27.03.2013 Views

LAW OF DURESS IN ISLAMIC LAW AND COMMON LAW: A ...

LAW OF DURESS IN ISLAMIC LAW AND COMMON LAW: A ...

LAW OF DURESS IN ISLAMIC LAW AND COMMON LAW: A ...

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

Islamic Studies (Islamabad) 30:3 (1991)<br />

<strong>LAW</strong> <strong>OF</strong> <strong>DURESS</strong> <strong>IN</strong> <strong>ISLAMIC</strong> <strong>LAW</strong> <strong>AND</strong><br />

<strong>COMMON</strong> <strong>LAW</strong>: A COMPARATIVE STUDY<br />

KHALED ABOU EL FADL<br />

This article war jhtpublished in the Arab Law Quarterly [ZSSN<br />

0268-0556, Graham & Trotman, Sterling Houre, 66, Wilton<br />

Road, London SWN ZDE], r4erenee [I9921 ALQ 121. It is<br />

reproduced here by the pennisswn of the Editor, Dr. Mark<br />

Hoyle.<br />

The Islamic and Common legal systems both assume that a person<br />

is normally free to choose which courses of action to pursue or abandon.<br />

From this assumption, follow the legal liabilities that attach themselves to<br />

certain acts. Duress is perceived as an aberration that negates the presump<br />

tion of voluatary action, and, thus, calls for exceptional treatment from the<br />

legal apparatus.' TZhe accepted wisdom is that people ought not be held<br />

responsible for choices imposed upon them. This wisdom, for instance, is<br />

reflected in BlacLstone's statement that it is "highly just and equitable that<br />

a man should be excused for those action, which are done through unavoidable<br />

force and compul~ion".~ Despite the absolutist language, the treatment<br />

afforded the coerced, in reality, involves a difficult balance between accomodating<br />

the weak .and the oppressed, and setting standards of conduct<br />

for society, On the one hand, it is important to take cognizance of the<br />

specific circumstances, and even the particular idiosyncrasies of an oppressed<br />

individual. On the other hand, the history of duress in Common law and<br />

Islamic law reflects the desire as a matter of policy, to set a standard of<br />

conduct that people are expected to live by.<br />

TZhe purpose of this essay is to provide a ompiuative study of the<br />

law of duress in the common law and Islamic law traditions. Both systems<br />

grapple with the same difficulties and problems, and resolve them in a similar<br />

fashion. Both legal systems differentiate between criminal and civil cases,<br />

and impose a more demondiag standard of d u c t in crimbal cases. Islamic<br />

law, however, offers a methodologically more coherent and systematic ap proach to duress. TZhe Common law's pronouacements on the subject are


306 Islamic Studies, 30:3 (1991)<br />

contradictory and vacillitate between subjective and objective epproaches<br />

without an internally consistent methodology. The Islamic law starts with a<br />

threshold objective inquiry into the nature of rights affected and then pro-<br />

ceeds to a consideration of the subjective feelings of the coerced. Addition-<br />

ally, Islamic law imposes general principles, such as choosing the lesser evil<br />

and proportionality, that provide useful limiting guidlines.<br />

'Zhere has been a wealth of material, that defects citation produced<br />

on difierent aspects of duress. This is partly because duress is an amorphous<br />

subject that encompasses a vast array of legal subjects and problems. Because<br />

duress involves an assessment of the voluntariaess of acts, it is not surprising<br />

to find it implicated in a multitude of legal acts. Hence, one finds duress<br />

factors into assessing the validity of adoptions, marriages, plea bargains,<br />

self incriminations, jury verdicts, contempt of court for refusal to testify and<br />

assumption of risk in the employment conte~t.~ In addition, duress is a<br />

significant aspect of the law of senritude: and duress can implicate freedom<br />

of speech issues or inten-iational law problems.5 Additiody, Duress ocws<br />

in many different forms, the most straightfornard of whihutright physical<br />

f o d s applied against the person of another to bring about a certain<br />

result. It could also take the form of a threat, whether explicit or implicit,<br />

to harm someone if a certain act is not undertaken. Even more, duress could<br />

take the form of some financial necessity not necessarily created by a particular<br />

person. In other words, a weak person might find himself in a dire<br />

financial position, and, consequently, such a person will be forced to comply<br />

with certain demands that might or might not be ad~antageous.~<br />

In each, of these fields, several policy and moral considerations as<br />

well as widely varied factual cinwnstances pertain. Hence the difficulty in<br />

finding a comprehensive and systematic method of analysing all cases of<br />

duress, or in even explaining the common moral and policy considerations<br />

that are relevant to each area of duress. Writers have proposed different<br />

theories to differentiate between legal and illegal duress. Some arguing for<br />

a value free empirical theory while others maintaining that duress essentially<br />

involves a moral judgement? At a less abstract level, He*rt Fingarette<br />

argues, somewhat persuasively, that at the core of all duress cases is a<br />

concept of victimization in which a more powerful party exploits a less<br />

powerful party in order to obtain a certain benefit.'<br />

But even if it true, this does not tell us what legal consequences<br />

should follow from th& victimization. The law does not remedy every act<br />

of oppression, exploitation or victimization, partly because victimization is<br />

as broad a concept as duress. Both concepts are ultimately products of social<br />

standards and moral policies a society prescribes for itself. More will be said<br />

about this issue later. This essay, however, does not aspire to present an


Islamic Studies, 30:3 (1991) 307<br />

overall approach or theory of duress. Nor will this essay address all forms<br />

of duress. The goal is to contrast Islamic law with the Common law, and to<br />

argue that the methodology adopted by Islamic law presents a useful addition<br />

to the field.<br />

A DEFTNITION <strong>OF</strong> <strong>DURESS</strong><br />

There is no uniform legal definition of duress. Because of the amorph-<br />

ousness of the concept, duress can only be defined in the most indefinite<br />

sense. Generally, duress is a wrongful pressure placed upon the person of<br />

another forcing such a person to commit or not to commit a certain act.9<br />

Article 948 of the Mejelle defines duress as "[Duress] is without right to<br />

compel a person to do a thing without his consent by fear."1° These defin-<br />

itions have the virtue of simplicity but, of course, they do not say much,<br />

some would add to this definition that the threatened harm must be present<br />

and imminent." While others might add that the threatened harm must<br />

overcome or overbear a persons' will and deprive him or her of the freedom<br />

of choice.12 Still, in the articulation of some sources, the threat must produce<br />

a reasonable fear of harm or produce a fear which a person of reasonable<br />

firmness would be unable to resist.13<br />

Regardless of the definition, at essence there is an everexisting tension<br />

between the desire to accommodate the actual feelings and practical limita-<br />

tions of the victims of duress, and the need for society to impose standards<br />

of conduct. Thus, should the law of duress accommodate the especially timid<br />

and weak, or should it require all persons to live up to a standard of social<br />

conduct irrespective of their particular circumstances? Should one hold de-<br />

terminative the subjective feelings and fears of the threatened person or<br />

should the type of threatened harm be held determinative Or, should the<br />

proportionality between the threatened harm, and the crime committed be<br />

determinative? If one decides that the subjective feelings of the victim are<br />

determinative, does it make a difference whether the victim's response to<br />

the threat is very unusual and generally unreasonable? Even then, does it<br />

matter that the victim's uncommon response is the result of his selfish and<br />

self-centred personality rather than a faint hearted and feeble character?<br />

Even more, are there situations in which society will decide that<br />

certain choices are inexcusable or unjustifiable as a matter of law? For<br />

example, assume that a scholar who adores her books murders an innocent<br />

person to escape a threat to destroy her library. Should society provide, as<br />

a matter of law, that human life is more valuable than books? What if the<br />

scholar's library consists of very rare and irreplaceable manuscripts, does<br />

that make a difference? What if in the course of trying to save a library<br />

from the hands of an oppressive government, a scholar commits a murder<br />

or, perhaps, seriously injures a person: does that make a difference?


308 Islamic Studies, 30:3 (1991)<br />

Furthermore, are there certain types of threats that are presumptively<br />

coercive; for example, a threat of death or serious bodily injury, while others<br />

are presumptively ineffective, such as threats to destroy property? In a sense,<br />

the tension is always between over-legislating to insure that certain social<br />

values and choices are upheld, or under-legislating to maintain a flexible<br />

standard able to accommodate individual feelings and exceptional cir-<br />

cumstances.<br />

The Common law, mainly in Britain and the United States but also<br />

in Australia and New Zealand, adopted different and often inconsistent<br />

solutions to these problems. W e maintaining a considerable degree of<br />

flexibility, the Common law remains unsystematic in its underlying rationale,<br />

Islamic law created dichotomy between types of acts, and types of duress.<br />

In criminal acts, Islamic law opted for a restrictive alternative, only admitting<br />

certain types of duress while adopting a much more flexible approach in<br />

civil acts. In either case, while accommodating the subjective feelings of the<br />

individual, Islamic law imposes overriding social standards of conduct such<br />

as committing the lesser evil. First, we consider the legal developments<br />

within the Common law and then we shall turn to Islamic law.<br />

THE <strong>COMMON</strong> <strong>LAW</strong> <strong>OF</strong> <strong>DURESS</strong><br />

The original Common law held a rather una~~~mmodating view of<br />

duress. In order to constitute duress, the coercion had to be sufficient to<br />

overcome the will of a constant or brave man.14 Even though this standard<br />

was eventually relaxed to that of a man of ordinary firmness, it did not<br />

significantly alter the law because it was assumed that only a threat of death<br />

or serious bodily injury would be sufficient to overcome the will of such a<br />

person. Hence threats of destruction of property or minor injury were not<br />

recognised as duress.'' Additionally, threats directed at third parties or<br />

persons other than the duressed were inadmissible." The threat had to be<br />

immediate and imminent leaving no opportunity for escape.''<br />

The focus at Common law was on the type of coercion, and not so<br />

much on the psychological condition of the coerced person. Certain types<br />

of threats, like death, mayhem or maiming, by definition, were considered<br />

coercive. Significantly, the same test applied regardless of the type of act a<br />

person was coerced to commit. Therefore, whether the threat was designed<br />

to force a person to sign a contract or commit a crime, the same test applied.<br />

Additionally, there was no inquiry as to the proportionality between the<br />

harm threatened and the act committed. Rather, the inquiry was largely<br />

focussed on the kn;er's misconduct in lieu of other factors.'' Common<br />

law courts approached the defence of duress with caution and conservatism.<br />

Therefore, the approach was rather categorical, designed to set limits that<br />

eliminate the potential for abuse inherent in defence.19


Islamic Studies. 30:3 (1991) 309<br />

At the present time, the Common law, particularly in the area of<br />

civil law, has undergone a major shift in the emphasis. For the most part,<br />

the type of duress became of secondary importance, and the impact of duress<br />

on the victim ascended to primary importance. Tbus, the focus became the<br />

state of mind induced by duress in the victim.m Consistent with this approach,<br />

Common law rules as to third party duress were liberalized, particularly in<br />

civil transactions. Likewise, the rules as to the immediacy of the harm became<br />

somewhat relaxed. We shall review the rules on these topics in some detail<br />

in later sections on criminal and civil acts.<br />

Tbe Common law retained the requirement that the duress be wrong-<br />

ful. Although, the traditional Common law held that "it is not duress to<br />

threaten to do what one has a legal right to do", this has been substantially<br />

modified. The threatened duress need not be unlawful in the legal sense,<br />

but need only be wrongful in the moral sense.21 Tbus; threatening to use a<br />

legal right in an abusive or oppressive fashion is considered sufficient<br />

duress." Tbe wrongfulness of the threat is at issue particularly in economic<br />

duress cases. Beyond cases of economic duress, the crux of the matter,<br />

especially in civil cases, is whether the victim felt oppressed and overwhelmed<br />

by the threat, and not necessarily whether the threat could be legally classified<br />

as impermissible."<br />

Despite the fact that the Common law has de-emphasised the type<br />

of duress, it has not been able to resolve whether if any attention whatsoever<br />

should be placed on the type of coerced act. Tberefore, even if we accept<br />

that only wrongful threats can overcome a person's will, must we con-<br />

sequently excuse any act the coerced commits regardless of its nature? This<br />

is fundamentally a question of policy and morality. But the failure of the<br />

Common law to realize that the whole defence of duress is founded on such<br />

considerations has created- inconsistencies and confusion. This will be<br />

explained in more detail later.<br />

For now, we turn to Islamic law and its approach.<br />

<strong>DURESS</strong> AT <strong>ISLAMIC</strong> <strong>LAW</strong>^^<br />

Islamic law has a multifaceted approach to duress. Motivated by a<br />

need to protect the sanctity of particular human and divine rights, Islamic<br />

law is in certain respects rigid. But motivated by a similar need to protect<br />

the rights of the duressed, it is in other respects flexible. Tbe whole Islamic<br />

jurisprudential discourse on the subject is phrased in terms of balancing the<br />

rights of God and society against the rights of the coerced individual. Hence<br />

Islamic law in certain areas emphasie the type of duress and the dature of<br />

the injured rights while simultaneously accommodating the subjective feel-<br />

ings of the coerced.


310 Islamic Studies, 30:3 (1991)<br />

Muslim jurists divided duress into two main categories. The first<br />

compelling or constraining (mulji), and the second, not as compelling or<br />

constraining (ghyr mulji) . 25 The first type (compelling duress) nullifies con-<br />

sent and vitiates free choice. The second type (non-oompelling duress) nul-<br />

lifies consent but does not vitiate free choice. In other words, there are two<br />

types of duress: one that is so compelling that the victim not only cannot<br />

freely consent but is not really left with a choice at all. The second type of<br />

duress is not as overwhelming and, therefore, practically speaking, the victim<br />

is left with a choice.26<br />

Hanafi jurists argued that consent, as in being content or pleased<br />

with ones decisions, often lacks even without duress or with minimal duress.<br />

Often a person agrees to something that is not entirely satisfactory, pleasing<br />

or even in her best possible interest. An example given by Hanafi jurists is<br />

that of a person who divorces his beautiful bride might not be happy with<br />

his decision, but he does it anyway because it might be neces~ary.~ On the<br />

other hand, choice always exists even if duress is present. One can always<br />

choose to die whether one is happy with the decision or not. But, if the<br />

duress is powerful enough then the choice, although not lacking, is vitiated<br />

or spoiled. Therefore, any amount of duress is liable to negate consent. But<br />

only serious or compelling duress will also spoil choice.<br />

Al-Kasiini (d. 587/1189) explains the two categories:<br />

Duress is of two types. One type creates necessity and leaves no<br />

recourse by its very nature like (a threat) of death or maiming or ti<br />

beating that endangers the life or limb (that is) wheth;er the beating<br />

is excessive or light. And some have said that such beating must be<br />

about the amount of lashes required in a &add [a set punishment that<br />

ranges from 40 to 100 lashes], however, such an opinion is incorrect<br />

because what is important here is that necessity is created and if<br />

[necessity] exists then there is no reason to require a certain amount<br />

of lashes. And this [ht] type is called fdm (complete). The second<br />

type does not create a necessity and does leave some recourse and<br />

that is like imprisonment or bondage or beating that does not threaten<br />

to cause grave injury. And bere again] there is no specific amount<br />

of duress required but that it [the duress] causes agony. . . and this<br />

type is called ikrcsh -4 (incomplete comp~lsion).~~<br />

As quoted above, al-Kasani cites imprisonment as an instance of<br />

non-compelling duress. Actually, the threat of imprisonment can never be<br />

compelling.29 While others have held that long imprisonment, contrary to<br />

a one-day detention, could be compelling duress." While still others implied<br />

that this depends on the condition of the prison; if it is in a bad condition


Islamic Studies, 30:3 (1991) 31 1<br />

then imprisonment is compelling duress.31 It would seem that the viey<br />

holding that long imprisonment in bad condition could be compelling duress<br />

is more consistent with the overall approach of Islamic law.<br />

The relevant point, according to Islamic law, is that duress is divided<br />

into two general categories. Threats of grevious harm, in whatever form,<br />

could excuse serious offenses. All other forms of duress would only excuse<br />

less serious offenses. The law defines what is a grevious harm, but the threat<br />

has to be subjectively felt and believed by the coerced. Therefore, there is<br />

a threshold question of whether the law recognises the form of duress and<br />

if it does, what category it falls under. Once the threshold question is trans-<br />

cended, there remains a question of the subjective feelings of the coerced.<br />

Consequently, if the law considers a threat of one day imprisonment to be<br />

non-compelling, regardless of the hypersensitivities of a timid person it will<br />

only excuse less serious offenses. Generally, only threats of death or serious<br />

bodily injury constitute compelling duress.<br />

There is some disagreement among Muslim jurists as to whether<br />

certain types of threats should be considered duress at all. For example,<br />

most jurists held that an act of public humiliation like a single slap on the<br />

face could be duress while a minority (particularly from the Hanbali School)<br />

disagreed." However, since a slap on the face cannot cause grevious bodily<br />

injury it is not compelling duress.<br />

According to the majority of Muslim jurists a threat of damage to<br />

property could constitute duress, and if the damage is substantial and grevi-<br />

ous, the threat could constitute compelling duress. Some jurists contended<br />

that whether the damage to property is substantial or not must be relative<br />

to the wealth of the victim.= A threat of destruction to ones home could<br />

be compelIing duress to a poor person while only constituting noncompelling<br />

duress to a person owning the means to easily replace his lost home.<br />

Most Muslim jurists also recognised threats of harm to third parties<br />

as duress. But they disagreed over who may the third party be. Some only<br />

recognised threats directed at parents or offsprings, and a few recognised<br />

even threats directed at strangers.% Nevertheless, particularly Hana6 and<br />

HanbaIi jurists insisted that whatever the type of threat, it only constitutes<br />

nowcompelling duress if directed at third parties.% Although the matter is<br />

not free from doubt, it seems that, as to the otber schooIs, whether a threat<br />

to a third party is compelling duress depends on the type of harm threatened.<br />

So, if a third party is threatened with death or grevious bodily injury then<br />

that is considered compelling duress.<br />

Notably, the Islamic approach to duress resembles. somewhat the<br />

traditional common law in its adoption of an objective inquiry focussing on


312 Islamic Studies, 30:3 (1991)<br />

the type of duress. Nevertheless, a major difference is that while the traditional<br />

Common law only admitted certain types of duress no matter the<br />

coerced act, as mentioned later, Islamic law admits most forms of duress,<br />

but insists on proportionality between the type of duress and the type of<br />

act. Additionally, the traditional Common law held people to an objective<br />

standard of a braver or constant person. Islamic law, however, combines a<br />

subjective inquiry designed to ascertain whether, in fact, the victim felt<br />

compelled due to a present fear to oblige the coercer. Hence, Muslimjurists<br />

stated that we should iuquire into whether the victim believed, by a preponderance<br />

of his thought, that he was faced with a necessity that left him no<br />

alte~native.~~ Al Sarakhsi (d. 483/1090) explains this point in the following<br />

passages:<br />

"[We consider] the preponderance of thought [of the victim] and<br />

what he felt because the victim's belief takes precedence over the<br />

reality concerning matters that we have no way of verifying indepen-<br />

dently. . . . The conditions of people vary according to their ability<br />

to withstand pain, therefore, we have no alternative but to wnsider<br />

what the victim believed.""<br />

Al-Sara argues that since we cannot know what people can withstand<br />

or endure. We have to inquire into the specific individual case to ascertain<br />

whether fear existed.38 Tben a14arakW argues that this approach is best<br />

in order to "alleviate hardship from the people" (taysfr 'ulu'l-?I&). Finally,<br />

he adds that in each individual case it will have to be left up to the judge<br />

to decide whether the victim actually felt compelled or not.39<br />

This necessarily means that duress could be relative according to the<br />

circumstances of the duressed. Hence, what is not duress for a street-wise<br />

persion could be its opposite for a timid and inexperienced persoh. Iikewise,<br />

a single slap on the face or single lash with a whip could be oppressive for<br />

one person but not for the other. Each case has to be decided individually<br />

on its facts.& However, as mentioned earlier, the person's subjective feelings<br />

cannot transform noncompelling duress into compelling duress.<br />

On the closely associated issue of whether the threatened duress need<br />

be impending and immediate, there is dhgreement among Muslim<br />

Some jurists held that the duress is recognised only if the victim performed<br />

the coerced act in the presence of the coerced." Nonetheless, the majority<br />

of Muslim jurists disagreed, Shafi'i jurists argued that the threatened danger<br />

has to be immediate (a'jif) leaving little opportunity to escape. The crux of<br />

the matter, however, is the formation of fear in the victim's mind and that<br />

the victim would think he is left with no choice. Actual physical presence<br />

of the coercer is not necessary in order for the victim to form the belief that<br />

he is in danger."


