05.07.2013 Views

linguistic structures - Professor Binkert's Webpage - Oakland ...

linguistic structures - Professor Binkert's Webpage - Oakland ...

linguistic structures - Professor Binkert's Webpage - Oakland ...

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

LINGUISTIC STRUCTURES<br />

LECTURE NOTES AND WORKBOOK<br />

Peter J. Binkert<br />

<strong>Oakland</strong> University<br />

Rochester, Michigan


Copyright © The Langtech Corporation 2012<br />

The Langtech Corporation<br />

643 Hazy View Lane<br />

Milford, Michigan 48381-2159<br />

All rights reserved, including those of translation into foreign languages. Except for the quotation<br />

of short passages for the purposes of criticism and review, no part of this publication may be<br />

reproduced or transmitted in any form or by any means, electronic or mechanical, including<br />

photocopy, recording, or any information storage and retrieval system, without prior permission in<br />

writing from the publisher.<br />

Printed in Milford, Michigan.


PREFACE<br />

This book is not a traditional introductory textbook for <strong>linguistic</strong>s. Although many of the traditional<br />

topics are discussed in the following chapters, the book does not aim at a comprehensive summary<br />

of the discipline. Rather, the intent is to present to the student a unified theory of human language<br />

which demonstrates specifically that the structure of human language is not arbitrary and that it<br />

derives directly from genetically determined faculties of human beings. The essential nature of<br />

human language is not a matter of choice, convention, or whim. Cultural diversity among different<br />

societies and <strong>linguistic</strong> diversity among different languages and dialects reflect superficial variations<br />

on this basic, biologically determined structure.<br />

The central theme of this text is quite simple: human language reflects the capacities and limitations<br />

of human beings. There are three facts supporting this theme. First, all normal human beings,<br />

regardless of the languages they speak and the cultures they represent, have the same basic<br />

biological makeup. Second, all children learn whatever language they are exposed to in whatever<br />

cultural setting; children are not predestined to learn specific languages. Third, language acquisition<br />

in all children proceeds in a uniform and predictable fashion despite widely varying environmental<br />

conditions.<br />

These facts clearly indicate that the structure of all languages must be based on the nature of human<br />

beings. This is not an original idea; indeed, much of the current work in <strong>linguistic</strong>s in all theoretical<br />

frameworks proceeds from this position. For example, it is basic to Chomsky’s concept of <strong>linguistic</strong><br />

universals.<br />

Where this text differs from most introductory texts is in the manner in which the various<br />

subdivisions within <strong>linguistic</strong>s are described. At every point possible, the development of our theme<br />

will be bolstered by specific arguments that have reference to human biology and psychology. All<br />

components of language will be related to each other, rather than presented as discrete units, so that<br />

elements of <strong>linguistic</strong> structure, change, and variation are integrated. Our discussion of different<br />

languages and different cultures will show how <strong>linguistic</strong> divergence is constrained by <strong>linguistic</strong><br />

universals.<br />

Generally, <strong>linguistic</strong>s departments on university campuses are grouped with the social sciences<br />

(psychology, sociology, anthropology, etc.) or humanities (philosophy, music, art, literature, etc.).<br />

In either of these contexts, <strong>linguistic</strong>s is in a distinctive position to make contributions to the history<br />

of ideas. Linguistic argumentation, that is, the justification of grammars, is a highly developed<br />

methodology that can be used to make predictions about the nature of man and mind. Traditional<br />

justification of theoretical models in the natural and physical sciences derives from experimentation.<br />

The techniques of justification in biology and physics are familiar to every student. In <strong>linguistic</strong>s<br />

also, it is possible to formulate hypotheses of considerable rigor and subject them to scientific<br />

scrutiny that leads directly to their verification or refutation. This book aims to show the<br />

introductory student how this is possible.<br />

More than anything else, this text is designed to disabuse readers of the many misconceptions that<br />

surround the study of language. These fallacies include, among other things, the idea that different


dialects, different cultural patterns, and even different languages reflect different levels of human<br />

competence, as well as the prevalent idea that grammatical structure is haphazard and unjustifiable.<br />

Although it may be difficult to believe at this point, the study of grammar can lead to provocative<br />

and interesting ideas about the nature of human beings and the origin of cultural diversity.<br />

