19.01.2013 Views

Campaign residen the P -litics - Princeton University

Campaign residen the P -litics - Princeton University

Campaign residen the P -litics - Princeton University

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

Professor Sarah-Jane Leslie *07<br />

really were terrorists. What prejudice did that spawn? How<br />

do we understand and combat it?”<br />

Joshua Knobe’s best-known contribution to experimental<br />

philosophy also is related to issues of blame, going back to a<br />

survey he conducted in New York City’s Washington Square<br />

Park. It was a question of intentionality, based on <strong>the</strong> following<br />

scenario: A proposed new product will increase profits,<br />

but at <strong>the</strong> cost of harming <strong>the</strong> environment. Declaring that<br />

he cares about money and not <strong>the</strong> environment, <strong>the</strong> head of<br />

a company gives <strong>the</strong> go-ahead to make <strong>the</strong> product. As<br />

expected, profits rise, as does environmental damage. So<br />

Knobe asked survey respondents if <strong>the</strong> executive was to<br />

blame for harm to <strong>the</strong> environment, and 82 percent said yes.<br />

Now imagine <strong>the</strong> same scenario, with one key difference:<br />

The new product helps ra<strong>the</strong>r than hurts <strong>the</strong> environment.<br />

The executive still cares just about profits, so <strong>the</strong> new product<br />

goes forward and <strong>the</strong> money rolls in. But when asked if<br />

<strong>the</strong> executive had helped <strong>the</strong> environment, only 23 percent<br />

of Knobe’s respondents gave him credit for that.<br />

Thus was born <strong>the</strong> “Knobe effect,” which summarizes that<br />

people are moralizing creatures who are far more likely to<br />

assign blame for bad things than credit for good things.<br />

Knobe has done fur<strong>the</strong>r research delving into questions of<br />

free will, determinism, and <strong>the</strong> philosophical processes that<br />

are involved in triggering emotional versus rational responses<br />

when it comes to passing judgment.<br />

The Knobe effect, which he uncovered while still a graduate<br />

student at <strong>Princeton</strong>, frequently is referenced in election<br />

years to explain <strong>the</strong> effectiveness of negative political advertising.<br />

It also made Knobe a star and one of experimental<br />

philosophy’s most visible figures. He is writing a book about<br />

experimental philosophy that he hopes will evoke <strong>the</strong> image<br />

of an armchair going up in flames.<br />

Not everyone is convinced. “If you had put this to philoso-<br />

phers before <strong>the</strong> advent of experimental philosophy, you<br />

would have seen this same contrast,” Gideon Rosen says.<br />

“Sure, you can go out and do surveys to confirm it. But those<br />

intuitions are interesting and available without doing surveys.<br />

Even if Knobe had never done an experiment in his<br />

life, he could have written a paper about this with <strong>the</strong> same<br />

significance. My hunch is that philosophers are good at<br />

channeling <strong>the</strong> judgments ordinary people would make.”<br />

Maybe, maybe not. Anthony Appiah, who was one of<br />

Knobe’s dissertation readers at <strong>Princeton</strong>, thinks that such<br />

surveys can only enhance <strong>the</strong> process of philosophy.<br />

“The question isn’t if you could come to <strong>the</strong> same conclusion<br />

without experiments,” says Appiah, “but do <strong>the</strong> experiments<br />

move us ahead in different ways or faster than sitting<br />

around reflecting? I think it would be hard to argue this<br />

hasn’t helped stimulate new questions. The test will be 10<br />

years from now, what we’ve learned by <strong>the</strong>n.”<br />

Ano<strong>the</strong>r common attack on<br />

experimental philosophy is that because most experiments<br />

involve asking <strong>the</strong> opinions of people not trained in philosophical<br />

thinking, <strong>the</strong> results are not valid. It’s “folk philosophy,”<br />

what ordinary people think of as philosophy, ra<strong>the</strong>r<br />

than <strong>the</strong> real thing.<br />

“[In] some of <strong>the</strong>se surveys, it’s unclear why <strong>the</strong> results are<br />

relevant to philosophy,” Rosen says. “So why jump through<br />

hoops? Why not just discuss substantive questions of right<br />

and wrong with people who have been trained to think<br />

about hard cases?” Nonsense, says Stich.<br />

“The whole ‘expertise defense’ [of armchair philosophy] says<br />

it doesn’t matter what <strong>the</strong> man on <strong>the</strong> street thinks about<br />

intuitive knowledge, moral permissibility, or intentionality,<br />

because he’s not an expert,” Stich says. “Philosophers claim to<br />

be <strong>the</strong> only experts capable of producing philosophical intuitions.<br />

But are <strong>the</strong>y? Do you have to have six years of graduate<br />

training at a prestige university to be philosophically savvy?”<br />

In recent years, Stich has been doing survey experiments<br />

to see if philosophers have systematically different intuitions<br />

from ordinary people (which conceivably would render professional<br />

philosophers’ judgments less universal than <strong>the</strong><br />

discipline claims). Early indications are that <strong>the</strong>y do, Stich<br />

says. But while those philosophers’ “right” intuitions might<br />

win over similarly minded peers on a tenure committee,<br />

does that give <strong>the</strong>m <strong>the</strong> weight of inherent truth? Experi -<br />

mental philosophy amounts to a generation saying, not so<br />

fast. Ultimately, <strong>the</strong> debate seems to come down to who<br />

owns philosophy and even truth — a closed society of<br />

experts, or everyone?<br />

“Truth does not belong to philosophy but to all of us,” says<br />

Appiah. “How ordinary people use it is part of <strong>the</strong> accounting,<br />

even if <strong>the</strong>y’re deploying it in ways that may be slippery<br />

and incoherent. Language and <strong>the</strong> mind are both messy, and<br />

so is <strong>the</strong> world.<br />

“Reality,” Appiah says, “is never tidy.” π<br />

David Menconi is a music critic and feature writer at <strong>the</strong> News<br />

& Observer in Raleigh, N.C.<br />

paw.princeton.edu • May 16, 2012 <strong>Princeton</strong> Alumni Weekly<br />

P<br />

39

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!