Islamic Studies, 30:3 (1991) 313<br />

The Malikis affirmed this argument; but they added that since the<br />

real issue is the formation of fear in the victim's mind, there is no need to<br />

require that the threatened harm be immediate. Consequently, even if the<br />

threatened violence would occur after a whole month and the victim was<br />

terrified by this, and he could not seek help, then there is duress.44 Al-<br />

Sarakhd, although a Hanafi, went much further in arguing that in certain<br />

situations even an explicit threat is not required. One such situation arises<br />

when A,ia person of authority, orders B to kill another, but A does not<br />

explicitly threaten to kill B if he does not comply. If from the context of<br />

the situation B believes that if he fails to comply, he will be killed then there<br />

is duress. Al-Sarakbsi justified this rule by arguing that, "it is the habit of<br />

oppressors, because of their haughtiness, not to explicitly threaten to kill<br />

people. But [in reality] they issue orden, and then if they are not obeyed,<br />

they always punish by death those who disobey them. And, therefore, if<br />

this is the common practice, then a simple order might be considered an<br />

explicit threat of death . . . that fulfills the requirements of<br />

Hence, the majority, and the better supported, view is that immediacy<br />

is only a factor to be considered as to the ultimate question of whether the<br />

coerced felt compelled.46 This is consistent with the Islamic emphasis on the<br />

preponderance of the victim's mind. As mentioned earlier, however, one<br />

should carefully note that the Islamic approach is not entirely subjective.<br />

For example, a single slap on the face or minor destruction to property,<br />

except perhaps to an indigent person, will never constitute compelling duress<br />

regardless of the particular idiayncrasies of the victim. Consequently, certain<br />

types of duress cannot excuse certain grave offenses although a particularly<br />

timid victim might feel completely overwhelmed by a relatively minor form<br />

of duress. The subjective inquiry is only designed to ascertain whether the<br />

victim in fact felt threatened. But the categorization of the duress, and what<br />

acts it can excuse is determined according to legal standards.<br />

The Islamic approach seems to be premised on the idea that although<br />

it is appropriate to consider the subjective feelings of the coerced, whether<br />

the duress should be recognised or not is essentially a policy and moral<br />

decision. Even in the existence of duress a person's will is really never<br />

overcome. Similarly, duress does not really negate consent nor the power<br />

of choice. Whatever the amount of physical or mental violence, a person<br />

still has the choice between endurance and submission. After all, a choice<br />

between two evils is still a choice. If a person is threatened by death to sign<br />

a contract, he could make a rational decision to sign the contract rather<br />

than die. The person might not be happy with the result, but he makes his<br />

choice based on the best possible scenarios available to him at the time. If<br />

the circumstances were different, the perion might have chosen a different<br />

course of action, but the circumstances being what they are, a person consents


314 Islamic Studies, 30:3 (1991)<br />

and chooses an undesirable course of action. This is why the Hanafi jurists<br />

argue that choice is merely corrupted duress (i.e it is not a choice made<br />

under the best possible circumstances) but the choice is never rendered<br />

non-existent. More will be said about this matter by way of evaluating the<br />

Islamic approach.<br />

Inherent to the Islamic approach to the types of duress, is that the<br />

victim's response be proportional. First, the victim cannot commit more<br />

damage than the situation requires and he is held liable for the excess<br />

behaviour or the over reaction. Second, the victim cannot commit a great<br />

harm to avoid a lesser harm.47 merefore, the threat required varies with<br />

the harm committed. In £act, the whole logic of compelling duress and<br />

noncompelling duress is that there be proportionality between the type of<br />

duress and the type of act committed. By contrast, the Common law has<br />

ignored, and to an extent continues to ignore, the requirement of proportion-<br />

ality?<br />

In addition to the principle of proportionality, Islamic law requires<br />

that a victim of duress choose the lesser of the evils he faces (Wycfr akhaff<br />

ol-&~arayn).~~ Al-S- sates the general principle, "And if it is said . . .<br />

'an unjustly treated person has a right to resist injustice in whatever way he<br />

can'. We say: 'yes, but an unjustly treated person cannot commit injustice<br />

against others'. . . ."'" 'Ibis rule applies if the two evils are equal; the<br />

victim cannot save himself at the expense of others. But if the evil he will<br />

suffer is greater than the evil he will commit then he is excused.51 Otherwise,<br />

the victim is always under a duty to minimize the damage. So if he is forced<br />

to divorce his wife or commit a murder he must divorce his wife rather than<br />

commit a murder." If he is forced either to kill someone or pronounce<br />

apostasy, and he chooses to kill then he is not excused because prqnouncing<br />

apostaiy is a lesser crime than murder.s3 If he is compelled to murder a<br />

slave or destroy property, he must destory the property because a slave is<br />

a protected life. Furthermore, if he is compelled to destroy the property<br />

either of a rich person or a poor person, he must destroy the property of<br />

the rich person because that is the lesser evils.% A final example; if pe<br />

victim is compelled either to rape or murder neither choices are excused' in<br />

the hereafter. Meaning he will be punished for either choice on the final<br />

day. But as far as the earthly legal remedies are concerned, he must commit<br />

rape rather than murder i.e. if he commits rape, he will not be punished.<br />

But if he perseveres and commits neither that is much better in the final<br />

judgement."<br />

THE EFFECTS <strong>OF</strong> <strong>DURESS</strong> ON ACTS<br />

In an attempt to formulate a systematic law of duress, Muslim jurists<br />

divided acts into two separate categories: (1) physical acts and (2) verbal


Islamic Studies, 30:3 (1991) 315<br />

acts.Physicalactskcrimiaalinana~esuchcrsmurder,rape,anddestruction<br />

of properly. Verbal acts are mainly civil such as forming contracts, divorce<br />

or marriage. In general, only compelling duress affects physical acts whild<br />

both compelling and noncompelling duress affect verbal acts.%<br />

Some Muslim jurists chose to make the centre of categorical divisions<br />

not so much the nature of the acts in question but, rather, the nature of the<br />

rights affected. According to these jurists, acts are divided into two kinds;<br />

(1) Those acts that only affect the rights of the victim of duress, and (2)<br />

lluse acts that affect the rights of other innocent people andlor the rights<br />

of God, such as apostasy. In the first type, a lesser form of duress may<br />

excuse the act. In the second type, a more compelling fonn of duress (like<br />

a threat of death or serious physical injury) is needed to negate liabi~ity.'~<br />

The Common law did not create a dichotomy between the types of<br />

acts and the types of duress. Nonetheless, some of the rules articulated at<br />

traditional Common law were apparently premid on a differentiation be-<br />

tween the nature of rights affected. Some of that can be discerned from the<br />

Latin maxim privik@m non vdct contra ranpublicon (necessity does not<br />

excuse acts committad against the republic), and, hence, the rule that neces-<br />

sity does not excuse treason. Fmds Bacon demonstrates the logic of the<br />

above-mentioned maxim in the following example. If people at sea are faced<br />

by a tempest, they are not liable if they cast properly and goods overboard.<br />

But they are not excused if the shipisuuryingordnnace or atnmunition "to<br />

relieve any of the king's towns that are distressed. . . . ." Blackstone offers<br />

a more telling example of the original approach at the Common law.<br />

Blackstone argues that duress excuses "positive crimes" or, in other words,<br />

aimes created by the laws of society. "[But] not [so] as to natural offenses,<br />

so declared by law of God, wherein human magistrates are only the<br />

executioners of divine punishment." Therefore, a person placed in danger<br />

of life or limb cannot save himself by killing another." Pursuant to this<br />

logic, crimes against God's laws, the crown or the commonwealth were<br />

deemed inexcusable. This categorical approach somewhat resembles Islamic<br />

law. But Islamic law, although categorical, did not rely on the same rationale.<br />

Crimw against the rights of God are excused by duress, and whether crimes<br />

against the commonwealth are excused depends on a variety of considera-<br />

tions, the belief of the coerced being among them.60<br />

The modem Common law for the most part has abandoned categorical<br />

or dichotomous approaches. Nevertheless, the modem Common law does<br />

adhere to different forms of analysis in criminal as opposed to civil cases.<br />

The distinction, however, is not premised on anything dubious such as the<br />

differentiation between verbal and physical acts, and it does not seem to be<br />

premised on a differentiation between-the involvement or non-involvement


316 Islamic Studies, 30:3 (1991)<br />

of innocent persom6' In fact, the Common law fails to explain the reason<br />

for adopting a standard of duress in civil cases different from that which<br />

applies in criminal cases.<br />

Other than discussing criminal and civil cases separately, this essay<br />

will not structure the discussion around the theoretical categories established,<br />

particularly, by Muslim jurists. Rather the focus will be on the specific rules<br />

that apply to the different types of acts. Firstly, contractual or civil matters<br />

will be examined, secondly, criminal acts such as destruction of property,<br />

rape and murder will be examined. Finally, our attention will be turned to<br />

the subject of superior orders.<br />

CONTRACTUAL <strong>AND</strong> CIVIL ACTS<br />

In the modem Common law, duress is recognised only if it overcomes<br />

the will of the victim. According to most cases and commentators, the<br />

approach is entirely ~ubjective.~' Therefore, section 492 of the Restatement<br />

of contracts states:<br />

Duress . . . means (a) any wrongful act of one person that compels<br />

a manifestation of apparent assent by another to a transaction without<br />

his volition, or (b) any wrongful threat of one person by words or<br />

other conduct that induces another to enter into a transaction under<br />

the influence of such fear as precludes him from exercising free will<br />

and judgement. If the threat was intended or should reasonably have<br />

been expected to operate as an ind~cement.~~<br />

Although, courts frequently speak of a will overcome by duress, and<br />

of an entirely subjective approach, evidence showing whether a reasonable<br />

person would have felt compelled is pertinent as to whether the victim's will<br />

was, in fact, overcome.64 In other words, a court would consider what a<br />

reasonable person would have believed or done in order to evalkte the<br />

credibility of the victim's claim. This is inconsistent with the entirely subjec-<br />

tive standard that the modem Common law claims to follow. In fact, espe-<br />

cially in cases involving economic duress,65 as opposed to threats of physical<br />

injury, courts often grant relief on public policy grounds such as unjust<br />

enrichment, gross unfairness or bad faith dealing by the ~oercer.~~<br />

The Restatement Second of Contracts resolves this discrepancy by<br />

abandoning the totally subjective standard. Section 175 provides:


Islamic Studies, 30:3 (1991) 317<br />

If a party's manifestation of assent is induced by an improper threat<br />

by the other party that leaves the victim no reasonable alternative,<br />

the contract is voidable by the victim.<br />

Hence, in order for duress to exist two prongs must be fulfilled. One,<br />

the victim's assent must be induced by an improper threat. -0, there, must<br />

be no reasonable alternative left to the victim.67 The assent of the victim is<br />

decided through a subjective inquiry.68 Nonetheless, the existence, or lack<br />

thereof, of a reasonable alternative is a "mixed question of law and fact, to<br />

be answered in clear cases by the court". In summary, the Restatement<br />

Second pursues both a subjective and objective inquiry. The feelings and<br />

understandings of the duressed are accommodated to an extent. But the<br />

reasonableness of the alternatives available to the duressed would be objec-<br />

tively determined. One, however, has to admit, as in all areas of the law,<br />

that the word "reasonable" is extremely vague. It is not at all clear what<br />

does the phrase, "leaves the victim no reasonable alternative" means. Fun-<br />

damentally, what is reasonable can only be determined by reference to moral<br />

and policy experiences and expectations of society. These are the same<br />

considerations that help draw the thin line differentiating hard bargain situ-<br />

ations from oppressive and coercive conditions.69 Therefore, the Restate-<br />

ment Second seems to open the door for a host of moral and policy deter-<br />

minations. Importantly, a determination of the reasonableness of alternatives<br />

left to the coerced, threatens to make the subjective inquiry into the duressed's<br />

assent largely irrelevant. For example, in Miller v. ~ ikele,~ plaintiff<br />

believed that his stock broker made improper charges to plainti£Ps securities<br />

account which resulted in additional margin. In order to prevent defendant<br />

from selling more of his securities, plaintiff made the margin call payments<br />

under protest. The appellate court held that the trial court erred in granting<br />

the defendant's motion for non-suit, asserting that there were sdficient<br />

factual issues to send the case to the jury. In reaching its decision, the court<br />

heavily relied on the fact that plaintiff made these margin call payments<br />

during the market crash of 1929. The subsequent depression, the court<br />

reasoned, proved the phiintiff prudent in not waiting to sue for the value of<br />

his securities.<br />

As a practical matter, the fact that the plaintiffs worries proved<br />

correct is quite irrelevant as to whether his assent was coerced or whether<br />

duress existed. If the depression did not follow, plaintiffs assent would have<br />

been equally coerced at the time he made his decision. Ultimately, in asses-<br />

sing the reasonableness of the alternatives available to the duressed, one<br />

might ignore the assent or feelings of the duressed since these alternatives<br />

.could have been unknown to the duressed. Once it is said that a reasonable<br />

person should have thought of the alternatives, we are no longer seriously<br />

considering, and, in fact we are ignoring, the subjective feelings of the<br />

coerced.


318 Islamic Studies, 30:3 (1991)<br />

It should be emphasised, however, that the approach of the Restate-<br />

ment Second does not represent the majority view. The majority of courts<br />

insist that the victim's will must be overcome and, consequently, that the<br />

inquiry be entirely subjective.<br />

In deciding whether the victim's assent was procured by duress, or<br />

in the terminology of most cases, whether the victim's will was overcome<br />

or not, the lapse of time between the threat and the coerced act only goes<br />

to the ultimate issue of fact. In other words, modem Common law, considers<br />

the imminence of the threat only as evidence of whether the victim's will<br />

has been overcome or not." Threats of harm to property or third parties,<br />

for the most part, are also admitted.n However, as to third parties, there<br />

is disagreement as to whether only threats to relatives should be recognised<br />

or all relationships should be admitted as long as there is affinity between<br />

the third party and the coerced person.n<br />

Finally, contracts made under duress are normally held to be voidable;<br />

they are void only in rare circumstance^.^' For example, if a person<br />

threatened by death signs a contract without knowledge of its contents or<br />

if a person under the influence of hypnosis signs a contract then these<br />

agreements are void rather than voidable. In both these situations, there is<br />

a total absence of consent. But in the more common situation, where the<br />

party's will has been overcome by duress, the contract is voidable."<br />

Islamic Law<br />

Islamic law, in many respects, is War to the Common law. As<br />

reviewed earlier, when it comes to civil acts, Islamic law recognises both<br />

types of duress, compelling and noncompelling. Since all types of duress<br />

are recognised, the only remaining question is whether, in fact, the victim<br />

felt that he had to assent to the transaction or risk getting harmed. If that<br />

is the case, as a matter of legal standard, and moralheligious policy, the<br />

transaction will not stand. Hence the inquiry as to the victim's state of mind<br />

is subjective. But as mentioned earlier, the law imposes an overriding objec-<br />

tive principle of choice of the lesser evil and proportionality. Therefore, if<br />

A threatens to destroys B's house unless he signs a condemnation order<br />

against ten houses, B cannot do so. The harm inflicted by B exceeds the<br />

harm avoided. Similarly if A threatens to destroy B's house unless B signs<br />

a condemnation order against Cs house and B is rich but C is poor, and B<br />

knows that C is poor, then B cannot inflict the harm.<br />

Islamic law incorporates the Common law dodrine that there must<br />

be no other alternative through the principle of choosing the lesser evil. If<br />

there was a less harmful alternative and the victim failed to pursue it then


Islamic Studies, 30:3 (1991) 319<br />

the lesser of the two evils has not been observed. For example, if the person<br />

could have avoided the harm by seeking legal advice or police protection,<br />

the victim has a duty to commit the lesserpvil which in this case means<br />

seeking legal advice.76<br />

Taken to the extreme, this logic would nullify all claims of duress of<br />

goods or, more broadly, most cases of economic duress. For example, in<br />

the Miller case the plaintiff's alternative was to refuse to make the demanded<br />

payments and sue for breach of contract as well as other grounds rather<br />

than claim duress. At one level, Islamic law appears to resolve this problem<br />

by pursuing an essentially utilitarian approach. If waiting to sue for breach<br />

of contract would cause more harm than an immediate claim of duress, then<br />

the lesser of the two evils is to comply with the defendant's demands, and<br />

then claim duress. Importantly, however, "harm" is not identified solely by<br />

reference to the plaintiff's condition. Rather social and religious policies can<br />

enter into defining the extent of An example, taken from outside<br />

the context of Islamic law might help demonstrate the point.78 Suppose that<br />

A, an already rich individual, is due to inherit a large sum of money from<br />

an estate. An unethical lawyer threatens to tie up the estate in court unless<br />

A agrees to pay him exorbitant legal fees. A has two options; either he pays<br />

the fees now and claim duress later or sue the lawyer immediately and risk<br />

receiving his inheritance after a long delay. Since Islamic law does not rely<br />

on the logic of an overcome will, it can hold that duress exists because as<br />

a matter of public policy, lawyers cannot be permitted to behave in this<br />

fashion. In Islamic terminology, litigating the dispute in court is not the<br />

lesser evil, since, as a matter of law, allegations of attorney misconduct are<br />

a greater and more general evil or harm (erar kuli and not a +rur hiss).79<br />

Interestingly, the Restatement Second in civil cases seems to be closer to<br />

the Islamic approach than the traditional Common law. Both are standard-<br />

setting or standard-recognising, and both are vague but for different<br />

reasons.80<br />

Once duress is found, Muslim jurists could not agree on whether the<br />

resulting contract is void or voidable. According to the Hanafis, a defect of<br />

duress differs from other contractual defects (like a defect of fraud or mutual<br />

mistake) in certain respects. One, the contract could be subsequently invali-<br />

dated and, two, it could be invalidated even if handled by an innocent<br />

purchaser.81 Thus, according to the majority of Hanafi jurists, a sale or<br />

contract induced by duress is compt fjiiid), nonetheless, it is enforceable.<br />

The victim of duress, however, has the power to subsequently invalidate<br />

the contract of sale.82<br />

If the victim of duress eventually attacks the validity of the contract<br />

of sale, it becomes void even if there & a third innocent party who relied


320 Islamic Studies, 30:3 (1991)<br />

on such a contract. In other words, even if the object of the illegal act of<br />

duress moves into the regular course of business (even if it is handled by<br />

hands, in Islamic terminology) it is still retrievable by the victim. If we may<br />

illustrate, assume A illegally compels B to give his horse to C and % sells<br />

the horse to D. Both C and D know nothing of A's illegal acts. Nonetheless<br />

B can retrieve the horse from C or D wherever it may be. D can sue C or<br />

A for the price of the horse, and D can sue A for the same price. In other<br />

words, the victim of duress is entitled to retrieve his rights, and the other<br />

parties are left to settle things amongst themselves. Ultimate, liability lies<br />

with the offending oppressor. The victim, however, cannot commit any act<br />

that evidences his acquiescence in the transaction. For example, if he willingly<br />

delivers the product or accepts a price after the duress is removed, that is<br />

a sign of acquiescence and approval. In effect, the Hanafis argued that<br />

contracts or sales induced by duress are voidable at the election of the victim.<br />