Needless to say, one cannot attain such a high level of generality about language, or anything else,<br />

without attention to detail. Therefore, in the following chapters, students will be introduced to some<br />

of the technical vocabulary of <strong>linguistic</strong>s. The aim is not to memorize facts per se, although mastery<br />

of some details is essential before application can begin; rather, it is to show how rigorous<br />

investigation can lead to meaningful generalizations. Lists of memorized facts rarely stay in<br />

people’s minds for very long, but genuine comprehension of issues does. Moreover, such<br />

comprehension can have a significant impact on one’s life. In this regard, this text aims to satisfy<br />

some of the major objectives of general education, which include, among other things, helping<br />

students understand and master basic techniques for the analysis and synthesis of ideas. Such<br />

techniques involve the ability to gather, organize, and interpret data, to separate what is significant<br />

and interesting from what is irrelevant and trivial, and to formulate hypotheses of real explanatory<br />

power. Effective thinking occurs when one is able to uncover the essential nature of any given<br />

problem and to propose reasonable solutions consistent with available resources.<br />

ii


TABLE OF CONTENTS<br />

Introduction: Linguistics and the Job Market ........................................1<br />

Chapter One: Fundamentals of Linguistics ........................................23<br />

1.1 Grammatical Characterization and Grammatical Realization ...............23<br />

1.2 The Study of Grammar ............................................28<br />

1.3 Speech and Writing ...............................................29<br />

1.4 Linguistic Argumentation ..........................................30<br />

1.5 Universal Grammar (UG) ..........................................32<br />

1.6 Levels of Adequacy ...............................................38<br />

1.7 Language Variation ...............................................43<br />

1.8 Language and Culture .............................................44<br />

1.9 Summary .......................................................47<br />

Exercises for Chapter One ................................................50<br />

Chapter Two: Phonetics and Phonology ...........................................55<br />

2.1 Phonetics .......................................................55<br />

2.1.1 Vowels ...................................................55<br />

Figure One: the Vocal Apparatus ..........................................56<br />

Figure Two: English Vowels .............................................57<br />

Figure Three: Distinctive Features for English Vowels .........................58<br />

2.1.2 Consonants ................................................59<br />

Figure Four: English Consonants, Liquids, and Glides .........................60<br />

2.1.3 Liquids and Glides ..........................................62<br />

Figure Five: the Major Phonological Categories ..............................62<br />

Figure Six: Distinctive Features for English Consonants, Liquids & Glides .........64<br />

2.1.4 Review of Issues ...........................................65<br />

2.1.5 Suprasegmentals ...........................................67<br />

2.1.6 Syllables ..................................................67<br />

2.2 Phonology ......................................................69<br />

Figure Seven: Phonological and Phonetic Representations ......................75<br />

2.3 Phonotactics .....................................................76<br />

2.4 Morphology .....................................................77<br />

2.5 The Biological Basis of Phonology ...................................79<br />

2.5.1 First Set of Observations .....................................81<br />

2.5.2 Second Set of Observations ...................................83<br />

2.5.3 Third Set of Observations ....................................85<br />

2.6 The Phonological and Lexical Components of a Grammar .................85<br />

2.7 English Spelling ..................................................87<br />

2.8 Summary of Rule Formalism........................................89<br />

2.9 Notes on Syllables ................................................89


Summary of English Sounds and Spelling ....................................90<br />

Exercises for Chapter Two ...............................................92<br />

Appendix A: Answers to Transcription Exercises .....................103<br />

Appendix B: Phonological Rules ..................................108<br />

Appendix C: Slash–dash Notation .................................111<br />

Appendix D: Phonology Problem ..................................112<br />

Appendix E: Morphology Problem .................................113<br />

Appendix F: English Vowel Shift..................................114<br />

Appendix G: English Morphology .................................115<br />

Chapter Three: Syntax .......................................................117<br />

3.1 Linguistic Argumentation Revisited .................................117<br />

3.1.1 Linguistic Argumentation: Sentence Types ......................117<br />

3.1.2 Linguistic Argumentation: Parts of Speech ......................120<br />

3.1.3 Linguistic Argumentation: Phrases ............................121<br />

3.1.4 Linguistic Argumentation: Strategies ..........................123<br />

3.2 Ordering Constraints .............................................124<br />

3.2.1 Testing Hypotheses: Reference, Omission, Placement .............125<br />

3.2.2 Language and Memory .....................................126<br />

3.3 Traditional and Structural Grammar .................................127<br />

3.4 Tense and the Internal Structure of Sentences..........................133<br />

3.5 Determiners and the Internal Structure of Noun Phrases .................137<br />

3.5.1 Abstract Elements: Ø .......................................138<br />

3.5.2 Phrase Structure Rules: First Proposal ..........................142<br />

3.6 The Endocentricity Constraint......................................145<br />

3.7 The Lexicon ....................................................147<br />

3.8 A Note on Scientific Inquiry .......................................150<br />

3.9 X–bar Syntax ...................................................152<br />

3.10 Generalizing Phrase Structure: S and NP .............................157<br />

3.11 Adjuncts (Modifiers) and Complements ..............................159<br />

3.12 Residential Grammar (RG) ........................................170<br />

Figure Eight: Features for English Morphosyntactic Categories .................183<br />

