d. I, q. 4–5, nn. 238–58, Vat. XVIII, 80–88. SeeHenninger, Relations, 78–85. In Scotus’s jargon, it may perhaps be said that an act <strong>of</strong> thinking isreally identical to but formally distinct from the relation to its object.42


(2) In the current order <strong>of</strong> things, the presence <strong>of</strong> a form in theintellect and the intellect’s own action as an efficient cause are separatelynecessary and jointly sufficient for an act <strong>of</strong> thinking to occur. Exceptionally,however, God can bypass both the intellect and the form and act as the solecause <strong>of</strong> an act <strong>of</strong> thinking.(3) The intentionality <strong>of</strong> an act <strong>of</strong> thinking is accounted for by aspecial relation founded on the act <strong>of</strong> thinking itself and linking it directly toits object. Such an intentional relation between an act <strong>of</strong> thinking and itsobject cannot be reduced to any <strong>of</strong> the Aristotelian causes. Rather, it shouldbe assumed as primitive.Scotus’s key move in his account <strong>of</strong> thinking was his insight that tothink is neither to do something nor to be related to an object. Rather, it is amental quality, i.e. a non-permanent condition present in the intellect. Bytaking that step, he gave up the idea that the occurrence <strong>of</strong> thoughts can beexplained as a kind <strong>of</strong> natural change or process and the cognate view that theintentionality <strong>of</strong> an act <strong>of</strong> thinking is a phenomenon akin to the production <strong>of</strong>natural effects. 9393 I presented a shorter version <strong>of</strong> this paper at the Franciscan <strong>University</strong>, Steubenvillein 2008. I am thankful to the audience for their questions and criticisms. I discussed some <strong>of</strong> theseissues with Marilyn McCord Adams, Susan Brower-Toland, Russell Friedman, Timothy Noone,Martin Pickavé and Cecilia Trifogli. Gyula Klima commented on a previous version <strong>of</strong> this paperand was a constant source <strong>of</strong> help in the course <strong>of</strong> many conversations on these and similartopics. I wish to thank them all.43

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!