The Shafi'is, Hanbalis and Zahiris disagreed. They considered such transactions<br />

as void from the moment of their creation. Ibn Hazm, the Zahiri,<br />

relied on the Qur'hic injunctions prohibiting compulsion in religi~n,'~ then<br />

he argued, by analogy, that duress creates inherently illegal transactions<br />

that may not be sanctioned at any stage." The Shafi'is took another point<br />

of departure. According to them, consent (al-tarrudi) is a prerequisite for<br />

a contract to form in the first place. Since duress negates such consent, in<br />

reality, a contract was never formed, and, therefore, no legal effect can be<br />

given to such duress. Thus, the contract is void from its inception. The<br />

Hanafis, on the other hand, argued that consent is not a prerequisite for a<br />

contract to form, consent, rather, is necessary for a contract to be effective.<br />

This led the Hanafi school to conclude that a contract induced by duress is<br />

simply voidable and not void.''<br />

The Maliki school chose a less stringent alternative. Maliki jurists<br />

decided that contracts or sales induced by duress are non-binding (ghayr<br />

kern): Thus, they cannot be enforced against the victim, but the victim<br />

cannot enforce his rights against innocent third parties who take in the course<br />

of business without knowledge of the illegality. The victim's remedy is to<br />

pursue the oppressor and obtain just compen~ation.~<br />

If we rank the Islamic schools of thought in terms of how far they<br />

were willing to go to negate the effect of duress, the Shafi'is, Hanbalis, and<br />

Zahiris were willing to go to the furthest; to them the contract is void. They<br />

are followed by the Hanafi school; to them the contract is voidable. The<br />

MHliki school seems to be the most permissive in this regards; to them the<br />

contract is not binding.87


Islamic Studies, 30:3 (1991) 321<br />

CRIM<strong>IN</strong>AL ACTS: DESTRUCTION <strong>OF</strong> PROPERTY, RAPE <strong>AND</strong><br />

MURDER<br />

The Common Law<br />

The Common law excuses all crimes except murder, and, perhaps<br />

treason, if such crimes are committed under the influence of a well-grounded<br />

fear of imminent death or serious bodily injury from which there is no<br />

escape." The Common law. of crimes for the most part has refused to<br />

recognise threats to property, financial interests or reputation.@ Although<br />

the traditional rule refused to recoguise threats to third parties, the modem<br />

Common law has created an exception in the case of close relativesg0 Ad-<br />

ditionally, the Model Penal Code does not require that the threat be im-<br />

mediate or imminent. Nonetheless, it does not seem that courts have accepted<br />

this reform.91<br />

The Common law standard, regardless of the crime, is the same, and<br />

as such it lacks pr~portionality.~~ Therefore, whether someone is forced to<br />

destroy someone's car or sever his arm, the test is the same. Similarly, if<br />

threatened by death or serious injury a person can inflict a bodily injury on<br />

another of the same or even greater magnitude, or such person can inflict<br />

bodily injury on two or even ten people.<br />

Partly in response to the Common law's inflexible standards and lack<br />

of proportionality, some commentators have advocated an entirely subjective<br />

standard in criminal duress. Thus, according to Newman and Weitzer:<br />

Factors such as the opportunities for escape, the weakness of the<br />

duressed, the immediacy of the situation, the availment of self help,<br />

the strength of the threat, the gravity of the crime, the resistance<br />

shown or not shown, should go to the weight of the evidence and the<br />

jury should be called . . . to decide whether these nuances of evidence<br />

prove lack of free willed action or not.93<br />

This approach unwittingly achieves proportionality, in certain regards,<br />

since a person threatened by a serious injury to property might be excused<br />

if he commits a less than serious offense. Nonetheless, this approach does<br />

not focus on, nor in any systematic sense promote, proportionality. Rather,<br />

the focus is on the will of the duressed regardless of the gravity of his crime.<br />

Consequently, even if the avoided harm is less than the committed harm,<br />

the duressed is excused if his will was overcome.<br />

This approach is untenable for three reasons. First, it relies ori a legal<br />

construct in trying to undermine other legal constructs. Namely, the assump-


322 Islamic Studies, 30:3 (1991)<br />

tion that a person can only be duressed by death or serious bodily injury is<br />

a legal construct. But the idea of free will overcome, as discussed later, is<br />

itself a legal construct. Second, it assumes that the criminal law has no<br />

interest in promoting certain moral or social standards in society. It is incor-<br />

rect to assume that the legal system should recognise the fallibilities of people<br />

without regard to any moral or social standards. After all, any crime commit-<br />

ted is the product of some human weakness, and, yet, no one will be heard<br />

to argue that such frailities of the human character should absolve a criminal<br />

of wrongdoing. The reason the law creates exceptions such as duress, mis-<br />

take, or self-defense is for moral and policy reasons quite apart from the<br />

mem rea or state of mind that the defendant laboured under. Third, there<br />

is no possible moral or policy reason to absolve someone who, for example,<br />

kills a human being in order to avoid injury to his beloved dog. That is so<br />

even if the duressed's will was overcome by the threat to his beloved dog,<br />

it would not be proper to say that a person who wished to save his beloved<br />

library, for instance, is excused if he rapes, severs a limb, or kills a person.<br />

A subjective standard is, of course, fair to the individual in that it accommo-<br />

dates his particular temperament and personality. However, it is inherently<br />

unfair to society unless it is accompanied by the principle of proportionality.<br />

Aware of the difficulties inherent in the subjective approach, the<br />

Model Penal Code rejected it stating that,"[t]o make liability depend upon<br />

the fortitude of any given actor would be no less impractical or otherwise<br />

impolitic than to permit it to depend upon such other variables as intelligence<br />

or clarity of judgement, suggestibility or moral insight."94 The Model Penal<br />

Code adopts, what it calls a "partially objective" standard. The victim must<br />

establish that he has been coerced in circumstances under which a person<br />

of reasonable firmness in his situation would have been unable to resit."<br />

The size, strength, age or health but, not the temperament of the duressed,<br />

would be considered in deciding whether a reasonable person in the victim's<br />

circumstances would have acted similarly.% There is no specific type of<br />

threat required by the Model Penal Code. Except for threats to property or<br />

reputation, which the Commentary says, cannot as a matter of law exercise<br />

sufficient coercive power over a person of reasonable firmness, all other<br />

threats are recogni~ed.~~<br />

Nonetheless, the Model Penal Code, Section 2.09 is incomplete in<br />

the sense that it is standardless. For example, assume A threatens to kill B<br />

if B does not break the lkg of C, a competent football player, right before<br />

the superbowl. A fanatic sports fan jury might find that B acted unreasonably<br />

in breaking Cs leg. B is not excused by Section 2.09. However, the Model<br />

Penal Code remedies this situation by Section 3.02. Section 3.02 provides<br />

that a person is justified in committing any act if the harm sought to be<br />

avoided is greater than the harm of the act committed.% Hence, because


lskmic Studies, 30:3 (1991) 323<br />

of Section 3.02, not 2.09, B in our hypothetical example would be justified<br />

in breaking Cs leg. Likewise, a person who kills one to save the lives of<br />

ten others would be excused.99<br />

Despite Section 3.02 which compliments and completes Section 2.09,<br />

the Model Penal Code's approach still lacks proportionality in important<br />

respects. Assume, A threatens to kill B if B does not plant a bomb 'on an<br />

aircraft full of passengers. B does so and 300 people are killed if a jury<br />

decided that what B did was reasonable, Section 2.09 vindicates B. Section<br />

3.02 would not apply. In the alternative, assume A and three other people<br />

are stranded at sea. A consequently kills and consumes all three people to<br />

stay alive. If the jury decides that A acted reasonably, it leads to a very<br />

disproportionate result. In other words, while Section 3.02 pennits a person<br />

to claim he committed the lesser of two evils, Section 2.09 would pennit<br />

the greater of two evils to stand. Consequently, although the Model Penul<br />

Code is successful in achieving a certain degree of proportionality, it lacks<br />

in other respects.<br />

One should note, however, that the Model Penal Code is unique in<br />

that it pennits the defence of duress in the case of murder. The traditional<br />

Common law refused to recognise that murder is ever excused or justified<br />

by duress, calling murder the "inexcusable choice". As Blackstone put it,<br />

"he ought to die himself than to escape by the murder of an innocent<br />

person".'00 Most modem jurisdictions recoguk the murder exception to<br />

duress,''' but this exception has been heavily criticised by several writers.'''<br />

It is argued that it is totally unrealistic to expect people to be willing to<br />

sacrifice themselves rather than murder another. The Model Penal Code<br />

itself calls it hypocritical to require a standard of conduct that a person's<br />

judges are unable to live up to if placed in the same ~ituation.'~~ It is argued,<br />

if most.people placed in the same situation would succumb to and<br />

commit murder then the law loses its deterent value in imposing too high a<br />

standard. The law, in fact, would be imposing a meaningless penalty unjustified<br />

by any social value.'Oq<br />

This argument, however, is not persuasive on several counts. Firstly,<br />

it assumes that the only reason for penal laws is deterence. Quite apart from<br />

deterence, the law could affirm moral values such as the sanctity of human<br />

life. Thus, the law could play a morally educative role setting standards of<br />

conduct. '"<br />

Secondly, this argument is essentially limitless since it defers to social<br />

practices regardless of their moral content. If most people would give more<br />

value to the lives of a certain mcial group, should that be accepted? Or, if<br />

most people would kill a person to save their pets, should that be accepted?


324 Islamic Studies, 30:3 (1991)<br />

The law is replete with instances where regardless of the dominant social<br />

practices, a standard is set. Thirdly, the argument lacks proportionality.<br />

Perhaps, it would make some sense to argue that a person should kill a<br />

stranger to save his three young children but it makes no sense to permit a<br />

person who plants a bomb in a crowded train to claim duress.'"<br />

Most criminal acts implicate @e rights of innocent persons. The limits<br />

and inviolabilities (hwzlmdt) are great because, according to Muslim jurists,<br />

one should not repel injustice by committing injustice. Since the rights of<br />

innocent people involved, the standards are higher and the moral and policy<br />

concerns of the law are greater. Therefore, Ibn Hazat asserts that the victim<br />

of duress has a primary duty to resist committing acts that violate the rights<br />

of others. A Muslim, according to Ibn Hazm, should resist injustice rather<br />

than succumb and harm others.107 Muslim jurists,including Ibn Hazm, then<br />

add that if a Muslim resists committing murder, rape, or destruction of<br />

property and is injured or killed in the process, he is rewarded by ~od.'<br />

The absence of altruistic behaviour, however, does not mean that<br />

the victim of duress is held liable. In Islamic law in most cases, there are<br />

two separate and independent rulings. There is a religious ruling (pertaining<br />

to the person's liability in the hereafter) and, a secular ruling (pertaining to<br />

the person's criminal liability in this world). The religious xuling is designed<br />

to uphold the ideals of religion. The secular ruling accommodates human<br />

frailties while at the same time trying to uphold certain standards of conduct<br />

inspired by policy and religion.<br />

We shall deal with three categories of criminal adestruction of<br />

property, rape, and murder-+ illustrations of the effect of duress on crim-<br />

inal liabilities in Islamic law. Generally, as mentioned earlier, in the field<br />

of criminal liability, only compelling duress is admitted. Once it is established<br />

that compelling duress was used, a subjective inquiq determines whether<br />

the person was, in fact, coerced. The rejection of non-compelling duress,<br />

in most cases, in this area, is motivated by the principle of proportionality.<br />

A person should not commit a greater harm than that which is threatened.<br />

The less serious case is that pertaining to the destruction of property.<br />

A typical example of this would be when A forces B to burn C's house or,<br />

alternatively, A forces B to burn his own house. As to the religious rules,<br />

there is no liability on the dwessed if the criminal- act does not involve the<br />

rights of others. However, if the rights of others are involved, a person<br />

cannot succumb unless the duress involves compelling duress. Muslim jurists<br />

argued, however, that even non-com~lling duress can act as an excuse if


Islamic Studies, 30:3 (1991) 325<br />

the property damage is not extensive so that the threatened harm is greater<br />

than the committed harm.<br />

The secular ruling as to criminal liability mirrors the religious ruling.<br />

Nevertheless, there is an additional issue of who should compensate the<br />

innocent party (C in our example). On the issue of compensation there is<br />

much disagreement among Muslim jurists. Some jurists10g asserted that if<br />

the duress is compelling then responsibility for compensation should lie with<br />

the mercer and coerced. So to apply this to our example, C (the i~ocent<br />

party) can seek compensation from A (the coercer) or, alternatively, from<br />

B (the coerced). Other juristsl10 argued that if the duress is compelling then<br />

only the mercer, A is liable and not the coerced, B.<br />

If, on the other hand, the duress is not compelling, the majority of<br />

jurists decided that only the victim (B in our example) would be liable to<br />

the innocent party (C in our example). Some jurists, correctly in my opinion,<br />

argued that, in this case, although the victim (B) might not be forgiven for<br />

his behaviour on the final Day of Judgement, liability should still be shared<br />

by A and B, or at least C must be able to get compensation from either A<br />

or B. In other words, Cs options for compensation must not be limited<br />

because of B's frailty."'<br />

Rape is a more serious matter. For one, it involves serious criminal<br />

sanctions, additionally, it is absolutely prohibited. There are several possible<br />

scenarios involving non-consenting intercourse. A could physically attack C<br />

(a female or male) and rape her or him. Alternatively, A (a male or female)<br />

could threaten to kill C (a male or female) if he or she does not have sexual<br />

intercourse with him or her. Or, A could coerce B (a male or female) into<br />

raping C (a female or male).<br />

The first two scenarios involve cases of traditional rape. As a general<br />

rule, the rapist is always liable and raped is never liable. The third scenario<br />

is the one more typically discussed by the law of duress, and the question<br />

is whether B could commit rape in order to save himself from harm.<br />

Most Muslim jurists held that if the duress involves serious bodily<br />

injury or death (but not extensive destruction of property) then B is excused<br />

from all liability, religious or secular. On the other hand, if the duress is<br />

nonampelling, the duressed is liable in this life and the hereafter. Some<br />

jurists, however, held that rape can never be excused, the duressed should<br />

have sacrificed himself rather than commit the grevious harm of rape."2<br />

Finally, we deal with the case of murder. The religious rule, in Islam,<br />

is that murder is never justified. Therefore, no matter what type of duress


326 isiamic Studies, 30:3 (1991)<br />

is brought to bear upon a person she may not commit murder, and if she<br />

does, she will be liable on the Day of judgement. The religious rule affirms<br />

the moral principle that people should not prefer their own lives over others,<br />

and that only God should decide when a person should die.<br />

As to the secular ruling, there are two main schools. The first school<br />

holds that if the duress is compelling, only the coercer is held liable, and<br />

the duressed, for the most part, is excused. The justification propounded<br />

by this school was that by the utilization of compelling duress the coerced<br />

has become the instrument of the coercer, and, therefore, it is as if the<br />

duressed has not acted at all. Nonetheless, this justification cannot be taken<br />

seriously since the proponents of this school insisted that the duressed should<br />

receive some light punishment as well as be responsible for the blood money.<br />

The second school, that includes the majority, and the most plausible in my<br />

view, decided that both the coercer and the coerced should be punished.<br />

The coercer is punished for being the primary motivator of murder, and the<br />

coerced is punished for prefering his life to the life of others.'" The hypothet-<br />

ical example frequently cited by Muslim jurists is that of a boat in danger<br />

of capsizing. In order to save themselves, the passengers may throw over-<br />

board property such as goods and animals. But they may not lighten the<br />

load by throwing human beings overboard even if it means throwing over-<br />

.board a single passenger to save the rest. As a matter of religious and moral<br />

policy, the law should not appear to be granting preference to the life of<br />

some over others."'<br />

The second school's view is justified particularly when a coerced<br />

person kills one or several innocent individuals to save himself. There is no<br />

reason to condone a person who saves himself at the expense of others. The<br />

more di£6cult situation is, as above, when fewer people are killed W save<br />

a larger n ~ber of lives. For example, if A threatens to kill B's three children<br />

unless B kills C. Here the rules of proportionality, and the principle of<br />

committing the lesser evil would not support holding B liable for murder.<br />

But the hypothetical example mentioned above, and the unequivocal language<br />

used by Muslim jurists in not excusing murder under duress suggest<br />

a contrary result. As noted eariier, Islamic law seems to premise its position<br />

on a belief that a human being should not prefer a life or, even a number<br />

of lives, over others. People should not be in the business of drawing preferences<br />

quantitatively or qualitatively between lives. As such, Islamic law does<br />

noi seem concerned with wrximizing social utility by sacrificing the least<br />

number of lives. Rather it upholds a principle founded on religious basis,<br />

as a goal in itself. All life is equally inviolable, and the law should not get<br />

involved in dangerous task of preferential selection.<br />

However, Muslim jurists dealt with the most straightforward situation,<br />

i.e. when A coerces B to murder C, or when A and B faced with starvation


lslamic Studies, 30:3 (1991) 327<br />

kill and consume C. Muslim jurists did not deal with the more difficult<br />

examples that might arise under 'a form of duress or necessity, and that<br />

might pose a serious challenge to the Islamic response to the problem. For<br />

instance, assume Ali and Ibrahim wete climbing a mountain while being<br />

roped together for protection. Ibrahim slips and fells, but Ali grip a moun-<br />

tain edge and Ibrahim dangles down supported only by Ali. Ibrahim is<br />

unconscious, and Ali cannot pull him up. Either Ali cuts the rope, kills<br />

Ibrahim but saves himself, or he will be overcome by exhaustion, and both<br />

Ali and Ibrahim will plunge to their death."' Ali cuts the rope, Ibrahim<br />

dies and Ali is saved.<br />

For another difficult hypothetical position let us assume Ali, an en-<br />

gineer, works on a dam. 'helve men are busily working on a farm below,<br />

Ali suddently notices serious over-floading. Either he opens the dam gates,<br />

drowning the twelve men and saving himself or he does not open the gates<br />

and drowns himself and a town lying behind the dam. There is no time to<br />

warn the twelve farmers below. Ali opens the gates, saves himself and the<br />

town but kills the twelve men.l16 The question in both hypothetical positions<br />

is: Can Ali be held responsible for murder? Ones moral intuition is to say<br />

no. More importantly, Islamic law does not offer a definitive answer."'<br />

One suspects that a serious answer will only emerge when a real case<br />

with similar facts arises in a court applying Islamic law.<br />

Another point of comparison between the Common and Islamic laws<br />

of duress is the area of superior orden. The legal doctrine of "superior<br />

order$' was much debated in the West after the Second World War. Basi-<br />

cally, as a criminal law concept, it is a defence raised by those accused of<br />

obeying illegal d en of superion (for example, a superior orden a soldier<br />

to execute a prisoner of war). The majority opinion in Common law jurispru-<br />

dence is that a superior order is a defence only if the follower reasonably<br />

and honestly believed that it was legal at the time he obeyed it. The Model<br />

Penal Code goes further in holding that members of the armed forces are<br />

insdated from liability in civil courts unless they had actual knowledge that<br />

the superior order was illegal. The fact that a person of o&ary intelligence<br />

would have known that the order was illegal is insu£ficient, acmrding to the<br />

Model Penal Code. Rather, the person must have actual knowledge and<br />

belief that the order was, in fact, illegal.11g<br />

Muslim jurists discussed a similar doctrine usually under the heading<br />

of amr al-sul* (the order of the ruler). The discussion centred on the legal<br />

consequences of an illegal order by a superior to one of his agents. Muslim


328 Islamic Studies, 30:3 (1991)<br />

jurists argued that the agent should be liable for any illegal orders implemented<br />

if the agent knew of their illegality. Some jurists added that the<br />

agent is also liable if he should have known of the illegality of the orders,<br />

either because of the superiors prior illegal course of conduct or becam of<br />

the agent's own presumed level of kn~wledge.~ Therefore, if the superior<br />

is well-known for his injustice, the agent will not be allowed to claim ignorance<br />

of the illegality of the orders. Similarly, if the agent is a knowledgeable<br />

person he cannot be excused.<br />

Both legal systems, quite apart from any question of an overcome<br />

will, reach a policy determination that an agent should not be able to insulate<br />

himself from liability by claiming he was simply following orders. The reasons<br />

for this are quite obvious. If the law decided that the agent should have<br />

known the illegality of the orders issued to him, the agent's subdued state<br />

of mind will not vindicate him as a matter of law. Once again, this de-<br />

monstrates that it is not so much the state of mind of the coerced that<br />

motivates the law of duress as it is the moral and policy standards that the<br />

law hopes to set.<br />

APPRAISAL<br />

The fact that there is a causal co~ection between a person's behaviour<br />

and an act does not necessarily mean that the person is legally responsible<br />

for such an act. There is a significant difference between, what Wertheimer<br />

calls, "ascription of responsibility" and "reasonability simp~iciter".'~'<br />

Beyond factual causation, the responsibility of a person for his actions in<br />

the moral or ethical sense can and should be taken into account. But countervailing<br />

policy reasons or even codlicting moral considerations might interfere<br />

to modify the co~ection between responsibility and liability. Such<br />

is the case, for example, with strict liability or statutory rape legislati~n.'~~<br />

The law, for the most part, does not hold a person liable if he commits<br />

an act under the pressure of wrongful duress. Not every duress, however,<br />

is wrongful, and not every wrongful duress merits a legal vindication. Rather,<br />

the relevant question to pose is: when is it appropriate to relieve a duressed<br />

person from liability for his acts?'"<br />

From the theoretical point of view, there are two approaches to this<br />

question; empirical or mora~ised.'~ One approach is to analyse duress basically<br />

as an empirical fact. Did the threat terrify the victim? Is there a causal<br />

co~ection between the psychological state and the act committed? Could<br />

the victim have done anything other than yield to the pressure exerted upon<br />

her?