3.13 Transformational Generative Grammar ...............................191<br />

3.14 Nontransformational Generative Grammar ............................194<br />

3.15 Command Relations in Phrase Structure ..............................195<br />

3.16 Empty Categories ................................................197<br />

3.16 The English Auxiliary ............................................203<br />

3.16.1 The Facts and Generalizations ................................203<br />

3.16.2 Problems with the Classic TG Analysis ........................206<br />

3.16.3 Resolution ...............................................214<br />

3.16.4 Summary of Nominals and Verbals in RG ......................217<br />

3.16.5 Parses Illustrating the English Auxiliary ........................218<br />

iv


Exercises for Chapter Three .............................................227<br />

Appendix A: Answers to Exercises ..................................231<br />

Appendix B: Latin Syntax ........................................249<br />

Appendix C: Summary of Tree Structures ............................251<br />

Chapter Four: Semantics......................................................255<br />

4.1 Preliminary Remarks .............................................255<br />

4.2 Denotation and Connotation .......................................255<br />

4.3 Synonymy, Homonymy, and Antonymy ..............................256<br />

4.4 Hyponymy/hypernymy and Meronymy/holonymy .....................256<br />

4.5 Idioms ........................................................256<br />

4.6 Ambiguity and Paraphrase.........................................257<br />

4.7 Pragmatics .....................................................259<br />

4.8 Thematic Relations: Case Grammar .................................260<br />

4.9 The Meaning and Use of the Word Case ..............................263<br />

4.10 Problems with Case Grammar ......................................265<br />

4.11 RG Semantics ...................................................266<br />

4.12 Positional Thematic Relations in Rg .................................273<br />

4.13 Some Basic Feature Distinctions ....................................274<br />

Figure Nine I: Proximal Positional Thematic Relations ([+PST, –TMP, +PRX]) . . . 277<br />

Figure Nine II: Nonproximal Positional Thematic Relations ([+PST, –TMP, –PRX]) 277<br />

4.14 Nonpositional Thematic Relations ...................................279<br />

Figure Ten I: Proximal Nonpositional Thematic Relations ([–PST, +PRX]) ........280<br />

Figure Ten II: Nonproximal Nonpositional Thematic Relations ([–PST, –PRX]) ....280<br />

4.15 Dimensional Thematic Relations ....................................283<br />

Figure Eleven: Classificatory Thematic Relations ............................284<br />

4.16 Prototypes and Strength of Association ...............................286<br />

4.17 The Perceptual Basis of Semantics ..................................292<br />

4.18 Semantic Networks ..............................................294<br />

4.19 Postscript ......................................................296<br />

Exercises for Chapter Four ..............................................297<br />

Appendix A: Summary of Thematic Relations...............................302<br />

Chapter Five: Language, People, and Computers ...................................305<br />

5.1 Syntax and Cognition .............................................305<br />

5.2 Overview of Anaphora ............................................325<br />

Exercises for Chapter Five...............................................337<br />

v


Supplement One: The Nature of Human Language ............................339<br />

Fundamental Empirical Problems for Linguistics .......................339<br />

Theories of Language ............................................345<br />

Linguistic Universals .............................................347<br />

Types of Languages ..............................................363<br />

The Evolution of Human Language ..................................366<br />

Limitations on the Form of Natural Language .........................369<br />

Supplement Two: Grammar Review ......................................371<br />

Syntactic Categories (The Parts of Speech) ............................371<br />

Syntactic Constructions ...........................................373<br />

Morphology ....................................................374<br />

Some Inflectional Categories.......................................375<br />

Supplement Three (Part I): Typological Classification ........................376<br />

Supplement Three (Part II): Typological Classification ........................377<br />

Supplement Four (Part I): Historical Classification ...........................378<br />

Supplement Four (Part II): Historical Classification ..........................379<br />

Supplement Five (Part I): Languages of Africa and the mid East ................380<br />

Supplement Five (Part II): American Indian Languages .......................381<br />

Supplement Five (Part III): Indo–european Languages ........................382<br />

Supplement Five (Part IV): Languages of East Asia & the Pacific ...............383<br />

Supplement Five (Part V): Other Languages of Europe and Asia ................384<br />

Supplement Six: Languages and Language Groups ...........................385<br />

Supplement Seven: Some Alphabets .......................................387<br />

Supplement Eight: Sample Parses from the Langtech Parser ....................389<br />

Sample Parses Illustrating Basic Sentence Patterns .....................389<br />

Supplement Nine: Sample Parses from the Langtech Parser .....................427<br />

Sample Parses Illustrating Noun Phrases ..............................427<br />

Supplement Ten: Sample Parses from the Langtech Parser .....................431<br />

