05.07.2013 Views

linguistic structures - Professor Binkert's Webpage - Oakland ...

linguistic structures - Professor Binkert's Webpage - Oakland ...

linguistic structures - Professor Binkert's Webpage - Oakland ...

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

(38) a. [Something] pleased the coach.<br />

b. [That [John] succeeded] pleased the coach.<br />

c. [John] succeeded and pleased the coach.<br />

The bracketed elements in (38) are subjects. In (38a), the sentence consists of one simple clause<br />

with one subject (something) and one tensed verb (pleased). In (38b), on the other hand, the<br />

sentence consists of two clauses, where the subject of the main clause is itself another clause, John<br />

succeeded. The function of that in (38b) is to subordinate one clause to the other, to separate them.<br />

In (38c), the word and performs a similar function of separating two clauses, only in this case it<br />

coordinates the two tensed verbs (succeeded and pleased), rather than subordinating one to the other.<br />

(37d) eliminates the that, so the two clauses are no longer separated; accordingly, the sentence is<br />

ungrammatical. It contains two tensed verbs that are not separated by either a subordinator such as<br />

that (cf. (38b)) or a coordinator like and (cf. (38c)). More importantly, its ungrammaticality is not<br />

arbitrary: it is predictable from (36). Therefore, children do not have to learn not to say (37d), any<br />

more than they have to learn not to try to look through solid objects. They are born with intuitive<br />

knowledge of the principles in (36), which evidently derive from some as yet unknown fact(s) about<br />

human brain function. These principles predict that all sentences like (37d) will be ungrammatical<br />

in any human language. This includes (37d), as well as (39d) and any others which violate (36).<br />

(39) a. The player who(m) the coach picked won.<br />

b. The player the coach picked won.<br />

c. The player who won did a backflip.<br />

d. *The player won did a backflip.<br />

e. The player won and did a backflip.<br />

Despite these remarks, it is always possible that a language might allow some particular construction<br />

under highly specified conditions even when there is a general constraint against it. After all, it is<br />

a well–known fact that languages do have exceptions. In such cases, it is useful to distinguish what<br />

is expected in language on the basis of universal principles from what is unexpected.<br />

Linguists call rules and <strong>structures</strong> that are expected UNMARKED, and those that are unexpected,<br />

because they violate general principles, MARKED. The more tightly constrained a principle is by<br />

the nature of human beings, the less likely it is to have exceptions and the more highly marked such<br />

exceptions become. For example, if the equivalent of (39d) were found to be grammatical in some<br />

language, it would be highly marked. As one would expect, marked constructions take children<br />

much longer to acquire than unmarked ones.<br />

1.6 LEVELS OF ADEQUACY<br />

There are several levels of adequacy that a linguist can attain in grammatical characterization. The<br />

first level, called OBSERVATIONAL ADEQUACY, is attained when the facts are noted. The<br />

second level, called DESCRIPTIVE ADEQUACY, is attained when the facts are described with<br />

37

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!