Islamic Studies, 30:3 (1991) 329<br />

A different approach is to ask, did the coercer have a right to threaten?<br />

Did the threatened have right to succumb to the pressure? Does the victim<br />

owe any obligations to others including the coercer? A third approach, I<br />

propose, is to combine both inquiries, and to incorporate a policy, based<br />

inquiry. This third approach would ask three essential questions: (1) Did<br />

the duressed in fact feel forced to do what he did? (2) Assuming that prop<br />

ortionality and committing the lesser evil are requirements of fairness, was<br />

what the duressed did fair to society or did the duressed unfairly violate the<br />

rights of others? (3) Are there any policy questions, including moral and<br />

constitutional, that need to be considered? Policy questions, for instance,<br />

could include concerns about due process guarantees against coerced confes-<br />

sions, finality of adoptions, or the necessity of obtaining testimony even if<br />

the witness feels intimidated and threatened.<br />

Islamic law roughly follows this approach, it begins by asking the last<br />

question first. Furthermore, Islamic law phrases the last question in terms<br />

of religious policy. Hence, as a matter of religious policy if the rights of<br />

innocent people, other than the rights of the coerced, are involved, the law<br />

demands a higher level of perseverance and endurance. Consequently, duress<br />

is divided into two types, compelling and non-compelling. The law excuses<br />

the act committed depending on the type of duress inflicted. In civil acts,<br />

in most cases, only the rights of the coerced are involved and, therefore,<br />

both types of duress are recognised. The dichotomy between compelling<br />

and non-compelling duress is also necessitated by the second prong. However<br />

this dichotomy alone cannotachieve proportionality. Although compelling<br />

duress will excuse serious crimes, it will not excuse all serious crimes whatever<br />

the scale.<br />

.Also, as a matter of religious policy, Muslim jurists maintain that<br />

murder is never excused. Additionally, religious policy determines if third<br />

party threats are recognised. As discussed, Ibn Hazm, for example, maintains<br />

that the policy of brotherhood between Muslims necessitates recognising<br />

threats directed at strangers.125 What is religious policy in Islam is informed<br />

by textual sources such as the Qur'h and the Sunnuh (the Traditions of the<br />

Prophet and his ~om~anions).'~ But, as noticed from the diversity of opinions<br />

within Islamic law, that does not preclude the possibility of disagreement<br />

among jurists nor does that necessarily create a well-defined set of religious<br />

policies.<br />

Furthermore, religious policy is not the only type of policy inquiry<br />

permitted in Islamic jurisprudence. Of course, Muslim Jurists did not deal<br />

with modem problems such as whether plea bargains are coerced. Nonethe-<br />

less, policy could be based on customs or social practices as long as these<br />

customs do not violate fundamental religious tenets.ln


330 Islamic Studies, 30:3 (1991)<br />

After passing the threshold question of religious or social policy, the<br />

subjective feelings of the coerced are considered, and, finally, the question<br />

of fairness is addressed. Therefore, the act committed must be the lesser of<br />

two evils as well as proportional and not excessive. Naturally, these limiting<br />

guidelines would play a more significant role in criminal law than in civil<br />

acts. The main virtue of the Islamic approach lies in its inner coherence and<br />

systematic presentation, and in the fact that it has clearly realized that the .<br />

law plays a standard setting role in the field of duress.<br />

The Common law, unlike Islamic law, does not offer a methodolog-<br />

ically systematic response to duress. As noted earlier, the traditional Com-<br />

mon law did pursue a categorical approach. And as seen, Blackstone's jus-<br />

tification for the murder exception is that the sdciety cannot forgive when<br />

the rights of God are involved. But this approach was never elaborated or<br />

developed.la In modern times, as to the question when is it appropriate to<br />

relieve a duressed person from liability for his acts, the Common law gives<br />

various answers. In civil cases, a person is not liable if his will is overcome.<br />

In criminal cases, the majority opinion is that a person is not liable if his<br />

response to duress is reasonable. The basis for the distinction is not de-<br />

veloped. More importantly, it is not clear what does an "overcome will" or<br />

"reasonableness" mean.<br />

A number of scholars have criticised the overborne or overcome will<br />

approach. P.S. Atiyah even recommends that the theory "be consigned to<br />

the 'historical ~cra~hea~".'*~<br />

The difficulty arises from the fact that in the course of life many<br />

decisions, although not the result of duress, are made under so called "no<br />

choice" conditions.lM For example, a person might be forced to accept a<br />

job he dislikes simply because there is no other option, other than starvation.<br />

Or, a person might be forced to take a loan to avoid becoming homeless or<br />

a person might be forced to go to a doctor and pay the medical fee in order<br />

to avoid the risk of death to his sick daughter. In other words, duress, in<br />

the Literal sense, exists in every aspect of life. Simply because humans have<br />

necessities, certain conditions are by their nature coercive.<br />

The duress recognised by law is a legal construct based on vague<br />

notions of fair play, equity and social and moral policy. As Atiyah contends,<br />

duress is only partly a question .of fact, but also a question of law. The<br />

overcome will theory gives the mistaken impression that duress is a question<br />

of psychology.'3' The fact that policy issues permeate the whole legal a p<br />

proach is quite clear. For example, it has been held that a fear of the death<br />

penalty does not render a plea bargain agreement coerced.132 Likewise, a<br />

fear of serious bodily harm does not necessarily excuse prison escapes.'33


lslamic Studies, 30:3 (1991) 33 1<br />

In these, and other fields of legal duress, there are contravening social<br />

problems that require balancing the psychology of the duressed with the<br />

needs of society. Therefore, the legal approach to the subjective feelings of<br />

the coerced depends on the particular area of law under considerati~n.'~~ I<br />

am not arguing that considerations of policy or morality should render a<br />

subjective inquiry entirely irrelevant. But as with most issues, law has to<br />

balance rights and such a balance renders the language of an overcome will<br />

inappropriate. 13'<br />

Nevertheless, from a comparative perspective, the Islamic approach<br />

would not yield very different results from those reached by the Common<br />

law. Both systems would not exclude most types of duress, and both would<br />

focus on the factual question of the coerced's state of mind. Nonetheless,<br />

Islamic law would, more consistently with its premises, be able to admit<br />

that it is balancing the interests of the individual with that of society. 'Ihree<br />

examples might demonstrate the similarities and differences.<br />

Assume that a wife threatens to expose her ex-spouse's extramarital<br />

affair unless he agrees to- certain property concessions. At Common law,<br />

there is some evidence that this threat would not be considered coercive.136<br />

Islamic law would probably consider such a threat coercive as a matter of<br />

religious policy. Unproven accusations of infidelity are a criminal offense,<br />

and the burden for proving infidelity is ins~mountable.'~' m e remaining<br />

question, since the type of duress is recognised, is what impact did such a<br />

threat have on the coerced's mind. This form of threat to reputation would<br />

probably also be recognised in criminal cases, but it is not clear whether it<br />

would be considered compelling or non-ompelling duress.13' Probably, like<br />

threats to property, the classification would depend on the extent of expezted<br />

damage to the coerced.<br />

To take a different scenario, assume that A threatens to destroy B's<br />

supply of cocaine if B, a drug dealer, does not sign a contract on a collateral<br />

matter. Assume further that B's will was, in fact, overcome by A's threat.<br />

Islamic law, can, consistently with its premises, refuse to recognise this type<br />

of threat as legal duress. This is because Islamic law's approach only gets<br />

to the coerced's mind after it decides as a matter of policy that the type of<br />

duress inflicted is actionable. The Common law probably would also not<br />

reoognise this type of duress. But it can only do so by referring to elements<br />

external to the coerced's will. The threat here might be wrongful but that<br />

does not necessarily olean it is recognisable by law.<br />

A final example will further help contrast the approaches. In King<br />

v. Lewis, an African-American farmer made statements before a grand jury<br />

to the effect that the county's sheriff is stealing money and accepting bribes.


332 klamic Studies, 30:3 (1991)<br />

Upon hearing these statements the sheriff vigorously expressed his displeasure.<br />

Fearing harm, the h e r and his brothers went to meet the sheriff.<br />

The sheriff made statements to the effect that the farmer had slandered him,<br />

and, again expressed his anger. 'Ihe sheriff advised the farmer to go meet<br />

the sheriff's attorney to settle the matter. Upon visiting the sheriff's attorney,<br />

the attorney stated that it was good thing the farmer came to see him because<br />

he was getting ready to attach everything the farmer owned for a 3000 dollar<br />

slander suit. After protestations of poverty, the farmer agreed to a 5000<br />

dollar settlement. The farmer later sued claiming that the settlement was<br />

obtained under duress. A jury found in favour of plaintiff, and defendant's<br />

motion for a new trial was denied. 'Ihe Supreme Court of Georgia reversed<br />

finding no evidence of duress. 'Ihe Court stated: "With an appreciation of<br />

the veneration and sometimes fear in which the 'high sherifP is held, especially<br />

by some members of the coloured citizens in this southern country,<br />

we can well understand how plaintiff, when he began to hear rumblings of<br />

the sheriff's wrath could have become frightened and fearful of the comequences<br />

to himself'. Nonetheless, the Court held that even if this fear resulted<br />

in his signing the contract that, "does not measure up to the legal definition<br />

of duress". The duress exerted upon plaintiff, according to the Court, came<br />

from within and not from with0~t.l~~<br />

If a standard to overcome will is accepted, the Court's holding is of<br />

doubtful validity.14' 'Ihe existence of an explicit threat from the sheriff<br />

should be irrelevant. If the plainti£f's will was overcome by the coercive<br />

situation, it would seem there is no reason to deny relief.<br />

As to Islamic law, we have already encountered Sarakhsi's analysis<br />

as to commands or requests by superiors known for their injustice or oppres-<br />

sion.14' Islamic law would deal first with the question of whether the practices<br />

of officials in a society call for recognition for this type of duress. The<br />

practices of the particular official are largely immaterial; the essential fact<br />

is whether the social circumstance call for added protection to a segment of<br />

society or all of society.142 Subsequently, the subjective feelings of plaintiff<br />

would be examined to determine if he was, in fact, coerced. The merit of<br />

this approach is that it would force a court to explicitly state its policy analysis.<br />

'Ihe standard of reasonableness pursued by the Common law in the<br />

criminal context seems to partly solve this problem. In explaining why a<br />

certain behaviour is reasonable, a court necessarily has to articulate the<br />

social and moral standards relied on. But the relevance of "reasonableness"<br />

to the law of duress is not readily apparent. It is not clear why is it important<br />

that a coerced person act reasonably, or even if it is possible. Realistically,<br />

it is entirely unreasonable to expect people panicking under the threat of<br />

an impending serious injury to act reasonably. In all likelihood, if placed


Ishmic Studies, 30:3 (1991) 333<br />

under the threat of imminent danger, a person will panic and react on<br />

impulse.'43 Nevertheless, to say that the reasonableness standard is unrealis-<br />

tic is not necessarily to say it is inappropriate.<br />

The reasonableness standard is too indefinite. What is reasonable for<br />

a particular person will vary with his or her personal characteristi~s.'~~ The<br />

indefinitness does not neoessarily arise from the need to individualize the<br />

inquiry, but because reasonableness essentially involves a hindsight evaluation<br />

of the moral appropriatness of the coerced's response to duress. To say<br />

someone acted reasonably under the circumstances is to say no more than<br />

that society approves or, at least, cannot condemn the coerced's rea~ti0n.l~~<br />

As Fletcher succinctly puts it:<br />

Indeed, the appeal of the reasonable man is precisely that he permits<br />

one, covertly, to make the same judgement that one would make in<br />

openly discussing the defendant's moral responsibility for his conduct.<br />

Yet if that is the case, one wonders why common law judges bother<br />

with the circumvention; why not simply ask whether the accused<br />

ought to have been able to resist the pressure exerted on him?146<br />

- Fletcher, however, argues that the law's approach to duress should<br />

not be based on rules. Rather it should focus on an individualized approach.<br />

However, rules are important not only for predictability, but also for affirm-<br />

ing standards of conduct. Such standards should be based on moral and<br />

social considerations and notions of fairness such as proportionality.<br />

It should be stressed that Islamic law does not ignore the individual's<br />

feelings. After all, there is something inherently moral about considering<br />

the individual feelings of a person in a difficult predicament. But that cannot<br />

be the sole consideration. At the same time, Islamic law does not commit<br />

itself to upholding vague moral standards such as "reasonableness". Con-<br />

sequently, it can limit itself to recognising only certain forms of duress in<br />

proportion to the interest at stake. Importantly, based on moral and social<br />

considerations, rules elucidating standards of conduct can provide an element<br />

of predictability in the law.<br />

But while adopting a methodology capable of providing predictability,<br />

Islamic law lacks in im*rtant respects. Foremost, Islamic law, as it now<br />

exists, speaks in too many voices. Hence many contradictory evaluations<br />

and determinations of the admissible types of duress and relevant standards<br />

of conduct can be found. Some voices, for example, have excused murder<br />

or, at least, held that the defendant will not be punished in this life although<br />

saving themselves at the expense of others.'" Further confusion is created<br />

by the fact that some jurists express rules or exclusions unsupported by any


334 Islamic Studies, 30:3 (1991)<br />

possible religious, moral or social policy. For example, there seems to be<br />

no rational policy behind refusing to admit duress directed at third parties<br />

especially relatives and loved ones.'48<br />

More importantly, Islamic law fails to comprehensively explain the<br />

proper balance between the rights of society, religion and*individual. The<br />

approach of saying some choices are inexcusable as a matter of law is fundamentally<br />

correct, but the essential question is what are the limits. For example,<br />

take a person who, threatened by rape, escapes from prison. Rape,<br />

according to Islamic law, is a grevious bodily injury and, thus, compelling<br />

duress. ~utcbuld society's interest in maintaining order in prisons be equated<br />

with society's interest in the inviolability of life, and, therefore, a threat of<br />

rape would not excuse an escape? In other words, as there is a murder<br />

exception, could there be a prison escape exception? It seems that there is<br />

something very immoral in saying, as a matter of law, people should withstand<br />

rape rather than escape. Probably, most Muslim jurists would insist that<br />

rape is compelling duress, and as long as the crime annitted is proportional<br />

to the threatened harm there is no liability. Hence a threat of rape would<br />

excuse prison escapes. Nonetheless, this response is unsatisfactory because<br />

if one recognises a murder exception, other exceptions could be created.<br />

Fundamentally, while Muslim jurists worked out an appropriate methodology,<br />

they have failed to fully explain the value system or moral theory that<br />

underlies this meth~dology.'~~ This lack of clarity is a product of the medieval<br />

historical period in which Islamic law was formulated, and also a product<br />

of the difficulties Islamic law has encountered in the modem w~rld.'~<br />

Since the Colonial era, and to this day, most Muslim countries have<br />

abandoned Islamic law in favour of Western legal systems, especially the<br />

Civil law system.''' This is unfortunate not only because Islamic law has<br />

been denied the opportunity for development, but also because Islamic law<br />

has been largely removed from the international legal discourse. However,<br />

incomplete legal systems can both inform and reform each other. Implicitly,<br />

comparative studies are indispensable for this task. Frequently, the specific<br />

rules adduced by a legal systems are not as probative and insightful as the<br />

methodology or approach adopted. In this regard, the main contribution of<br />

Islamic law in the field of duress is its methodology.<br />

As Alan Watson has stressed, a comparative approach to the study<br />

of law is not only significant for understanding the relationship of law to<br />

society, but also for the practical value of reform through selective borrowing.'"<br />

Beyond outright legal borrowing, comparative studies could inspire<br />

innovative thinking that transcends the'constraining influence of precedent,<br />

and the mental sets of a particular legal cult~re.''~ The fact that the Islamic


law of duress is in need of development and elaboration does not negate<br />

the validity of its approach. This approach could inspire the Common law<br />

towards a more systematic and coherent approach to duress.<br />

NOTES <strong>AND</strong> REFERENCES<br />

The term "duress", instead of coercion or compulsion, will be used in most pans of this<br />

essay. Coercion in Common law refers to a special defence available to wives who commit<br />

an illegal act in the prcscnce of their husbands. Smith and Hogan, C M Low (5th 4..<br />

1983) p. 209; Bishop, Commmtariu on the C M Lmv, vol. 1 (7th ed., 1882). p. 224.<br />

The justification for this rule as explained by Francis Bacon is that "the law intends [a<br />

woman] to have no will, in regard of the subjection and obedience she owes her husband".<br />

F. Bacon, "A Collection of Some Principal Rules and Maxims of the Common Laws of<br />

England," in Thc Works of Francis Emon, vol. 13, ed. B. Montague, (831). pp. 161; and<br />

see, W. Blackstone, Blacksfone's Commentaries, ed. G. Tucker (18[n), bk. N, chap. 11, p.<br />

27, noting that the rule is at least a thousand years old. But this defence is now becoming<br />

defunct. W. Lafave and A. Scott, Handbook on Criminal Low (1972). pp. 3W81; Perkins.<br />

Criminal Law (2nd cd., 1969). p. 918. But see, Edwards, "Compulsion, Coercion and<br />

Criminal Responsibility," 14 Mod. L. Rev. 297,312-13 (1951), who argues for the retention<br />

of the special defence of coercion. Compulsion seems to apply to situations where one person<br />

physically form a person to commit an act by the application of direct force, for example,<br />

grabbing a person's hand and striking another with it. See H. Fingarette. "Victimization: A<br />

Legalist Analysis of Coercion, Deception, Undue Influence and Excusable Prison Excape",<br />

42 Wash. & Lee L. Rev. 65, 65 n. 1 (1985); 1. Dennis, "Duress, Murder and Criminal<br />

Responsibility," % Low Q. Rev. U)8.u#1 n. 1 (1980). Also see Edwards, Id.. p. 297 for the<br />

differences between the !ern. The Arabic term for duma b -but it will not be used<br />

in this essay for the sake of consistency.<br />

Blackstone, Commenfarics, p. 27. Blackstone reasons that punishment is only appropriate<br />

for the abuse of the will given to people by God. Francis Bscon repeats the similar rhetoric:<br />

"The law chargeth no man with default where the act is compulsory and not voluntaj, and<br />

where there is not a consent and election; and, therefore, if either there be an impossibility<br />

for a man to do otherwise, or so great a perturbation of the judgement and reason as in<br />

presumption-of law man's nature cannot overcome, such necessity cameth a privilege in<br />

itself." F. Bacon, Colkchbn, p. 160.<br />

D. Bradley, "Duress and Arranged Marriages," 46 Mod. L. Rev. 499 (1983); L.N. Brown,<br />

"Shotgun Marriage," 42 Tul. L. Rev. 837 (1%8); Robert Brown, "Dwess and Fraud as<br />

Ground for Annulment of Marriage," 10 Znd. L. J. 471 (1935); H. Abrams, "Systematic<br />

Coercion: Unconstitutional Conditions in the Criminal Law," 72 1. Crim. L. & Criminology<br />

128 (1981); C. Brunk. "The Problem of Voluntariness and Coercion in the Negotiated Plea,"<br />

13 L. & Soc'y Rev. 527 (1979); Gammty v. New Jew, 385, US. 493 (1967); S. Mass, '"The<br />

Dilemma of the Intimidated Witness in Federal Organized Crime Prosecutions: Choosing<br />

Among the Fear of Reprisals, the Contempt Powers of the Court, and the Witness protection<br />

Programme," 50 Fordham L. Rev. 582,590410 (1982); and see, A. Wertheimer, Coercion<br />

(1987) pp. 54144.<br />

See, G. Alexander, "Freedom, Coercion and the Law of Servitudes," 73 Cornell L. Rev.<br />

883 (1988); J. Haag, "Involuntary Servitude: An Eighteenth-Century Concept in Search of<br />

Twentieth-Century Definition," 19 Pac. L.J. 873 (1988).<br />

See for example. Note, "The Effect of Duress on the Iranian Hostage Settlement Agreement,"<br />

14 Vand, J. Tranmnl'l L. Rev., 847 (Fall, 1981); and Comment, "Coercion, Blackmail,<br />

and the Limits of Protected Speech," 131 (1. of PA L. Rev. 1469 (1983).