Empty Categories: Ø, [U], and [E] ..................................431<br />

Supplement Eleven: Sample Parses from the Langtech Parser ...................434<br />

Sample Parses Illustrating Participles ................................434<br />

Index .....................................................................443<br />

vi


INTRODUCTION: LINGUISTICS AND THE JOB MARKET<br />

There is no doubt about it: the competition for jobs in today’s market is intense. According to an<br />

Associated Press news story on April 25, 2012, half of all new graduates are either jobless or<br />

underemployed:<br />

“In the last year, [graduates] were more likely to be employed as waiters, waitresses,<br />

bartenders and food-service helpers than as engineers, physicists, chemists and<br />

mathematicians combined (100,000 versus 90,000). There were more working in<br />

office-related jobs such as receptionist or payroll clerk than in all computer professional jobs<br />

(163,000 versus 100,000). More also were employed as cashiers, retail clerks and customer<br />

representatives than engineers (125,000 versus 80,000).<br />

“According to government projections released last month, only three of the 30 occupations<br />

with the largest projected number of job openings by 2020 will require a bachelor’s degree<br />

or higher to fill the position – teachers, college professors and accountants. Most job openings<br />

are in professions such as retail sales, fast food and truck driving, jobs which aren’t easily<br />

replaced by computers.” (Recent College Graduates Finding Few Job Prospects, Hope Yen,<br />

Associated Press, www.detroitnews.com/article/20120425)<br />

Despite these numbers, college graduates still fare better than those without degrees according to<br />

the Bureau of Labor Statistics (Yes, A College Education Is Worth the Costs, Rodney K. Smith, USA<br />

Today, 2011, www.usatoday.com/news/opinion/forum/story/2011-12-06/). Unemployment rates<br />

decrease as education increases (Bureau of Labor Statistics, 2010, www.bls.gov):<br />

•14.9% of those without a high school diploma<br />

•10.3% of those with a high school education<br />

•7% of those with an associate degree<br />

•5.4% of those with a bachelor’s degree<br />

•2.4% of those with a professional degree<br />

•1.9% of those with a doctoral degree.<br />

Also, educational attainment correlates with income. Here’s the average weekly income for those<br />

who have jobs (Bureau of Labor Statistics, 2010, www.bls.gov):<br />

•$444 for those with less than a high school degree<br />

•$626 for those with a high school degree<br />

•$767 for those with an associate degree<br />

•$1,038 for those with a bachelor’s degree<br />

•$1,550 for those with a doctoral degree<br />

Clearly, making the most out of a college education is crucial. Before choosing a program of study,<br />

students should spend some time surfing the internet and googling such search items as “what<br />

employers want,” “skills needed for the workplace,” “trends in the marketplace,” and so on. There<br />

are many myths and traditions surrounding options like the choice of a major in college. For


2<br />

example, students often think that it will be impossible to get a job in a specific discipline unless<br />

they study that discipline in depth in college. They cannot, for instance, become a manager unless<br />

they are a business major. Actually, careers often have little to do with specific majors in college.<br />

The Employee Benefits Research Institute, reports that the average tenure for all wage and salary<br />

workers age 25 or older was 5.2 years in 2010, compared with 5.0 years in 1983 (www.ebri.<br />

org/publications, Vol 31, No 12, 2010). That means that in the United States for nearly three<br />

decades workers generally stayed at the same job for about 5 years. As a result, if individuals work<br />

for 50 years, they can expects to have about 10 different jobs during their working careers. Different<br />

sources report slightly different statistics, but surfing the internet clearly shows that frequent job and<br />

career change is the norm in today’s market.<br />

Such change is in stark contrast to the situation in the past when individuals not only kept the same<br />

job for their entire lives but also had the same job as their parents and grandparents whether they be<br />

policemen, farmers, teachers, doctors, coal miners, etc. Nowadays, on the other hand, people can<br />

expect to change not only the company they work for but actually the type of work they do, that is,<br />

change their careers. Thus, one of the first things students should consider in choosing a program<br />

of study is finding one that can provide them with the skills to be adaptable, flexible, and mobile in<br />

a global and unpredictable economy. It is unlikely that the job a student finds after graduation will<br />

be directly linked to the course content of a specific undergraduate major.<br />

Problem Solving Skills Needed for the Workplace<br />

What exactly are the skills that will prepare a student to be adaptable, flexible, and mobile? One<br />

way to answer that question is to look at the kinds of skills that various employers look for. Again,<br />

surfing the internet, one finds that employers across the board look for many of the same skills in<br />

their employees. Chief among these skills is the ability to solve problems. For example, one survey<br />

of 301 executives in Fortune 1000 companies found that 99% of the executives think that the ability<br />

to solve problems and to think critically is either an absolutely essential or very important skill for<br />

college and career readiness (The MetLife Survey of the American Teacher: Preparing Students for<br />

