02.02.2021 Views

Valuing Life_ A Plea for Disaggregation

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

2004] VALUING LIFE 435

programs that benefit them, the autonomy argument for WTP is

greatly reduced; they are enjoying a benefit (partly) for free, and it

does not insult anyone’s autonomy to give them a good on terms that

they find acceptable. Note that these points do not bear directly on

the question of whether VSL should vary across risks. But they do

bear on the issue of varying VSL across persons, and in particular

across disparities in income and wealth.

Suppose, for example, that beneficiaries of a proposed drinking

water regulation are willing to pay only $80 to eliminate a risk of

1/50,000. Assume, in addition, that the per-person cost of eliminating

a 1/50,000 risk is $100—but that for every dollar of that cost, the

beneficiaries pay only $.80. The remaining $.20 might be paid by

water companies themselves, in the form of reduced profits, or by

employees of the water companies, in the form of reduced wages and

fewer jobs. In this example, the costs of the regulation exceed the

benefits: it is inefficient. But by hypothesis, the regulation makes its

beneficiaries better off. If the WTP criterion is used, the fact that the

monetized costs exceed the monetized benefits is decisive. But as a

normative matter, the analysis here is far harder than in the easy

cases. On what assumption should the WTP numbers be decisive?

The assumption must be that economic efficiency is the goal of

government, at least in the context of regulation—that to know what

to do, government should aggregate the benefits and costs of

regulation, and act if and only if the benefits exceed the costs. When

using the WTP numbers, government is acting as a maximization

machine, aggregating all benefits and costs as measured by the WTP

criterion. But this is a highly contestable understanding of what

government should be doing. In fact it represents a shift from the

relatively uncontroversial Pareto criterion, exemplified above, to a

version of the far more controversial Kaldor-Hicks criterion, 178 which

assesses policy by asking this question: Are the gainers winning more

than the losers are losing? The Kaldor-Hicks criterion is sometimes

described as potential Pareto superiority, 179 because it asks whether in

principle, the winners could compensate the losers, and a surplus

178. It is only a version of that criterion, because it is measuring welfare in monetary

equivalents. A direct assessment of welfare, if it were possible, might justify the regulation in

question on Kaldor-Hicks grounds.

179. See, e.g., RICHARD A. POSNER, ECONOMIC ANALYSIS OF LAW 13 (6th ed. 2003) (“The

Kaldor-Hicks concept is also and suggestively called potential Pareto superiority: The winners

could compensate the losers, whether or not they actually do.”).

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!