Islamic Studies, 30:3 (1991)<br />

For a useful discussion see Hale. "Bargaining, Duress and Economic Liberty." 43 Cdum.<br />

L. Rev. 603 (1943); J. Dawson, "Economic Duress: An Essay in Perspective," 45 Mich. L.<br />

Rev. 253. (1947).<br />

See, D. Zimmerman, "Coercive Wage Offers," 10 Phil. and Pub. Aff. 121 (1981): G.<br />

Dworkin, "Compulsion and Moral Concepts," 78, Ethh 227 (1968); also see, discussion in<br />

Wettheimcr. Coacion, pp. 242-266.<br />

fingarctte, "Vition." 6546.<br />

See, "Lafavette Dramatic Reductions Inc. v. Ferank." 305 Mich 193, 9 N. W. 2d 57,65<br />

(1943) relying on Webster's Ncw Intrmotional Dictionary 2d Ed. for a definition of dwess<br />

and coercion; G. Orchard. "The Defence of Compulsion." 9 New Zcoland UniwrsiricJ L.<br />

Rev. 105 (Dec. 1980)<br />

The MejeUe, Tysar Demetridas, Haqqi Effendi, trans. (Lahore: Punjab Educptid Pms.<br />

1%7). The MejeUe was compiled between 1869 and 1876 as a codification of Hanafi Muslim<br />

Civil law. A similar definition is in the Iraqi Civil Codc article 112 (Duress is to compel a<br />

person, without right to do something which he does not consent to) bn Hajar al-'Asqallani,<br />

Fat+ af-Bdrifi Sharh af-BuWlriri (Beirut: Ma'arif, n.d.), vol. 12, p. 311, defines duress as<br />

"forcing someone to do something which he does mt wish to do". See also al-Darayni,<br />

af-Tardifi'l 'Uqrid wa'l-MubddcJirr (Jadah: Dar al-Sh-, 1982). p. 362 (Duress is to force<br />

someone to do an act that he does not wish to do if it had not been for the force applied<br />

against him) and B+r al-'UJBm, 'Uytib al-lrcidoh fi'l Shaniah af-lshniyyah (Beirut: Dar<br />

al-Zahri, 1984) p. 257 (Duress is to force someone to commit an act that he would not have<br />

otherwise committed if it had not been for the fear of harm). Although offering a definition<br />

of actual duress, these jurists are not describing legally recognisabk duress.<br />

Nall v. Commonwealth, 208 Ky 700,271, S.W. 1059 (1925); State v CIay 220 Iowa 1191,264<br />

N.W. 77, 83, (1935); Burns v. State, 89, Ga. 527, 15, S.E. 748 (1892); Baine v. State, 67<br />

Miss 557.7 So. 408 (1890): United States v. Contentc+Pachon, 723. F. 2d. 691,693-W (9th<br />

Cir. 1984).<br />

17 C.J.S. Conrroc~, kc. 168 (1955); 25 Am. Jur. 2d. "Duress and Undue Influence" sec. 1<br />

(1%4); Ruhenstein v. Rubenstein, 20 N.J, 359 120 A. 2d. 11, 14 (1956); State v. Gann, 244<br />

N.W. 2d 746,752 (N.D. 1976); Talmadge v. Robinson, 158 Ohio St. 333,109 N.E. 2d 404,<br />

500 (1952); B v. Boume (1952) 36 Crim. App. R. 125, 128 (1952); R.v. Hudson, [I9711 1<br />

All. E.R. 244, 246-47,<br />

See. Mpdel P d Code (MPC) set: 2.09 (Of6cial Draft. 1962); Lafave and Scott. Handbook<br />

374; State v. Toscano 74 N.J. 421,378 A. 2d 755.765 (1977); Lafavette Dramatic Rodudions<br />

Inc. v. Ferenk, 305 Mich. 193.9 N.W. 2d 57.65 (1943); see, Hochman v. Zigler's Incorpo-<br />

rated, 50 A. 2d. 97.99 (N. J. 1%).<br />

17. C3.S. Confmcfs, sec. 174 United States v. Hasttell, 26 Fed. Cas. 207 (Pa. Cu Ct. 1823);<br />

Calamari and Perrillb, The Low of Confmcrs (1987). p. 337.<br />

Commonwealth v. Refitt, 149 Ky. 300,148, S.W. 48 (1912); Moore v. State, 23 Ala. App.<br />

432, 127 So. 796 (1930); People v. Ricker, 45 111,2d. 562,262. N.E. 2d. 456 (1970); State<br />

v. Toscano, 74 N.J. 421, 378 A. 2d. 755, 761, (1977); 25 Am. Jw. 2d. "Duress." sec. 11;<br />

Pdha d Boyce. Crimind hw (l!J82), p. 1061; BlacLstoac, Cornmcnforics, bk. 1, chap.<br />

1. pp. 1W31; M e. Second Institute 483 (1648).<br />

Bishop, The Criminaf law (1892). vol. 1, p. 207;17C.J.S.,Conbacrr, sec. 179; 25Am. Jur.<br />

2d, "Duress" sec. 22; Edwards, Compulsion, p. 334, but see Bush v. People, 10 colo. 566,<br />

16 Pac. 290 (1888) (recognising a serious injury directed against a brother).<br />

Bums v. State, 89 Ga. 527, 15 S.E. 748 (1892); Baine v. State. 67 Miss. 557, 7 So. 408<br />

(1890); D'Aquino v. United States, 192 F. 2d. 338,358 (9th Cir. 1951); Burton v. State, 51<br />

Tex. Crim. 1%. 101 S.W. 226 (1907); G. Williams. Textbook On Criminul h w, 580(1978);<br />

17 C.J.S. Contmcu, sec. 168.<br />

Damon, Economic Duress, p. 255; L. Newman and L. Weitzer, ''Dwess. Free Will and<br />

the Criminal Law." 30 S. Cd. L. Rev. 313,329-331 (1957); 25 Am. Jw. 2d. "Dunu." sec.<br />

11; State v. Toscano, 74 N.J. 421, 378 A. 2d. 755, 762, (1977).<br />

L. Newman and L. Weitzer. "Duress, Free Will," 315. 'Ibe approach of the common law<br />

was far from unusual. In fact, most anaent legal systems approached the subject with the


Islamic Studies, 30:3 (1991) 337<br />

same conservatism. For example, at Roman law, "'Mchrc (duress) consisted in threats of<br />

pbykal hum, death, emlavement, accusation on a capital charge or of an attack upon the<br />

chastity of the prty so threatened or of a member of his family; threats of merely economic<br />

damage would not suflia." Thomas. Tatbook of Romon law (Amsterdam: North-Holland<br />

Publishing Co., 1976). p. 227. Jwrimimf Digest, however, states that fear of infamy is not<br />

amred by the mthh edict. See Juuinian's Digest, Book 4. Title 2, section 7 Watson<br />

bum. 7%~ Digw of Jy1rinion (Philadelphia: Univ. of Pem Ress, 1985) vol. 1 at p. 114.<br />

Rubenstein v. Rubenstein, 20 N.J. 359,120 A. 2d. 11,15 (1996); Ensign v. Home for Jewish<br />

Aged, 274 S. W. 2d. 5U2 (Mo. App. 1955); Orchard, Defence of compulsion, 11 1; G. Fridman,<br />

"Duress in the Canadian and English Law of Restitution: A Comparison," 11 no. 1 Ddho11sie<br />

L.J. 47. XL52 (Sept. 1987); 17 C.J.S. Controctr, sec 175, p. 959-%0.<br />

See, 17 C.J.S. Contracts, sec. 172, 954-956, sec. 175 at %2 and sec. 177, 966-%7; 25 Am.<br />

Jur. 2d. "Duress," sec. 18. Hochman v. Zigler's Incorporated, 50 A. 2d. 97, 100 (N.J. Ch.<br />

1946); Miller v. Elsele. 168 A. 426,430 (N.J. 1933); Uniform Corrrmcnicrl Code, sec. 2-3U2<br />

(1%2) (Pqmses). "The act or heat upon which a claim of coercion is predicated must<br />

only be wrongful in a moral sense, not necessarily a legal one." Justice Holmes earlier on<br />

held that whether the threat is unlawful or not is not determinative. Sallsbee v. Webber.<br />

171 Maos, 378, 50 N.E. 555 (1898). However, some modem courts continued to state that<br />

it is never duress to threaten to do what one has a legal right to do, for example, Fidelity<br />

& Casuality Co. of N.Y. v. United States, 490 F. 2d. %0, !766 (Ct. CI. 1974). But see,<br />

Rubenstein v. Rubenstein, 20 N.J. 359, 120 A. 2d. 11, 15 (1956).<br />

See, Fingarette, Vidimizcrtin, p. 109, Fridman, Canadian and English law, pp. 51-52 (expressing<br />

the view that British law is unclear on this point); Hale, Bargaining, 613-615; N. Rafferty,<br />

'The Element of Wrongful Resure in A Finding of Duress," 18, no. 3 Alkm L. Rev. 431<br />

(I=); Sutton, "Duress by Threatened Breach of Contract," 20 McGill L.J. 544 (1974);<br />

Dalzell, "Duress by Economic Pressure," 20 N.C.L. Rev. 341 (1942); J. Dawson, "Duress<br />

Through Civil Litigation". 45 Mich. L. Rev. 571 (1947).<br />

Wer(beimervthst m dl - m a twopronedysisisat work. One, what the<br />

lntbor alb a "cboia pmq" ia which tbe coart iaqr6ra rhetber the coenrr's "jmqod<br />

rruta a cboia aihution for [the merad] such thst [the d] has no alternative but to<br />

do I". lko, a "pupad prone" m which the mutt inquirts "whether it i wrong for [the<br />

anrar] to make such a prcqxmal to [the menad]". Wertheimer argues thst courts adopt a<br />

~.admonlrppo;rhm~bdh~.Butwhikthepmposslprmg:'does<br />

matdtheaat"meivil~,thecboiapronemmmdm~tiveincriminalcsrres.<br />

(Wertheimer. Canion, pp. 17273; 274-75). Only a selective reading d the came law csn<br />

support thir adysk. But even if this is, m fact. the underlying philosophical reasoning<br />

behind the cauq this h not the law. The case law does not reflect such a coherent and<br />

It is difficult to make a uniform presentation of Islamic law since, not unlike the Common<br />

law, there is no single authoritative source of law. Islamic law is represented in the writings<br />

of several medieval Muslim jurists. mere are five major Sunni schools of law, ShWi, Hanafi,<br />

MPi, Wbali and w, as well as, at least, two Shi'ite schools. When I use the term<br />

:slatkc law, I mean the opinion of the majority of the jurists on a particular point. If there<br />

is no majority view. I point that out in the endnotes. Additionally, in prrwnting Islamic law<br />

I have sometimes used the consensus of modem Muslim jurists studying the subject.<br />

This division is often ascribed only to the Hanaii school of thought in Islamic law. See M.<br />

Hamid, "Duress and its Effect on Contracts in Islamic law," Sudon L.J. and Reports 334.<br />

334-335 (1971); A. El-Hasan, "The Doctrine of Duress (ikd) in Sharia, Sudan and English<br />

Law," I. Arab. L. Q. 231, 231 (1986). However, this is largely inaccurate. Other Islamic<br />

schools did have a general conaption of two types of duressone so compelling as to negate<br />

liability in grave offenses and the other not so compelling. The Shafi'i jurists used the term<br />

ruinous duress (ikr& dlik) while the MBliki jurists used the term total duress (ikrcih<br />

mu!laq) for what the I+I%S called ikr& m4i. See al-Jamal. Hlirhiyat al-JaMI (Cairo:<br />

al-Wktabah al-Tij*yyah al-Kubra, n.d.), vol. 5, p. 9; and al-Dusuqi. Hlirhiyaf d-Dusuqi


Islamic Studies, 30:3 (1991)<br />

'ala'l-Sharh al-Kabir(n.p.: Dar ih~S al-kit&b .I-'ArPbi, n.d.), vd. 2 at W, h see F. Abu<br />

Myy&, d - M ji'l Swah d-lsbniyyah (al-Mdh: PI-Rubid. 1982). p. 41. a d M.A.<br />

AWur RPhim, lk Phciph of M- Jvrispnrdarae (198I). pp. 232-37.<br />

Lbn al-HmnHm. Sh@ Fe d-podt. (Cairo: al-Mntba'ab al-AmmAmiriyyeh, H 1317). d. 7,<br />

pp. 293-294; Ibn 'Abidin, Radd al-Mukhtrir (Cairo, al-Halabi, 1%6), vol. 6, pp. 128129;<br />

al-KasPni, Badci'i d-Sanri'i' fi Tmib d-Sharci'i' (Beirut: Dar al-Kitab al-Arab, 1974). vol.<br />

7, p. 175; al-Sarakhsi, d-Mabsri! (Cairo: al-Haji Muhammad Effendi, n.d.), vol. 23, p. 40.<br />

'Zhis distinction between consent and choice is particularly Hanafi. Other schools of thought,<br />

though recognising that there are two types of duress, did not distinguish between consent<br />

and choice.<br />

Al-KaQni, Ba&i', p. 182.<br />

Al-KasW, &rdm", p. 175. The Mejdle codifies this rule in Seetion 949 which states: "[Duress]<br />

is of two sorts. The first sort is compelling duress. It leads to destruction of life, or loss of<br />

a lib or one of them. It is the compulsion. which is by a hard blow. The second sort is<br />

noncompelling duress. This causes only grief and pain. It is compulsion which is by things<br />

like a blow or imprisonment." 'Zhe Iraqi Civil Coclr, Article 112, similarly provides: "And<br />

duress is considered compelling if it poses a serious and imminent threat of loss of life or<br />

limb or severe beating or severe harm or great destruction of property and it is not compelling<br />

if it is a threat of imprisonment or beating, and this varies a&ording to the condition of<br />

people." Also see. discussion in Abdur Rahim. Principles, pp. 233-34.<br />

For example, albarakhsi, d-Mhri!, pp. 49-50, and Ibn Nujaym, d-Ashbdh wa'l Nazci'ir,<br />

printed with Hamawi as commentator in Ghnmf 'Vyrin 01-Be't (Karachi: Idkat al-Qur'8n.<br />

1988). vol. 3, p. 203.<br />

Ibn Humiim. Sharh fat!^ d-Qodir. p. 294.<br />

Ibn 'Abidin, Rae., p. 133.<br />

See, al-Ramli, Nwah d-M+tcil (Cairo: Musfafi al-Halabi 1%7), vol. 6, p. 447; alJamal,<br />

Hbhiyah, vol. 4, p. 325; al-Dardir, d-Sharh d-Soqhir (Cairo: Dar al Ma'arif, 1972). vol.<br />

2, pp. 546-547; al-Khd-, d-Shu+ d+aghir 'dd MI&- Sayyid K M (Cairo: Matba'ah<br />

al-Kubra, H. 1317). vol. 4, p. 34. al-Dusfiqi, Hashiyard-Dq vol. 2, p. 368: Ibn Qudimah,<br />

d-Mughni (Cairo: Maktabat al-Qahirah. 1968). vol. 7. p. 384, Ibn Muflii, al-Maqdisi, al-<br />

Mubdi'fiSharh d-Mughni(Damascus: al-Maktab al-Islami, 1977), vol. 7, p. 2%; al-Buhuti,<br />

K~(hafd-Qina' 'an M~mdlg~'(Riyad: Maktabat al-Nasral-Hadithah, n.d.),vol. 5. p. 236.<br />

Al-Ramli, Nilrciyah, vol. 6, p. 447; al-Jamal, Huiyah, vd. 4, p. 325; al-Dardir, d-Saghir.<br />

vol. 4, p. 35; Lbn Qudhah, d-Mughni, vol. 7, p. 384, andsee, ~ bii ~a6yyah. d-lknih, p. 44.<br />

See Lbn m, d-Mu@fd (Cairo: Dar al-Turath, n.d.), vd. 8, p. 330, d-Jamal, Hdshiyah.<br />

vol. 4, p. 325. Zbn Hazm, for example, after citing a @&% stating that Muslims are.brothers,<br />

argues that it follows that they should proteet one another. Si MusIims are joined by<br />

mutual empathy, hanu to a third party. even a stranger, will cause enough grief to constitute<br />

duress.<br />

A-M, N W , d. 6, p. 447; al-mi, H w d-D- vol. 2. pp. 368369,<br />

-, d-Mbbsuf, d. 5, p. 236, Lbn Qudimnh, d-M- vol. 7, p. 384, Lbn m,<br />

d-MUM', vol. 7, p. 255. Also see PI-Damyni, d-Td, pp. 3Z-375; Blgr al-Ulh, 'ma,<br />

pp. 281-283; Dagbi. Mabda' d-R@fl 'VqJd. (Beirut: Dar al-Basha'er al--yah, 1985)<br />

vd. 1. p. 4W, Ah S&yy&. d-lbnh, pp. 53-SI.<br />

Al-Knan-. Bad&ii, p. 176; Daghi. M W d-Reidcr pp. 428429.<br />

AISaRLhsi, d-MahM!, p. 49, alao see p. 50. Also see al-Kashi. M for the same idea.<br />

Id; h see Lbn 'Abidin (Commentator), Rdd, d. 6, p. 133.<br />

Al&dhai, d-Mabslit, pp. 52 and 66. The MejeUc codifies this ruk in acction 1004, which<br />

states:<br />

It is a condition that the pem compelled should be afraid of the taking place of<br />

the thing, which causes his fear, that is to say, that he should have formed a<br />

preponderant opinion in his own mind,.that the person using compulsion, would<br />

do the tbing threatened if he did not do the thing k was compelled to do.<br />

'he EgypPirn Civil Codc, Artide 127, and the Imqi Civil Codc, Artide 113. have


Islamic Studies, 30:3 (1991) 339<br />

See. al-Ramli, Nih@ah, vol. 6, p. 447; al-Jamal. Hbrhiyah, vol. 4, p. 325; al-Buhuti,<br />

M-hid KhM, ~ l 5, . p. 236, lbn QudBmah, MU@, VOI. 7, p. U)4, lbn Mm, d-~uhk, vd. 7, p. 256 (duma varies with thc conditions of people); al-Kh- (al-'Adawi,<br />

commnt.tor) MuUirafm Sayyid Khdil, vol. 4, p. 34, al-M, d+agW, vol. 2, p. 546,<br />

al-. Hdpkiya d-Lhdqi vol. 2, p. 368, and a& ibn al-Humh (ad-Babarti, commenmar).<br />

Shm?, d-F+ d-Qadir, p. 295, for the same approach m thc Hanafi school. Also a&<br />