College and Careers, 2011, p. 21).<br />

Other studies also emphasize the importance of creative problem-solving skills. “Employers know<br />

that in business, the chessboard changes daily. As soon as we think all is fine, the economy changes<br />

or the competition makes a surprise move and the company’s own strategy must change,” said Mark<br />

Stevens, author of Your Marketing Sucks (Crown Business, 2003) and CEO of MSCO, a global<br />

marketing firm. “A person who gets locked into a set way of doing things finds it difficult or<br />

impossible to adjust. They are a drag on the business as opposed to an asset for it. [An employee<br />

must know] how to tackle challenges and opportunities in a way no one will find in a textbook.”<br />

(CNN: Top 10 Reasons Employers Want to Hire You, Rachel Zupek, www.CareerBuilder.com,<br />

2011).<br />

A multitude of sources including magazine articles, newspapers, on-line reports, scholarly papers,<br />

and books all suggest that critical thinking and problem solving skills are essential for success in


today’s job market. There is also general agreement on what such skills entail. Two on-line sources<br />

define the necessary skills as follows:<br />

(1) Quintessential Careers: What Do Employers Really Want? Top Skills and Values Employers<br />

Seek from Job-Seekers, Randall Hansen and Katharine Hansen (www.quintcareers.com, 2012).<br />

a. Analytical/Research Skills. Deals with your ability to assess a situation, seek multiple<br />

perspectives, gather more information if necessary, and identify key issues that need to<br />

be addressed. Highly analytical thinking with demonstrated talent for identifying,<br />

scrutinizing, improving, and streamlining complex work processes.<br />

b. Problem-Solving/Reasoning/Creativity. Involves the ability to find solutions to<br />

problems using your creativity, reasoning, and past experiences along with the available<br />

information and resources. An innovative problem-solver can generate workable<br />

solutions and resolve complaints.<br />

(2) UC Davis, Human Resources: What do Employers Want from Employees? (www.hr.<br />

ucdavis.edu/sdps, 2012).<br />

a. Analytical Thinking – The ability to generate and evaluate a number of alternative<br />

solutions and to make a sound decision regarding a plan of action.<br />

b. Researching – The ability to search for needed data and to use references to obtain<br />

appropriate information.<br />

c. Organizing – The ability to arrange systems and routines to streamline work and<br />

maintain order.<br />

It is important to note that sources like the above do not stress the need for workers to have<br />

extensive knowledge of particular facts in order to be employable. Actually, nowadays it is rather<br />

easy to get information about almost anything very quicky using the internet. What workers do need<br />

instead is the ability to organize, analyze and integrate the information they find so that they can<br />

make viable proposals to solve problems.<br />

The Information Explosion<br />

In addition to finding a program of study that emphasizes critical thinking and problem solving<br />

skills, students should also consider whether the program will prepare them to deal effectively with<br />

the nature of the modern workplace and the specific problems they will be asked to solve on the job.<br />

First, in today’s workplace, the amount of information that the average corporate worker must digest<br />

is enormous. Consider, for example, just the issue of emails which must be looked at, evaluated,<br />

and often answered before work on a problem can even begin. By 2014, it is projected that the<br />

average number of legitimate corporate emails a worker can expect to receive per day will be 65;<br />

3


4<br />

the average number sent will be 39 (Email Statistics Report, 2010, Sara Radicati, The Radicati<br />

Group, Inc., April, 2010). Adding instant messaging and social networking, it becomes clear that<br />

workers must handle a massive amount of data.<br />

Again, different sources provide different statistics; yet, an undeniable fact is that the internet has<br />

fostered an explosion in the amount of information that is available virtually instantaneously. “Each<br />

year the world produces 800 MB of data per person. It would take approximately 30 feet of shelf<br />

space to hold that amount of information in books. The amount of data produced each year would<br />

fill 37,000 libraries the size of the Library of Congress” (How Much Information Is There? Mark<br />

Shead, 2007; www.productivity501.com). Recent lapses from agencies like Homeland Security, the<br />