E& d--, 'Urn, p. 267; and al-Dar~pi, d - T d , pp. 367-368.<br />

This dhgree~nt has been noted by the commentator to Ibn 'AbiQn's work, Radd, vol.<br />

6, p. 129.<br />

lEia h pdomiaatly thc opinion of some Hanrfi Jurists. The Mjdlc relyiug on this opinion<br />

date in Article 1005:<br />

If the person ampelled, do [sic) what he is compelled to do, m thc presence of<br />

the person, who u~ts compubion, or his agent, the compulsion is wnsided.<br />

But, if he do [sic] it m the absence of the person who u~ts c~mpukion, and m the<br />

absence of his agent, the compulsion h not dded, by reason of his ha*<br />

acted with willing auhissh afier thc removal of thc comprlsion.<br />

Some HanbaG jurists went even further in requiring that some physical harm would befall<br />

the victim before he submits to pressure; therefore, a mere threat unaccompanied by some<br />

actual physical harm will not suiia. Ibn M*, d-Mubdr', vol. 7, p. 256; and Ibn Qudhah,<br />

al-Mughni, vol. 7, p. 383. But see al-Buhuti, Kmhdf. vol. 5,236, from the HanbaG school,<br />

for a contrary opinion.<br />

AI-Jamal. Hddiyah, vol. 4, p. 323; and al-Ramli. NWyah, vol. 4, p. 447. Also see lbn<br />

al-. S w Fu@ d-(?ad&, p. 293, fmm thc +di school for thc same appmach.<br />

Al-Khurashi, M-ar Sayyid Khalil, vol. 4, p. 34; and al-Dusiiqi, Hahiyal al-D~~~liqi,<br />

wl. 2, p. 368.<br />

Al-Sarakhsi, al-Mabse, pp. 76-77. AISaraLhsi, later argues, somewhat i~lconsistantly. that<br />

if a person 01 authority orders another to grab people's money, the ordered person cannot<br />

comply if he is far away fmm the oppressor. Thea al-- adds that those who assist<br />

opprcssor~ always claim that they were compelled to do so but m reality they had no excuse<br />

unless the opressor was standing over them at all times. Otherwise, they really never know<br />

whether the oppressor will in fact s u d in hurting them and, therefore, they cannot assist<br />

oppressors. See al-Sarakhsi, al-Mobslit, pp. 77-78. me only way we can read the two abovedrscussed<br />

passages consistently is to rend al-SarM as saying that if a person has an opporhlaity<br />

to escspe he will not be excused unless he is cornered mto compliance. Also see Ibn<br />

'Abidin, R d , p. 132; and lbn al-Nujaym, d-Ashbrih. vol. 3, p. 203; Ibn Qayyim al-Jawziyyah,<br />

A ' h d-Muqa'in (Beirut: Dar al-Jtel, n.d.) vol. 4, pp. 53-54.<br />

See. D&-. M M d-Re, pp. 427; Blgr al-'UItim 'Uyyrsb, p. 269; al-Daray-, d-Tmdii<br />

pp. 371-372; al-Sanhm-. Ma+ d-Haqq fi? Fqh d-I- (Beirut: al-Mujama al-by,<br />

n.d.), vol. 2. pp. 1W52.<br />

Al-Saralrhsi, al-Mobsri!, p. 135; Ibn Qud%mah, d-Mughni, vol. 7, p. 384; al-Kashi, Ba&ii',<br />

p. 181.<br />

Atcomm~ah."[t]he~to~thedcgreeofcDmpulsionmtcrmsofgravity~f<br />

thc o&aa ~ lI- r overlooked". (Pertins and Boyce, Criminal Lmv, p. 1061). Regde=<br />

of uime, thc test of that ef death or serious personal miury, was thc same. State v. Toscano<br />

J18A. 2d. at 762; R.v. Hudson & Tavloc. [I9711 2 Q.B. 202. Whatever the offense, the<br />

threat of a serious physical mjwy is required. (Orchard, '"I'k Defence of Compulgion,"<br />

111; Ncumau & Wdkcr. "Duress," p. 330). However, an 1887 a&ms to hart reeogrised<br />

& of- dcgree of pmportionelity etating: "It m~gt be obvious to thc dctiberate<br />

judlFment of cvq reflecting mind that much less freedom of will is requisite to render a<br />

pcm responrdbk for wimc thau to bind him by a sale or other contrsct. To overcome the<br />

will, so far rr to render it iacapable of contrecting a avil obligation, is a mere trifle compared<br />

with~ittoth.tdcgecofal.veyand~~bmirsionwbichwillexamp~punishmcnt."<br />

McCoy v. State. 78 Ga. 490, 3 S.E. 768. 769 (1887). In McCoy. a judge ch- thc jury<br />

thrt,"Ihuwaanmintsmthabofbodilyorothcrhsrm,orOthermtans.. .amo~ntillgto<br />

or tending to ooera thc will of another. . . ." The Supreme Court of Georgia reversed


Islamic Studies, 30:3 (1991)<br />

stating that tbL imtrvction mi@t be proper in civil cmes. But the criau of perjury. Iike<br />

other felonies, reqe a threat to lik or limb. Some Watgn aebob have mpd for a<br />

rule ofpqmhdky. See. Mve & Sam, Handboo&, pp. 37Em. M. !hmaj&. "Dursu<br />

d Murder in the ClnnmonllraW CrimiaPl JAW." 30 1w. prd Canp L. Q. tXO,678 (1981).<br />

See,Ehvudr"."pppp.302md308.<br />

AtCammoalaw.~ofcvilMe~y~inthelawof"ntarity"a<br />

opposed to "duress". In neagity the force of mcrcion is natural face whik in duress the<br />

compelling fora isa human being. Modern Ameriaa c . have tended to blur the dirtinetion<br />

between durar d nearity. See United Stata v. Balky. 444 U.S. 394. 410 (1980). but<br />

ccrtaiu ampa haw praaved the dirtinction. United State v. Conteato-Padnm. 723 E 2d.<br />

691,695 (9h Q. 1981). Islamic law das not dbthpbh bmeen the two doetriaer. On<br />

the"chdaofWMe.=Hi~."~.saDefeaain~Csres."4Va<br />

L. Rev. 519 (1917) Lafaw. CriminolIm, (1986) at pp. 433 and 441-443. Abo ace, the ~~IUOUC<br />

cane of Qucen v. Dudley & Stephens (1884) 14 Q.B.D. 273 and its dkmkm in Smith &<br />

Hopn. Criminal Low, pp. 201-209.<br />

AlSaraLM. dSiyor d-Kabi? (Hyderabad: Da'int al-Ma'arif), Irt ed. rol. 4, p. 222.<br />

Abo scc Ibn m, d-MuMld, vol. 8, p. 330.<br />

There are exaptions as will be seen in the next section.<br />

Al-Dardi. d-Saghir, vol. 2. p. 548.<br />

Ai-K&ni. Badrk". p. 181, and see al-Sarakhsi. She@ d-Siyar, pp. 131136 for the argument<br />

that even though the victim makes the wrong choice by commiting murder, the victim should<br />

not be punished if he believed in good faith that pronouncing apostasy was i#*cusable<br />

under all circumstances. It seem that al-Sarakhsi is arguing that this is a common mistake<br />

peopk make and, therefore, as a matter of policy they should be excused.<br />

Al-Sarakhsi, d-Mabsai!, p. 141 and see p. 135.<br />

Ibn 'Abibin (Commentator). Rudd, p. 140 and al-Sarakhsi, d-Mobsti!. 137. See more examples<br />

in Abdur Rahim. Ptinciplcr. p. 233.<br />

I am greatly simplifying the &&rent categorizdtion efforts by Muslim juriats. But for the<br />

purpores of this essay there is no need to go into the details. See al-Sa&h& d-Mabsti!,<br />

pp. 39-42; al-KasiM, Bodcii' p. 176; and Ibn Nujap, d-Ashbtih, vol. 3, p. 2(n. Also see,<br />

Abdur Rahim, Principles, p. 234 and 356. The Mcj& codified these categorizations in<br />

Section 1007, which states:<br />

[Duress], which is canpelling, like as it is considered in tmudom by word as<br />

above said so also it is considered in tmmactions by deed. But [durese], which is<br />

[noncompellig], is considered only in verbal tmnsa&m, in transactions by deed<br />

it is not considered.<br />

Therefore, if someone says to another, "Destroy the property of such a one. if you<br />

don't I will kill you or cut off one of your limbs", and the person, against whom<br />

the anupubion is used, dsstroys it, the compulsion is taken into coarideration,<br />

liability &I be enforad agaiuat the person u& tbe compllaion &me.<br />

-But if the says, [sic] "Destroy the pmperty of such a one, if you do not, I will strike<br />

or imprison yw," if that peMn does not destroy it, rhc compulsion is not taken<br />

into consideration, it is nwesq for the person, who destroys the thing, alone to<br />

make compensation.<br />

See abo. Ibn Hum, d-Mu+& vol. 8, p. 330.<br />

See Ibn 'Abid~~, ilPldd, p. 129: Ibn Nujap, d - a d. 3, p. p(; d-Dudir, d-+z@t,<br />

d. 2, pp. 367 d 370. For a far mom complu theoretial catc~tion from a ShWi<br />

SCC, d-Tdug, (d. 2, p. 197) dLwrcd d quoted by alS.nb~& MnpddL, 4. 2,<br />

pp. 195-196.<br />

Bacon. Cdlecnbn, p. 161. Although the dsrsic rule at common law was that no amount of<br />

durar would jurtay .cts of treason tbi abrolutist view was never followed to the latter, me.<br />

Edwards, ~vlrion, p. 298, Smitb and Hogan, Crlminol Low, p. 212 d Perldar and<br />

Bop, Crlminol LAV, p. 503.<br />

Bk+ckstone. Cmma&rh, bk., IV, chap. 11, p. 30. Blackstone displays a logic amazingly<br />

similar to Islamic analysis. Blackstone states that duress per minar excuses many crimes and


Islamic Studies, 30:3 (1991) 341<br />

mLdcmeanoro "at least before the humsn tribunal". Hem, implying that sccularvindicaoion<br />

does not neceararily wan divine hgivewr. This rearoning has been fully expounded by<br />

Mudim jurists.<br />

See, al-Sm-. Shu+ dSiy d-Kabir, vol. 3, pp. 218-38, on treason. Al&rakk argues<br />

that if a Muslim is threatened by compelline duress to manufacture maponary fDr the enemy.<br />

he may do so only if in the preponderance of his thought such weapons will not cause the<br />

defeat of Muslim armies, and likewise if he is threatened by death to reveal the road to an<br />

WIIllic fort, he may do so ody if in the prepondtrana of his thought the enemy will not<br />

be able to conquer the fort. But if the enemy threatens him to find out where a partiarlar<br />

person is, and he believes that the enemy wishes to rape or Lill such a person, the coerced<br />

should sacrifia himself.<br />

The coed is not entirely innoant because he ads as the instrument or agent of the<br />

eoerar. Sec, Wertheimer, Coercion, pp. S281. Werthcimcr argues that murk adopt a<br />

higher stadud of duress when inooant parties are involved. This, aamrding to Werthcimer,<br />

partly accounts for the higher standard in aiminal cases. Id. p. 162. This might be correct<br />

asamattcrof commonsense but hisis not how courts justify the different standardsadopted.<br />

Cdamari aad PerriUo. Lmv of Confroc~~, p. 397; 17 C.J.S.. Conbucts, aec. 175; 25 Am. Jur.<br />

2d, "Dunsr." sec. 512; United States v. Bethlehem. 315 U.S. 289. m301 (la); Eclrstein<br />

v. Eckstcm, 38 Md. App. 506,379 A. 2d. 757 (Ct. Spec. App., 1978); Slade v. Slade 310,<br />

111. App. n:33 N.E. 2d. 951 (1941); Kaolan V. K;aoIan. 25 111. 2d. 181. 186, 182. N.E.<br />

2d. 706.709 (1%2); R~t(llUMlf Second, Contrrcb, a. 175 Comment (1979); Alma S.S.<br />

Co. v. Vela, 285 F. Supp. 123,125 (D.P.R. 1%8), (duress is the pres~urc of circumstances<br />

which aornpeU the will to yield).<br />

Ratntacn, Conbacbi aec. 492 (1932). Comment uplainr; "The same threats may cause<br />

feu in one person and not in another. Tbe test of what act or threat produces the required<br />

degree of fear is not objective. The threat need not be such as would put a brave man, or<br />

even a man of ordinary firmness, in fear. Tbe question is rather, did it put one entering into<br />

the transastion in such fear as to preclude the exercise by him of free will and judgement.<br />

Age, sa, capacity, relation of the parties. attendant circumstances, muat all be conridered.<br />

Pmom of a wed or cowardly nature are the very oaes that need protation. Tbe co~lr;leaouo<br />

can usually protect thcmoelves; timid persons are generally the ones iatluend by threats,<br />

and thc unaaupulou~ are not allowed to impme upon them because they are so unforhmately<br />

conrtituted."<br />

Calamari aad Pcrrillo. Law of ConfrocLI, P. 337, Ru-, Contracts, aec. 492, comment<br />

(b) (1932); Sec. Milla v. Eisck. 168 A. 426.432 (N.J. 1933) indicating that since the plaintiff<br />

acted reasonably he can daim durcy; sad Wm v. Midtown Motors, 231 ffi. 46.42 N.W.<br />

2d 404 (1950) defendant threatened to firt plaintiff unless he signed a release of an aaion<br />

againat a fDnier employer. In granting relief the court ituisted that the test is entirely<br />

subjective. Tbe type of threat or the response of a penon of ordinary firmness are irrelevant<br />

ddrrpdiom. However the decision of the court primarily relied on the wrongfulaess of<br />

thc thnat. aad on the fact that plaintiff had no other rearonable alternative. Id. 407-406.<br />

Econolaie duma ohea involves a threat to cause a victim financial injury unless the victim<br />

agreed to certain terms. This could involve a threat to deny esential goods or services or a<br />

threat to breach a contract.<br />

Aurtia Itmumat Inc. v. Lod Corp., 29 N.Y. 2d. 124,324 N.Y.S. 2d. 22.272 N.E. 2d.<br />

533 (1971); Leeper v. ~eltraml, 53 a. 2d. 195.1 ~al. ~ptr 12.347 p. 2d 12 (1959); young<br />

v. Hoaghd, 212 Cal. 426,298 P. 9% (1931); London Homes Inc. v. Korn 234 Cal. App.<br />

2d. 333, 44 Cal. rptr 262 (1965); See also Calamari and Perillo, Law of Confmcts. p. 337;<br />

Fridman, CrmodicM ad English Law, pp. 54-55; Hale, "Bargaining," pp. 2&4-286, Dawson,<br />

haa l#uough Civil Uigrrtion, op. at.. pp. 695m. Daizeil, "Duress by Ecooomic Prrssure."<br />

pp. 367-382; F v . Viaimircraion, pp. 86-91. In economic duma caas the inquiry<br />

k often p h d in terms of whether the threat is wmngful. LaBcad~ v. Beatrice Foods Co.,<br />

461 E Supp. 152,1567 (S.D. N.Y. 1978); Louiwik Tie Ins. Co. v. Surety Title and Guar<br />

Co. 60 Cal. App. 3d 781,805,132 Cal. rptr. 63.80 (1976). A court may look to the moral


Islamic Studies, 30:3 (1991)<br />

obligations of the coercer and whether his threat is made for outrageous purposes. Hochmen<br />

v. Zigler, 50 A. 2d. 97,100 (N.J. Ch. 1946) or to whether the threat is against public policy.<br />

shaeta Water Co. v. Croke, 276 p. 2d. 88.91. (GI. dist. a. App. 19YI). (threats of criminal<br />

su&red the risk of heparable injury. Tri-State Roofins Company of Union Town v. Simon,<br />

187 pa. super 17.142. A. 2d. 333 (1958). Needkss to say. as a pwerical matter even rightful<br />

(as opposed to wrongful) threats an ovenmne a will.<br />

The RatoPnncnf Second rrfusbd to incorporate the "omcome will" language saying that it<br />

is too vague and hpradbble. Ramemmt Second, '"tracts," see. 175, Comment (b).<br />

Ibid., Comment (c).<br />

fidelity & Causality Co. of New York v. United States, 490 F. 2d. %0,966 (Ct. C1.1974).<br />

(mere strcss of ~~ circumstances is not duress). Despite similar factual situations, cwrts<br />

will reach different conclusions depending on how the court evaluates the equities and policies<br />

at stake. For example, see, Meier v. Nightingale. 46 A. 2d. 785 (N.J. 1946). defendant<br />

refused to return plainWs car unless he pays an amount greater than what plaintiff believed<br />

they agreed upon. Plaintiff paid and used daiming duress of goods. The wurt denied relief<br />

to plaintiff asserting that plaintiff had other, especially statutory, alternatives. But see,<br />

Leeper v. Beltrami, 53 Cal. 2d. 195,347 p. 2d. 12.1 cal. Rptr. 12 (1959), defendant threatened<br />

to foredose on plaintiff's house unless she made a certain payment. Plaintiff paid and then<br />

claimed duress. Court held fo~ plaintiff relying on equity and policy consider;ltions. It is not<br />

reasonable, according to the wurt to e w people to lose their homes as they await the<br />

result of litigation. Aka see, Tri-State Roofing Co. v. Simon, 187 Pa. Super 17,142 A. 2d.<br />

333 (1%5), (wrongful threat to breach contract is not duress because there is no irreparable<br />

injury). Austin Instrumental v. Loral Corp. 29 N.Y. 2d. 124 (1971), (wrongful threat to<br />

breach a government contract is duress). Hochman v. Zigler's Incorp., 50 A. 2d. 97. 100<br />

(N.J. Ch. 1946), (when landlord's threat of eviction is made for outrageous purposes and<br />

the tenant had no adequate relief, duress is found); Laaeach v. Beatria Foods Co. F. Supp.<br />

152 (1978), (summaryummaryjudgment for defendant appropriate when plaintiff claimed that-he<br />

was intimidated by defendant's vast economic power into releasing his interest in a Nigerian<br />

company).<br />

168 A. 426,432 (N.J. 1933).<br />

RarutmMf, Coutracts, 492 Comment (c); Calamari and Perillo, Lmw of Contmcts, 4436, 1<br />

Perkins and Boyce, Criminal Lmw, p. 1064; Clark and Marshall, A Tmatise on the Law of I<br />

Crimes (7th ed.), p. 366.<br />

Calmari and Pedo, Lmw of Contnacts, pp. 343-344; 17 C.J.S. "Conhacts," p. %3; 25 Am<br />

Jur. 2d. "Dunns," pp. 358-359.<br />

Kronmover v. Vuck, 258 III, 586.101 N.E. 935 (1913); (only recognising a close relaltive):<br />

Saxon v. Saxon (1976) 4, W.W.R. 300, 305 (B.C.S.C.) (only rrcognising a close relative),<br />

25 Am. Jur. 2d. "Dwess," sec. 22 (noting that courts only rewgnise close relative); 17 C.J.S<br />

"contractr." sec. 179 (noting that there is disagreement between the courts); Restatement<br />

'<br />

First of Contracts only recognised threats to near relatives (sec. 499, but Rc~fatemrnt Second<br />

of Contracts provides that the threat does not even have to be directed at a relative as long /<br />

as the third party duress induces the victim to manifest his assent. Sec. 176 Comment (b). j<br />

See, Corbin, On Comm (one volume edition, 1952). pp. 10-14. In modem legal tenninol- :<br />

ogy, contracts that might lack legal effect are either voidable, void or unenforceable. In the<br />

case of voidable contracts, a party has the power to either validate or avoid the contract. I<br />

In other words, the legal effect of the contract is a-ested until released by the wronged<br />

party. A void contract has no legal effect from the moment of its inaption. It is negatory i<br />

!<br />

and ineffective and cannot be cured by a subsequent validation. An unenforceable contract I<br />

'<br />

is a contract enjoying complete legal validity, however, it is unenforceable because of external<br />

legal factors like a statute of Limitations or the statute of frauds. i<br />

See. Ra- Second, article 174 and 175. See; Rcstclrmuru, C h ~ utides , 4% and<br />

495; and Calamari and Perrillo, h w of Contmcn, pp. 349-350. In Roman law, contracts I ,<br />

obtained by duress were not void per se. Nonetheless, the victim of duress (metll~) could<br />

i


Islamic Studies, 30:3 (1991) 343<br />

Oppose the @I-tation of the contract and render it ineffective. Additionally, the vi&,,<br />

dd bring a delis (ac&n q d metus UW) agaiost the oppressor and be entitled to a<br />

penalt)Lsuch action had to be brought witbin one year from the date of the illegal<br />

See- Ihom=, Tex&ok of Itom Low (Amsterdam: North-Holland Publishing<br />

Co., 1976). pP 228 and 373; Md lber, Rorrurn Private Low (Durban: Butterworth, 1%5),<br />

P. 49. Also see Kes~el, ~ ~ ~ ~ R c I ACrhinak, D J u Beinhart s and Warmelo trans. (Johannaberg:<br />

Juts and Co. Ltd. 1973). VOI. 1, p. 389 and vol. 2. p. 907.<br />

See, B e al-'Uliun, 'Uyyrib, p. 306.<br />

See, Me#&, Artides 26-30. Artide 26 provides: "A private injury is tdmted in order to<br />

ward off a public injury." Also see, al-Qarafi, d-Fvnip, vd. IV (Beirut: 'dam al-Kutub,<br />

n.d.), pp. &9; al-Gh-, al-Musmsjd, vol. I (Cairo: al-Matba'a al-Amiriyah, p. 322) pp.<br />

S297; Ibn 'AM alSalam, Qawa'id al-Ahhim, vol. I (Beirut: Dar al-Ji, 1980). pp. 54-62<br />

and 93-94. me work cited are on the general principles of Idamic law. me example given<br />

by these jurists comes from criminal law but the example only demonstrates the general<br />

principle.<br />

This factual scenario is taken from Wertheimer, Coenion, p. 275. Wertheimer, however.<br />

uses this scenario in the amtext of addressing diierent issues.<br />

Wertheimer seems to argue that A should pay the fees and sue to recover later. 1 am not<br />

sure that even under the Common law system this conclusion is correct.<br />

'2ht Ra-w Suond is vague becaw of the imprecision inherent in the reasonableness<br />

standard. Idamic law is vap bmw the value system on which it relies is unclear.<br />

lbn Nujaym, d-Ashbcih, vol. 3, p. 203.<br />

The only disagreement from within the Hanafi ranks came from war who argued that the<br />

contract is not corrupt, rather, it is conditioned on the victim's s"bsequent approval. If the<br />

victim never approves it then the contract is unenforceable. I am not sure, however, that<br />

there is a real difference in contents between Far's arguments and his other Hanafi col-<br />

Som of the Whit verses state, "Let there be no ampubion in religion; T ~th stands<br />

out dcar from em." (11:256) "Anyone who, after accepting faith in God, uttaymbelief,<br />

except rmda complbioo. . . On them is wrath from God." (16:106) A h sec (24:33) and<br />

(4:19). 'Lbe Propha is reported to have Mid, "My nation has been absolved [from liability]<br />

regardiug [* invohg] mistakes, forgcthrlness and what they have been compelled to<br />

do." See, Ibn H-, al-Mu!uaUii, wl. 8, p. 334.<br />

Ibn +mu, aCM- vol. 9. p. 21.<br />

See, an extensive discussion of this issue in al-Sarakhsi, d-She al-Siyar, pp. 55-59, also<br />

see, pp. %97. ALSO see, al-Ramli, Nihdyah, vol. 3, p. 397; al-Jamal, Htishiyah, pp. 17-18;<br />

Ibn M e , al-MihY, vol. 4, p. 7; and Ibn QuW, d-Mu*, vol. 5. p. 110.<br />

AI-K~&-, M-r Sayyid KW, wl. 5, pp. 9-10; al-Wqi. Hbhiyat d-Dus~iqi, vd.<br />

2, p. 369, and al-Dardii, al-Saghir, vd. 3, p. 18.<br />

See. al-Sanhh-. Maydir, pp. 207-214 for a fairly detailed study of this issue. me Imqi Civil<br />

Code, article 115, provides that duress makes a contract unenforceable; the Egyptian Civil<br />

Code, article 127, provides that duress makes a contract voidable.<br />

D'Aquim v. United States, 192 F. 2d 338.358 (9th Cir.. 1951); Nall v. Commonwealth.<br />

208 Ky, 700,271 S.W. 1059 (1925); State v. St. Claire, 262 S.W. 2d. 25 (Mo. 1953); United<br />

States v. Gordon, 526 f. 2d. 406,407 (9th Cir. 1975); Shannon v. United States, 76F. 2d.<br />

490,493 (10th Cir., 1935); DPP v. Lynch, [I9751 A.C. 653,655; R.V. Hudson [I9711 2 All<br />

E.R. 244,247; United State v. Balley, 444 U.S. 390,410-11 (1980); United States v. Boomer,<br />

571 F. 2d. 543-545 (10th Ci.) Cert denied 436 U.S. 911 (1978); Cde v. United States 347<br />

F. 2d. 492 @.C. Ci.) Cert. Denied, 381 U.S. 929 (1965); United States v. DiFr01120.345<br />

F. 2d. 383 (7th Cir.) Cert, Denied, 382 U.S. 829 (1965); Phillips v. United States, 334 F.<br />

2d. 589 (9th Cir., 1%4) Cert Denied. 379 U.S. 1002 (1965); 22 C.J.S., C* Low, Sec.<br />

100.180. Perkins. C* Low, 916-18.<br />

United States v. Palmer 458 F. 2d 663 (9th Cir., 1972); People v. Ricker, 45 111. 2d. 562,<br />

262 N.E. 2d 456 (1970); Kawakita v. United States, 343 U.S. 717 (1952); Even the Model


Islamic Studies, 30:3 (1991)<br />

3.) However, threats to property or reputation are adpiribk under seaion 3.02 (Choice<br />

of Evils). And see Commonwealth v. Reffitt, 149 Ky. 300 148 S.W. 48 (1912). recognising<br />

threats to property or reputation.<br />

Koonh v. State, 204 So. 2d. 224 (Fla. App., I%?, State v. Nodine, 198 Ore. 679,259 p.<br />

2d. 1056 (1953); State v. Torano, 74 N.J. 421, 378 A. 2d 755, 762 (lm); y, Orchard,<br />

Defeme of Cornphion, 111-112, for the law in Newzedand. Several writers have argued<br />

that threats to strangers should be rewpnised. Wan and Scott, Hadbook, pp. 1W1061,<br />

Clark and Marshall, Treotire, W, Wave, CriminrJ Low, pp. 436-438; Donaclly. Goldstein<br />

and Schwark, Criminol Law (1983), p. 662; and Bishop. Criminal Imc: p. 207.<br />

MPC, Comment 3. However, a British case R.V. Hudron [I9711 2. Q.B. 202.2 All E.R.<br />

244, has allowed a defence of durcss although the threatened harm was not immediate.<br />

See, note 44 above but see, State v. Toscano, 74 N.J. 421,378 A. 2d 755,762 (19?7), stating<br />

that under certain circumstances the commiseion of minor crimes should be excusable even<br />

if the threat is not one of death or serious bodily injury. Also see, Orehard, Defmce of<br />

Compulsion, p. 111, discussing cases that imply that the threat required should vary with<br />

the seriousness of the harm amunitted. K.J.M. Smith. "Duress-the Role of the Reasonably<br />

Steadfast Man," 98 L.Q. Rrv. 347. 351 (1982), argues that issues of praportionality limits<br />

should be a matter for the legislature because matters of policy such as this should not be<br />

left to juries.<br />

Newman and Weitzer, "Duress, Free Will." P. 331; also see, Williams, Criminal Law; The<br />

General Part, sec. 246 (2nd ed. 1%1).<br />

MPC, m. 209 comment 2, p. 374.<br />

Section 2.09; (1) it is an affirmative defena that Ihe actor en& in the amduct drarged<br />

to constitute an offense because he was coerced to do so by tbe urt of or a that to use<br />

unlawful force against his person or the person of another, that a person of reasonable<br />

firmness in hi situation would have been unable to resist.<br />

(2) The defena provided by the Section is unavailable if the actor recklessly placed hidlf<br />

in a situation in which it was probable that he would be subjected to duresr. Ibe defence<br />

is also unavailable if he was negligent in placing himaelf in such a situation, whenever<br />

negligence suf6ces to establish culpability for the offense charge.<br />

(3) It is not a defence that a woman acted on the command of her husband, unksc she<br />

acted under such coercion as would establish a defence under this don. presumption<br />

that a woman acting in the presence of her husband is a~rced is abolished.]<br />

(4) When the conduct of the actor would otherwire be justifiable under Sectioa 3.02, this<br />

Seaion does not preclude such defence.<br />

MPC, at comment 3, p. 375. 'Ibe reasonablenes test adopted by the MPC seems to be the<br />

majority position in the modem criminal Common law. MPC. Id., pp. 376-378. Several<br />

commentators have suppolted the reasonablener standard. See, Milgate. "Duress and the<br />

Criminal Law: Another Aboutturn by the House of Lords," 47 CMlbridge L.J.61.67 (1988);<br />

Dennis, "Duress, Murder," pp. 232-235; Sornarajah, "Commonwealth Criminal Law," pp.<br />

665-667.<br />

MPC, Comment 3, p. 375.<br />

Seetion3.OLstata:(l)Coaductthattheactorbe~~tobe~toavoidahsrmor<br />

evil to hbdforto.notha kju&hbk, provided tIut<br />

(c) a k@ddvc puposc to exdude the jurtidiatioa chimed does aot otkwk<br />

PMY w.<br />

As note at noted 49 above, the choice of evils doctrine musually requires that<br />

that comes fmm natural causes. Ibe Model Pmd Codc rej- that position.


klamic Studies, 30:3 (1991) 345<br />

One paaes the question: would a penon who asravinated an authoritarian leader or even<br />

a demoeratic one be entitled to claim the defena if he believes that in doing so he is saving<br />

tbe country or working for the general good? 'Ibc last segment of 3.02 (1) (a) might resobe<br />

th* mblem. Ihe defena of necessity hu been rejected in r~~litidy motivated offenses.<br />

~ee.'~nited States v. Knmcke, 459 F. 2d Zd, mi (8th CE~.~ 19?2); speci6ca~y relyiag on .<br />

this provision of the MPC. Courts often mad in a resronabkncss requirement by atating<br />

that there must be a reasonable anticipation of a causal connection between the action taken<br />

and the hanu sought to be avoided. Courts also often rely on the rationale of the availability<br />

of other reasonable alternatives, a rationale that poses a serious problem in non-democratic<br />

nations. United States v. Cassidy, 616 F. 2d lOl,l(n (4th Cir. 1979); United States v. Kabat,<br />

797 F. 2d 580. 591-92 (8th Cir. 1984); United States v. Seward. 687 F. 2d 1270. 1276 (10th<br />

ar. 1982); United States v. Coup, 603 F. 2d. 1347, 1352 (9th Cir. 1979); United States<br />

v. Simosoa, 460. F. 2d 515,518 (8th Cir. lW2); United States v. DomU, 758 F. 2d 427 (9th<br />

Cir. 1985). Wave and Scott note that a defena of necessity necessarily implicates the<br />

determination of the relative values at stake. If a criminal statute has made a determination<br />

of values then a wurt is pduded from sewnd pesiag the legislature. Otherwise, a court<br />

d d have to weigh the relative values involved. 'Ibis matter takes spacial prominence when<br />

abortion statutes or invohred. Wave and Scott. Handbook, p. 382; and See, Rex v. Bourne,<br />

(19391 1 K.B. 687 (the value of a mother's health ishigher than the value of an unborn fetus.)<br />

Blackstone, C-, bk. 4, p. 30. Also sce, Bishop. Criminnl Law, p. m, and Clark<br />

and Marshal, Treairc, p. 362; Edwards, Compulsion, 301, murder, "the crime being so<br />

heinous that even the strongest duress should not be a justification".<br />

LaFave and Scott. Hand600k. P. 376; But see, E.B. Amolds and N.F. Garland. "The<br />

Dcfena of Neassity in Criminal Law." 65 1. of Crim. L. & Criminology 289 n. 14 (1974);<br />

in D.P.P. for Northern Ireland v. Lynch (1975) A.C. 653, the House of Lords held that the<br />

defena of duress was available to a charge of principle in the sewnd degree (aiding and<br />

abatiog). In Abbott v. r., [19n] A.C. 755, the judicial committee of the Privy Council<br />

refused to extend the defena of duress to a charge of ruder as primapel in the 6nt degree.<br />

Recently, the House of Lords in R v. Howe and Barrister (19871 A.C. 417 held that duress<br />

can never be a defena to murder and. hena. reversing - ~ynch. - - see, - G. Fletcher, '*The<br />

Individualization of Excuting ~onditions;" 47 S. ~al. L. RN. 1269,1279 n. 33 (1974). noting<br />

that wum frequently base this rule on the impermissibility of killing innoant pemns. The<br />

rule seems entrenched in the Common law. For example, when the Supreme Court of<br />

Georgia recognid duras u a defena m murder caaes, Jones v. State, 207 Ga. 379,152<br />

S.E. 2d. 187 (1950), the Georgia legblature intervened to revem the ruling. G.A. Code<br />

AM. sec. %906 (I!%!), cited in Fletcher, Id.. p. 1289 n. 65.<br />

Suaarajah, Commonwcrrlth Criminol hw; Milgate. Dums and Ihc Criminol Law; Dennis,<br />

"Duress, Murder."<br />

MPC (Comment 2) at p. 374.<br />

Thir essentially utilitarian argument is promoted by Jeremy Bentham. Bentham argues that<br />

in cares of duress punishment is inefiicacious. J. Bentham, Infmkhn to the Ptinciprcs of<br />

Mods and hgirlotion, sec. 3, Xii. 6 (1873). Taken to the extreme, this view would lead<br />

to excusing all acts wmmined under d m , a view not sanctioned by any legal system. 'Ibc<br />

theoretical response to Bentham'sargument ispropounded by Hart. Hart arguesthat although<br />

punishing a person acting under duress might not have a deterrent effcd on the coerced, it<br />

might deter others. H.L.A. Hart, PvnLhmmt and RwpoNibiliry (1%8), p. 19 see, the<br />

dirusdon in Wcrtheimer. C@n. p. 1489.<br />

See, Jean Hampton, "The Moral Education theory of Punishment," 13, no. 3, Phil. and<br />

Pub. Aff. 208 (1984).<br />

See. Wertheimer's Mena of the murder ruk exception on mod grout&. However, his<br />

a%lment on omd rr(pcoey (h coerad being the mod ant of the carter) - is umemmsive. .<br />

'Ibis has the same overtones as the "ins&ent ration&' utitized by some M& jurltl.<br />

exapt Mdim jurists argued that by becoming the imtrument of the coerar, the coerced<br />

is not hue. See. Kasbi. E d , p. 179, Rnhim. f%c@lu, pp. 35157. This instrument or<br />

agency theory, if admitted, cannot be limited to the cau of murder. In other words, sina


Islamic Studies, 30:3 (1991)<br />

narldamrbeuamed.<br />

Ibn m, d-M-, ~ l 8. . p. 330.<br />

lbn 'AbkSn. w, p. 136, .I---. B&, p. In, al-Buhiiti, Kmhdf, vol. 5. p. 517;<br />

al-DsrdIr, d+aghir, -1. 2, p. 548, al-Dusiiqi. Hdahirrt d-Dm*, vol. 2, p. 367; ad see<br />

notabelow.<br />

EapeciaUrtheshiUi%.~andMlliLis.<br />

Primprily, and ysullu68.<br />

See, Ibn Rajab, Qawd'id ((him al-Halabi. lnt ed.), p. 286; alSuyii!i, d-hhbah vo'l Ne'ir,<br />

(Cairo, Matba'at Mustafa Mohammad, n.d.), p. 176; al-Dprdir. d-+z&fr, wl. 3, p. 5, see<br />

pp. 581412; al-Lhuiiq& HdsM d-mi, vol. 3, pp. 444 and see 442a. Ibn Nujaym,<br />

d-hhb&, vol. 3, p. m, al-Kurinl, Boddi: p. 177 lad 179; Ibn al-HumCm. S w Fcclfc d<br />

Q&, p. 3@ -and al-SurLhd, d-Mae, p. 69; abo aee. p. 142 for the view that llomaimes<br />

a pmvm is duty- bound to destroy property to save a thi~I peram's life.<br />

See, al-Dusq. H&hiat d-Duniqi, vol. 2, pp. 369-Jl0, sod al-Ddk, d-+gfi, vol. 2, pp.<br />

548-549. See, on this topic as a whole Ibn Hazm. d-M+Ud. vol. 8. p. 331; al-Sarakhsi.<br />

d-Sip, pp. 13&37; al-Jamal. Hdshiyah, vol. 5, p. 9; Ibn QudSad~, d-Mughni, vd.<br />

9, pp. 59-60., al-Matdab. (al-Muwaq; on the side bar), Mavdlrib d-Jdil (Bcit: Dar al-Kitab<br />

n.d.),vol.6,p.2W,d-~M~Soyyid~,~l.8,p.80,al-R~~~i,N<br />

vol. 7 on p. 424; d-BulWn, Knrhdf. vol. 6, p. 7.<br />

ste, on the ~ubjed, ~bn H-. PI-M- WI. 10, p. ~ 8 al-M-. ; ~oddi', pp. in and<br />

179.80. lbn al-Humim,~Sha+ d-Fed-Qadir,~. 3QIbn 'Abidin. Radd, pp. ?2-74, al-Jamal,<br />

Hdshiyah, vd. 5, p. 9; al-Buhiiti, Khhdf, vd. 5, p. 517; lbn Qud&nah, d-Mughi, vol. 8<br />

onpp. 26647; al-Khunahi. M~arsoyYidKlubl, vol. 8. onpp. 3 dP-lo; aod al-Dusiiqi,<br />

Hayah d-Dm- vol. 2 on p. 369. See Abdur al-DimPsbqi. Rahmat d-Ummah<br />

fi lkhlildfd-A'immd, (Kuwait: Mahabat al-Bukhari, ad.), p. 327.<br />

See, discussion in Sub@ Mahmasaai. The Philosophy of Jwispnrdmcr in Islam. Farhat<br />

Ziadeh trans. (Malaysia, Pencbitao Hizbi. 1987). p. 158; Rahim, Rinciplu, pp. 237 and<br />

257. and s o w cited Idem. Al-GW. (MY1 111) further states that a starving group of<br />

Muslim amot daughter one of their fold for food inorder to stay alive. M G W , ia a<br />

very sophisticated discussion, distinguishes this fmm a cane whcre the ~mintentiod sacri6a<br />

of some people is absolutely necessary for a definitive and universal publicgood. For example,<br />

if the enemy is holding Muslim hostages, then attacking the enemy, and in the proass risking<br />

the life of the hostages, is permitted only if several conditions are WiIled, Fmt, attacking<br />

the enemy must be absolutely necessuy. For example, if the enemy is not attacked the<br />

Mush state would be in snious danger. Second, there is no alternative but to take action<br />

that would risk the Lives of the hostages. Unfortunately, al-Ghmdi's discussion is too<br />

extensive for an adequate review here. AlGhd, d-Mwfasfi, pp. S97.<br />

One would be remiss not to note the remarkable similarity between the hypothetical<br />

example used by the Muslim jurist writing for the most part about 800 or more years ago,<br />

and thc case of Queen v. Dudley, and Stephens (1884) 14 Q.B.D. 273, in which two men,<br />

last at sea, drifting in a boat killed a boy and kd on him until they were saved. They were<br />

convicted for mu&, and the death se&d was imposed. ~o-r, responding-to the<br />

invitation of the court, the Crown commuted the sentence to six months im~risonment. For<br />

a similar case from the United States is United States v. Holmes, 26F. Cas. 360 (No. 15.<br />

383) C.C.E.D Pa. 1842). 9 seamen and 32 passangers were in a life boat in danger of sinking.<br />

14 passangers were thrown overboard with the intention of saving the rest. Defendant was<br />

convicted of manslaughter and received sentence of *month's hard labour. .See discussion<br />

in LaFave and Scott, Handbook, 385.<br />

This hypothetical example is taken from Perkins and Boyce, Crimjnul Low, 1057.<br />

This hypothetical is inspired by Smith aod Hogan. Crimid Low, P. 208.<br />

GhaztS's analysis. (see note 114 above), seems to yield a positive response for the second<br />

hypothetical. But that depends on how "unintentional dce" and a "univenal public<br />

good" is defined.