CIA, and the FBI have shown alarmingly how easy it is for important communiques to get lost in<br />

the avalanche of data even though such agencies employ experts in surveillance. While national<br />

security is rarely at stake in office emails, the point is clear: to be successful, modern workers need<br />

to be able to digest, sort, organize, and prioritize massive amounts of information efficiently and<br />

expertly.<br />

The Problems Facing Today’s Workers<br />

Another factor that students should consider in selecting a program of study involves the nature of<br />

the problems that workers face on a routine basis in the 21st century. Today’s problems are<br />

invariably complex, multi-faceted, and subtle. It used to be the case that one could formulate a<br />

problem into a relatively well-defined and stable statement, that one would know when a satisfactory<br />

solution was reached, and that one could clearly evaluate the solution objectively as being good or<br />

bad, or right or wrong. That is no longer the case for many problems facing society, government,<br />

and businesses such as the following:<br />

(3) a. Should colleagues be disciplined if they are caught using drugs?<br />

b. How should we deal with crime and violence in our schools?<br />

c. How can we make air travel safe from terrorism?<br />

d. Should people be fired if it is discovered that they are illegal aliens?<br />

e. How can we improve the gas mileage of family cars?<br />

f. Should same sex partners have medical benefits like married couples?<br />

g. How should we improve the language programs in US schools?<br />

As these examples indicate, today’s problems are frequently ill-defined and ambiguous. For<br />

example, in (3a), the question raises other questions like the following: How much drugs, What<br />

kinds of drugs, Are they prescription drugs, Is alcohol included, Is it a first offense, and so on.<br />

Often, today’s problems are associated with strong moral, social, political and professional issues.<br />

For example, it is not possible to talk about preventing violence in schools (3b) or about making air<br />

travel safer (3c) without also considering whether increased surveillance will destroy individual<br />

freedoms or whether certain policies will lead to stereotyping groups on the basis of color or<br />

ethnicity. In some instances such as (3d), there is little consensus about what the problem is, let<br />

alone how to resolve it. Overall, today’s problems are rarely fixed and stable; they involve sets of


complex, interacting issues developing in a dynamic social context. Often, new forms of problems<br />

emerge as a result of trying to understand and solve the original issues (Wicked Problems - Social<br />

Messes, Tom Ritchey, Springer, 2011). For example, proposals about gas mileage (3e) invariably<br />

raise issues about pollution, energy policies, dependence on foreign oil, the dangers of fossil fuels,<br />

the materials from which vehicles are made, and a host of other matters. As a result, in dealing with<br />

today’s problems, there is generally no right answer, and proposed solutions are not good or bad,<br />

but better or worse. To be successful, modern workers must be able to juggle competing proposals<br />

to determine which alternative satisfies the most factors or constituents in the most effective way.<br />

Abstract Thinking<br />

Summarizing, today’s workers need to be good problem solvers and creative thinkers; they need to<br />

be able to organize, analyze, and interpret massive amounts of information and to make proposals<br />

that consider all the stakeholders involved and all the possible consequences that might arise. It is<br />

with the those considerations in mind that students should approach the courses they take at<br />

university and the exercises and problems they are asked to complete in those courses. Frequently,<br />

students fail to see the connection between solving a specific problem in a particular course and the<br />

problems they will face outside of the classroom. In fact, there are strategies and procedures that<br />

are useful in attacking all problems, and teaching students how to make such connections is an<br />

objective of education. Students often miss those connections when they focus instead on what<br />

appear to them to be irrelevant facts about useless issues.<br />

The ability to form such connections is vital to success both in college and in the workplace.<br />

Consider the following scenario. A young boy about two years old is walking with his grandfather<br />

in the country near a dirt road when the grandfather says, “Alex, don’t go in the road. You could<br />

get hurt.” Later that day, the family visits some relatives who live in a suburban subdivision. Alex<br />

runs into the paved street in front of the house to get a ball. The grandfather, very upset, says to<br />

Alex, “I told you not to go into the street.” Alex looks at his grandfather as if to say, “No, you<br />

didn’t. You told me not to go into the road.” At the age of two, children cannot see the connection<br />

between a dirt road in the county and a paved street in a subdivision. Their interpretation of the<br />

world is concrete and literal. It will take a few more years before they are capable of the abstract<br />

thinking required to make such connections.<br />

Abstract thinking is a level of thinking that is removed from concrete, literal, here-and-now<br />

situations. Abstract thinking assesses a variety of specific examples of phenomena and unites them<br />

into a generalized concept that embraces all of the individual instances. Abstract thinkers are able<br />

to put together seemingly disconnected issues and see a larger picture. As an example, consider<br />

another scenario. Two people are applying for a job with an automobile manufacturer. The<br />

interviewer mentions that one of the industry’s most pressing problems is gas mileage; consumers<br />

are concerned about the cost of fuel. The interviewer asks the applicants general questions about<br />

customer satisfaction, options available on new models, electric cars, hybrids, changes needed in<br />

the industry, and so on. During the discussion of options, one applicant volunteers that she is<br />

unhappy with the little “donut” spare tires that come with cars because a person cannot drive very<br />

5


6<br />

long with them and must rush to have the flat tire fixed; she believes that cars should come with full<br />

spare tires the way they used to. The other applicant responds by saying that a full spare tire weighs<br />

more than a donut tire. The increased weight will make the car heavier and, therefore, reduce gas<br />

mileage. Who gets the job?<br />

Practice<br />

Students don’t always see the connections between the various exercises that they are assigned to<br />

complete in various courses and the “real world.” But, learning how to solve problems, think<br />

abstractly, analyze data, propose hypotheses, and argue for a particular position – all of the skills<br />

required for today’s workplace – require exactly the kind of practice one gets working on different<br />

exercises in different courses. Practice is essential. Even experienced people practice and train on<br />

a daily basis so they can maintain their expertise and develop professionally. Ballet dancers spend<br />

long hours every day at the barre practicing plies and tendus so they can become proficient. Boxers<br />

train every day; authors write every day; scientists experiment; philosophers ponder; golfers golf.<br />

It’s often said that it takes 10,000 hours of practice to achieve mastery in any skill. Students cannot<br />

expect to become successful thinkers if they don’t have practice solving a variety of different<br />

problems as often as possible. Students generally think that they should be able to solve any<br />

problem in twenty minutes, and, if they can’t, something must be wrong with them or their teachers.<br />

That is incorrect as the above facts about today’s problems clearly indicate. Developing skill in<br />

problem-solving like everything else takes practice. When students don’t see the purpose of taking<br />

a particular course to satisfy a particular general education requirement, they need to try to see the<br />

larger picture. It is exactly that larger picture – the relationship between roads and streets, the<br />

relationship between gas mileage and tire size – that is crucial to adaptability, to flexibility, to<br />

mobility, and to success.<br />

Learning by Doing<br />

Students in the United States generally believe that teachers should supply them with facts,<br />

illustrations and the specific means by which they can successfully complete an assignment. There<br />

is an excellent reason for that belief: teachers in the United States generally supply students with<br />

facts, illustrations and the specific means by which they can successfully complete an assignment.<br />

Unfortunately, the problems that one faces in life and at work do not come with instructions for their<br />

solution. In short, what happens in American classrooms frequently has little bearing on what<br />

happens outside them. When evaluation measures depend on memorization and replication, there<br />

is little motivation for creativity, imagination, and objective thought. Consequently, high school and<br />

college graduates often have great difficulty applying what they have learned in new situations. They<br />

have difficulty with abstract thinking. Complexity often paralyzes them because they have few tools<br />

to break down problems into manageable parts. They have not had enough practice doing so.<br />

Students need to have practice and experience dealing with unknowns, managing problems that have<br />

no clear answers, and evaluating competing approaches to find the best solution for the


circumstances when no single approach is completely satisfactory. As the above discussion on<br />

today’s problems shows, those are the skills that are needed in today’s workplace. A teacher’s<br />

function is not to supply students with the right answers or even with the formula to arrive at the<br />

right answers. Rather, teachers need to act more as guides, helping students figure out how to solve<br />

a problem and discover by themselves the principles that best describe the data under investigation.<br />

In that way, students become better able to cope with new and different problems, which will always<br />

occur. It is counterproductive for students to complain that teachers don’t give them the right<br />

answers or the precise way to find the right answer. After all, teachers will not be following students<br />

around for the rest of their lives pointing out the right answers to problems that arise.<br />

Most students pursue a college degree knowing that it will help them in the job market. They know<br />

that college graduates have more and better job opportunities than people without college degrees.<br />

Furthermore, there is abundant research indicating that “college graduates are healthier, contribute<br />

more to their communities, and raise kids who are better prepared academically” (How Much Is a<br />

College Degree Really Worth, Kim Clark, US News, 2008, usnews.com/education). Having decided<br />

to pursue a college education and chosen a major, an immediate concern for students is finding<br />

courses and programs (concentrations, minors, etc.) which will make them most marketable, that is,<br />

ones which will give them practice in the specific skills employers are looking for. As a result,<br />

students should select classes which will help them become innovative and creative thinkers who<br />

can make proposals and solve problems on their own. In that regard, courses in <strong>linguistic</strong>s are<br />

especially appropriate. All <strong>linguistic</strong>s courses focus on gathering, organizing, and analyzing data,<br />

setting up hypotheses to account for the data, and proposing and defending the most generalized and<br />

effective solutions. By investigating problems in a variety of languages, students of <strong>linguistic</strong>s get<br />

practice developing just those skills that employers are looking for.<br />

A Linguistic Example: English Syntax<br />

As an illustration, consider two approaches that might be used in teaching some basic facts of<br />

English syntax, which is the study of the way sentences are constructed. This illustration might<br />

appear to be absolutely irrelevant to a student’s life or to the “real world” outside of the classroom,<br />

but we will see that it isn’t. One approach to syntax begins with definitions like those in (4) which<br />

teachers ask their students to memorize.<br />

(4) a. The subject of a verb is the person or thing that performs the action in the verb.<br />

b. The object of a verb is the person or thing that receives the action in the verb.<br />