Islamic Studies, 30:3 (1991) 347<br />

118.<br />

119.<br />

120.<br />

121.<br />

122.<br />

123.<br />

124.<br />

125.<br />

126.<br />

in.<br />

See, United States v. Wey, 22 C.M.A. 534 (1973); Neu v. McCarthy, 309 Mos. 17, 33<br />

N.E. Y. 570 (1941); LaFave, Crimincd Law, P. 441; Bishop, C m Low, P. 212; Smith<br />

and Hogaa, Climinol Law, p. 22. Some writers have claimed that the sEandPrd is far kss<br />

stringent. If the order given by the superior "does not expreesly and clearly show on its faa<br />

its illegality", the follower h entitled to rely on it. Clark aod M.rabPU. Tnoaiac, p. 36B.<br />

MK, sec. 2.10 Comment 2. Section 2.10 provides: "It is an afknative defence that the<br />

actor, in engaging in the conduct charged to constitute an offem, does no more then excute<br />

an order of his superior in the armed se~ees that he does not know to be unlawiitl."<br />

Ibo Qudhmh. d-Mughi, rol. 8. p. 36& al-Bdttiti. w, MI. 5. pp. 518-519; al-Jd.<br />

Hddu'yd, vd. 5, p. 11; al-W-. (al-'Adawi, c~mmentator), Mukh+r hyyid KhdIl,<br />

vd. 10; ~ba H-. d-~+&i, MI. 10, p. 511; and al-smakhsi, d-~obs*, pp. n76.<br />

Werthekr, anmion, p. 282.<br />

Id., but Wexrheima amtests thc of making d m claims turn on policy<br />

d~Ptpp.~281.Kant~thattbm~c~,aswbeaarhipmcL<br />

paroo thnnamotberoverboard to~avehimself, in whirhbehrviourisnot iaarlp.bkbut<br />

it might deserve punitive Petion. Kant, of anuse, advoc;ltes that the &naption iItight be<br />

annbined in both caxs. and. therefore. this difierentatkm would dhmcar. Thus, whenever<br />

the bcimviour is m l e , it would also be punishn~e. 1mmpnue1 Kant. ~lribsofiy of<br />

Law. W. H.slL trans. (New Jeney; Augustus Valky. 1974). p. 53.<br />

AsDwoxtin T, a pmonmight act ~~~dercomprlrion but that -not neasssrily<br />

nuan he was compelled to act. Although acting under caqmhion, b behaviour atight wt be e x d or justified. Dvorkin, "Cornpubion and Moral Conapts," p. 229. Although a<br />

major issue of camtention among jurists, it is not helpful to enter into thc debate to<br />

wI~~ther duress is an excuse or justilkation. See, on this kue Dennis. "Duws. Murder."<br />

pp. 228-235. Thc question is whether duress judies the act amunitteal, and, thus, responsibility<br />

omr attrhLs m the 6mt place, and the law merely mmgokd this £act. Alternatively.<br />

if~,isan~,then~'bilityattrrhestothe~~ttealbutthelawu<br />

the act because d the circumstanux surrouading the act. Although of obvious moral<br />

came, this debate would take us too far alidd.<br />

In the world of philosophy both concepts k a rather predse meaning and notable prop<br />

onents. Zimmcrmclo, "Coercivc Wage Offers," reprerents the empirical appmach. Dworkin.<br />

"Compllrion and Moral eoacepts." Robat N&, "Comion." ia l%ilosophy, sciaue d<br />

M& hays in Honor of Eincn Noqd. tds. Sid~ey Mogeabacxr. Patrick ruppes and<br />

Morton White (I-); and Jeffrie Murphy. "Consent. Coercion and Hard Choias." 67 Virg.<br />

L. Rev. 79 (1981). represent the moralized app.oeeh. See the dircussion in WCrtpeimer,<br />

Coercion, p. 7 and Z4U-258 on fhe two approache. Ncvcrtheksc. when I use the tern I<br />

rm not refering to their pm+c meaning within the philaophical tradition.<br />

Se+. note 34 above.<br />

Frapmtry, textual ropnar will be mcondndve or at least invotve<br />

-<br />

complex adysb. For<br />

example, Ibn Hazm dhwes a subject of Idamic law lmoM as the "sale of the preswued"<br />

(bay'd++g&) or oramhacts of necessity. Ibn explains that typically in thae sales<br />

a pcmm goes through financial hardship or poverty, and in order to survive he sells his<br />

~ . ~ ~ ~ ~ t h a t ~ t o m p p o r t t h e ~ t b a t t<br />

dapmoninon-bhding.Ibo~~b.cl;Pad~thathcwooldhavelmed<br />

to.cceptsuch~aadbddth.toaathefinaocial~tioaofsuchapmonimproves<br />

he is entitled to invatidate the sale. Nevertheless, the H&, Ibn argues, are weak<br />

or unauthentic, and cannot be relied on as a murce of legislation. Atter noting that the<br />

Prophet himstif sold his in order to survive at times of hardship. Ibn Hazm<br />

condu&sthatmchasakbbinding. Ibn+m,d-MI+& vd.9.pp.22-23. Seed-Khurmhi.<br />

MuMwpr Sayyid KhalR, MI. 5, pp. %lo; al-Dusiqi. Hdrhiot d-Dtrniqi, vol. 3. p. 6; and<br />

al-Derdir. d-pghir, MI. 3, p. 18 on the Wliki position on this matter, and al-hakhsi,<br />

d-Mabag, p. 61 for a H d treatment.<br />

Foruampk.~,mtc45aboveand~yingtuton~s~onth<br />

p.Ctiarofoppressive~,andthe~omsuchpraEtia8haveforthchwofdm.


348 lslamic Studies, 30:3 (1991)<br />

128. See. mm 539 above and, acamp+q W. Som liLe the m in L.hvene.<br />

-tic Produebioo v. Fcrcnh, 305. Mieh. 193.9. N.W. 2d. 57.65 (1943) ooatimred to<br />

ate that "[t* qaatim a to what constitutes domr is a matter of law, but wktkr dums<br />

edrts in a particular cau is a quation of fact". Tbir, of anute, raembh the Llamic<br />

appro& in m y rrspear. Nevertheless, at Comntam law his appwh is lugely limited<br />

129.<br />

to~oft~)nomicd~inrhichtbc~~intothenooBfulntsrofthedurrsstaL<br />

apdal pr6mhma.<br />

P.S.Atiyeh."EcwomicI)mtsrandtheOverbomcnill."98L.Q.~~.'197.201(April.<br />

1982); rimikr mitiquw have been made by lbfbty. "Ekmenm of Wrongful Raaue." p.<br />

440; Pertins and Boys. Chid Low, p. 1054; Smith and Hop, Criminal Law, p. 209,<br />

cal.rmui and Penillo. Luw of Confmcp. P. 338, Dcnnio. "Duress. Murder." P. 222; LaFave<br />

and Scott. .. . Handbook, p. 382; Fitte. vicrunrroho n, pp. 73.74.7881; Fridman. Gmadian<br />

Md English Law, pp. 69-70., L. Vandervoit. "Social Justice m the Modern Regulatory State:<br />

Durea. Necc~sity. and the Chsemunl Model in Law." wl. 6. No. 2 L. & Mill, 205, %211<br />

(1987); Hale. "Bargahrio1p." pp. 606 and 618; Dawson, Econ. Dunn," p. 267; Orchard.<br />

"Dcfemr of Compulsion." pp. 105106.<br />

130. David Hume ona argued, can we seriously claim that a poor pxsmt who knows m foreign<br />

language, and lives day to day by small waga is free to lave his country? D. Hume. "Of<br />

the Origi~I aontrrt." m 2 &says and TraatLe. 268,281-282 (London: 1710). In fact, the<br />

~thfraetol~butheirunaMeto&~o.hArLtotle~thntlo~w<br />

choice dtuatiom are only involuntary m the abtract. Aristotle. Eahico N i c d , 1110a.<br />

(W.D. Ross trans. 1925). ci&d in Flacber. "Individualization." p. 1277. See. Fittc,<br />

Vidimizaton, pp. 78-79 diacussion of free choice and duress. and P. 104 N. 157 citing cases<br />

that strecs the difference betweea legal duress and d v e life situations.<br />

131. Atiyah. sypm mte 125 p. 2112.<br />

132. Brady v. United States, 390 U.S. 570 (1%8); ace. Note, '%e Udtutiondity of Plea<br />

Bnrgrining." 83 Haw. L. Rev. 1387. 13%-1403 (1910); pointing to the iaeOairtency in tbc<br />

Supreme Court's wlition adysis. The Supreme Court held that a kar of king 6rcd is<br />

mcrcivc cnougb to reodes ones self incriminating testimony in vduntary. Gmity v. New<br />

Jersey, 385 U.S. 493. 497-498 (1%7). In SpeneL v. Klein. 385 U.S. 511-515 (1%7), the<br />

Supreme Caurt held that a feu of dihnnmt rndtrs d-' ' ' ltiag testimony mvoluntary.<br />

This secmr inanrfrtent with maiataiaing tb.t fur of the death ptnalty is noncocrcive<br />

d u e one is conaidering other than the dcfcodant's psychology.<br />

133. State v. Grccn. 470 S.W. Y. 565 (Mo. 1971). M. Denicd. 405 U.S. 1U73 (197L). lhc trt<br />

is objadve; thsrr mut lm an .caul belief and a mammabk belief, Pbopk v. Coadkv, 69<br />

Cal. App. 3d. 1008. 101@1011. 138 Cal. Rptr. 515. 521-522, Cert. Denied. 434 U.S. 988<br />

(1977). Courts frequently ltresr policy masons for denying a claim or necessity, and the<br />

importame of maintaining prison order. People v. Richards. 269 CI1. App. 2d768,778,75<br />

Cal. Rplr. 597,6041 (I-); State v. Pahner. 45 Del. 308.310. RA. 2d 442.444 (0. Gea.<br />

~er., 1950); ~sople V. NOW 18 m. ~pp. MD, im N.W. Y. 916,918 (I-). see,<br />

dirurion and cases cited m Fletcbcr. "IadividualiPtion." pp. 124S1286. Conrcquently.<br />

Chrla E.ilor solution that -tes the prisoner's predicament and sodety's interest<br />

in not having prbmm escape. People v. Lover Camp, 43 Cal. App. 3d. 823,831-32.118<br />

Cal. Rpa. 110. 115 (1947); United Statcs v. Boomer. 571 F. 2d. 543, 545 (Cir.), Cert.<br />

DM, 436, U.S. 1911 (1976); United Statu v. Bailey, 444 US. 394,41243 (1980) and<br />

United SUtg v. Mer, 598. S.W. Y. 540 (Mo. App. 1930) (w a mon hdividurlizad<br />

rpporrb).Thm~~t~theCourtsmarhetherprimoucapeaorspdca<br />

of the ddena of aeadty or durcs. United Srates v. MicheIron. 559 F. 2d 567 (9th Cir.<br />

19n), (dunar); Pmple v. Luther, 394 Mich. 619,232, N.W. 2d. 184 (1975). (durcs); State<br />

v. Baker, ibid. (nearrity); People v. Lover Camp, idem. (nemrity); Pwpk v. Uoger. 66.<br />

III. 2d. 333 5 III Du. 848.362 N.E. 2d. 319 (1977), (nummity); People V. Ricbudr, idem.<br />

(noceaity). See gcnwdly. Note, "Prism Esgpe and Dchces bad on Ckditbm: A<br />

cboory of Social Prehmcc." 67 Caf. L. RN. 1183 (1979); Note "Intokmble,*' Coaditim<br />

m a Defence to Risoa Escape," 26 U.C.L.A. 11% (1979) and Note, "Duress and the Rioon<br />

@acapc: A New me for an old Dcfena," 45 S. Cd. L. Rev. 1062 (1972).


Islamic Studies, 30:3 (1991) 349<br />

For example, conarning tbe Wbility of involuntary coofedom, the Supreme Court<br />

baa~aniadividualizcdrpproeehbsredonthetotrlityd~.(3ulombev.<br />

Canoectieut, 367 US., 3%. 602 (1961); Fikes v. Alabama, 352 U.S. 191,197 (1957), Paync<br />

v. Artuua. 356. U.S. 560. 567 (1958); Haley v. Ohio. 332. U.S. 596. 599 (1948). Sec,<br />

Mdloy v. Hogan, 378 U.S. 1.7. (1964); Haynts v. W-, 373 U.S. 503 (1963) Minay<br />

v. Arinnu, 437 U.S. 385 (1978). In Cukms6e. while atstiq that dmtahcu h the utiinatc<br />

test of the ntidity of umfcdsions, the Supreme Court recognLsd that this h not &ly a<br />

quation of pychololly but nrlee of law applied to psychological facts. In Stein v. New York.<br />

346 U.S 156.182-186 (1952) m'd on other grounds. Jsctson v. Denno. 378 U.S. 368 (1964).<br />

the Cwrt uaerted that sina physical violence serves no lawful pqm& it is inhenntly<br />

d. Intamgation docs serve a axial value and, tbmfore, it i not inbcrently coercive.<br />

Sec.Pletcber. "Individualiution",pp. 1m-1mand Fiagamte. VicZindElllion, pp. SlW.<br />

ThcImpedofdmoresisevidentinthe~ofanradmarri.ges.Se~notiom<br />

concerning women's honour played a larger rde than they at present do. Sac. Memdith v.<br />

Meredith. 79 Mo. App. 636 (1899). (Threatending to kill the man who dishonoured a<br />

daugbtm is not dureaa); Shepberd v. Shepherd. 192 S.W. 658. 661-63 (1917). (threats that<br />

raulthaman~the~he~tedandpomiaedto~inotdurrrv<br />

bealeethmisastrongprerrumptiOnthattbemarrisgewasentmdhtoinMmntof<br />

moral obligations); Sec also, L.N. Bmwn. 'The Shotgun marriage," 42 Tul. L. Rev. 837<br />

(1968). D. Bradky. "Duress and Arranged Marriages," 46. Modem L. Rev. 499 (1983);<br />

Wertheimer, C h , pp. 71-n.<br />

A eue miming from outside the field of dues dmomtrata, that even juries can believe<br />

that there i h a p a choice. In Maddl v. Rraoe. 511 S.W. 2d 225 (Ts. 1974). Marshall<br />

was held priooner in his how by his neighbow's vidous boar. The boar had charged Marahdl<br />

ten or twelve timcs. MarsbaU had pmioudy disarssed the Hog's viaoumea with defendant.<br />

Eventually, the boar managed to in@ Marshall as be attempted to kave hio home. The<br />

jury found that MarsbaU was conbibutody negligent for fading to build a face around hio<br />

~,andbe*~therisLofinjurywhen,despiteofhiob~ofthe<br />

v i h propearities of boar. Madd faikd to aboot the boar. Thc Court of Appcd affhncd.<br />

Thc Supreme Court of Texan held that contributory ne-a is not a dsfoaa in stria<br />

lirbility cases. Importantly, the Court held that Marshall did not anumc the risk because<br />

he did not have a free and voluntary choice. The plaintiff's choice3 of riaking injury arc<br />

remaining a Ppironer at home mere not as a mattcr of law the vduntary choices to which<br />

the law mtiW him. Additionally. the daughter ofthe aoimal was not areaonable al-tive<br />

sina be d d have faad pnxca,tion for ouch an act. Idcm, at 2#%1. Evidently, tbe<br />

Covrtwasforcedbythe jurie8uns~emlyvadicttoa~prrtcnrionrofaviYmenx,me.<br />

'h Cow? had to rely on legal standards, and on the I@ jargon of "as a mattcr of law"<br />

which in reality betray idea of appmpriate social bebaviow. and balancing of rights and<br />

entiUemmts. ilia arc is d*arsred h Wcrtheimer, Cocrdan p. 61.<br />

Kaph v. K.plan. la. N.E. 2d. M6.710 (1962). (the threat of personal embamsmmt<br />

wuwt~asnttorendcrpl.intitibmnofqdtyofd~ti.lformaLingacon~);<br />

ace. Wertheimer. Corrdon, p. 12.<br />

Inordertopmvedterytheaccuoerha~topmvidefourwi~whobdtheseNd<br />

ret including penetration without apying. Sec, on Qcrdhf (the crime of ururing mucone of<br />

sdultery or fornication). Ibn Rushd. Biddym d-MyW, (Cairo Mumtapha Halabi. 1981),<br />

VOI. n, pp. 44043.<br />

'he MPC, docs not ~~4)gniSe threats to reputation in criminal carcs. Sac note W above<br />

and acannpanying W.<br />

WV. Lewis, 4 S.E. 2d. 464,468 (Cia. 1939). lbis case is d i d in Wertheimcr, Coercion,<br />

P. 38.<br />

Ibe Court in m, hoveva, atated that, 'lbc thnat. . . must be suf6cicnt to ovmanc<br />

the mind and will of a penon of onbary hem." Id.. p. 467. 'hk might uplrin the<br />

court's duision. Oae ferL the Court WM motivated by mutated policy (or otherwbe)<br />

conaidemtiom cspeeidly in Light of the fad that the purportbdly ~d that a -tiff


Islamic Studies, 30:3 (1991)<br />

wan a yarn- rrmn he "would have givcn him hell." Id., p. 466. If belimd by the Jmy.<br />

refuses. A angdy leavethe amtract in B's possessim and leaves. 'lh days later C telb B<br />

that A is a violent person, and that A once broke someone's arm. B bearms tenified and<br />

his will m although no cxpliat a implicit threats were levied rgeinst him, and he<br />

nuhestosbtheam~.Assumetb.tBhasnoruaoatobelievethatCisA'srl&nt.Ibe<br />

~ommon~,ifthe~ofen~will~tobetlteamianlg,~h~ld<br />

amtractvoidable. Ihe~ofarulthreatorthe~c~of B'scwchrtshould<br />

be irmnatcrinl. Islamic law, however, m this csse, can deny relief on the banb that the type<br />

of duress inflicted hm is not donable because thm is no moral or social policy resson<br />

to recognise duress ~BMOml#LOied by M explicit threat m this context.<br />

Fa a good critical PpprPbal of the MsoaaMencaa requinmcnt in Neumcm end Wcitzr.<br />

"Durese. Frce wffl," pp. 326328.<br />

Smith. at p. 348.<br />

See. Idem for the same poiat and on the indefiniteness of the reasonabkness standard.<br />

Fletcher, "IndividualiEation," p. 1293.<br />

Note 113 above end accompanying text.<br />

Notes 34 and 35. end acunupM~ text.<br />

For example, al- opposes the beating of suspeeb to obtnin evidence or confessions<br />

but he does so on baakally utilitarian grounds. Al-Ghazdi, d-Mwta$6, vol. I, 297-299.<br />

morally motivated rules such as the murder exception.<br />

Most of the rules were articulated mound the nincth to fourttenth centuries.<br />

Several voias have called for the dmlopmcnt of Islamic law but not much haa been achieved<br />

in that regard. See, on modern attempts at reform, and on Islamic law in the modern world.<br />

N.J. wulson. A History of lslunic Low (1978). especially pp. 149-225; M. Khaddiiri, 7he<br />

I k i c Conaplion of Jvstice. (1984). especially pp. 192-232.<br />

Alan Watson. Roman Lmu and Cotnparalive Low (1991), particularly pp. 97-110 and Alan<br />

Watson. L.qd TmplMtr (1974).<br />

See, on the subject of legal mental sets and the legal culture, Alan Watson, Failurn of tkc<br />

Legd Imrrgindon (1988). particularly pp. 13S154.<br />

AAA

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!