Given (4), students are then asked to find the subjects and objects in sentences like (5).<br />

(5) The dogs frightened the little girl.<br />

Applying (4) to (5), students identify the dogs as the subject phrase because they are causing the<br />

fear, and the little girl as the object phrase because she is experiencing the fear.<br />

7


8<br />

The approach, therefore, seems successful. The students have memorized some formulas, the<br />

definitions in (4), applied them in exercises, and learned a tool that can be reused elsewhere. The<br />

teachers have done their job in supplying the formula for completing the assignment.<br />

The difficulty is that English also has sentences like (6).<br />

(6) The little girl feared the dogs.<br />

In (6), the dogs are still causing the fear and the little girl is still experiencing the fear so it seems,<br />

according to (4), that the dogs is still the subject phrase and the little girl is still the object phrase.<br />

If that is correct, then we cannot say that subjects precede verbs in English and objects follow, which<br />

seems to be the case in most sentences. So something is wrong. Since students do not know how<br />

or why the definitions in (4) were proposed in the first place, they generally have no idea what to<br />

do when the definitions seem to fail as they do in sentences like (6).<br />

Now notice what is going on here at an abstract level. We have some data, which happen to be<br />

sentences in English. We have a hypothesis which describes the data, namely, (4). We get some<br />

further data which the hypothesis can’t handle. Thus, we must revise the hypothesis and look for<br />

another proposal. This is exactly what happens frequently in the workplace. Consider, for example,<br />

another scenario from the auto industry.<br />

Several years ago, Ford Motor Company produced a van called the Mercury Villager. This van<br />

originally only had a sliding door on the passenger side. Marketing analysts at Ford had determined<br />

that parents would not want to have a sliding door on the driver’s side because their children might<br />

get out of the van on the side of traffic. The other major auto manufacturers had vans with sliding<br />

doors on both sides, because their marketing analysts had determined that people would find it too<br />

inconvenient going to one side of the car to deposit items like groceries and then walking to the<br />

other side of the car to get into the driver’s seat. Having sliding doors on both sides of the van was<br />

considered a plus. Ultimately, Ford modified its design and offered a new Villager with sliding<br />

doors on both sides. “A sliding door on the driver’s side of the vehicle [was] the subject of popular<br />

demand from customers” (carpartswholesale.com/cpw/mercury~villager~parts.html). At an abstract<br />

level, this problem has the same characteristics as our grammatical problem. Ford began with data,<br />

namely, its marketing analysis of what it seemed parents wanted in a van. Ford then designed a car<br />

accordingly. But further data indicated that the design did not match all the needs of its customers.<br />

So, Ford began to produce a new van which did match the additional customer information.<br />

Returning to our grammatical example, consider now an alternative approach to describing subjects<br />

and objects which begins by looking at the data, that is, good sentences like those in (5), (6), and (7),<br />

as well as bad sentences like those in (8), where the asterisk means that the sentence is<br />

ungrammatical.<br />

(7) a. They frightened her.<br />

b. She feared them.


(8) a. *Them frightened she.<br />

b. *Her feared they.<br />

Given data like the above, it is clear that words like she and they must be distinguished from words<br />

like her and them. All native speakers of English know this fact unconsciously whether or not they<br />

have studied English grammar in school. They know that sentences like (7) are good and those like<br />

(8) are not; so they say (7), not (8), even though they usually cannot explain why. As a result,<br />

distinguishing the two groups of words is a necessity for a speaker of English, not a convention or<br />

a convenience. The distinction is part of the English language; it is not something that teachers of<br />

grammar made up.<br />

Since the two groups of words exist, suppose we give them each a name. Notice that there is<br />

nothing odd about this: we have names for all kinds of groups (cars, animals, food, laws, sports,<br />

etc.). Suppose we call words like she and they “subject pronouns” and words like her and them<br />

“object pronouns.” With these new names, we can now succinctly state the distinction between<br />

subject phrases and object phrases, also a necessity if one wants to be a speaker of English.<br />

Consider (9).<br />

(9) a. Subject phrases are specified by subject pronouns (she, they, etc.)<br />

b. Object phrases are specified by object pronouns (her, them, etc.)<br />

Given (9), students attempt to replace phrases in sentences like (5) and (6) with pronouns. The<br />

result is always sentences like (7), never (8). Therefore, students, like native speakers, immediately<br />

know what the subjects and objects are: if a phrase can be specified by a subject pronoun, then it<br />

is the subject; if it can be specified by an object pronoun, then it is an object. In addition, students<br />

learn that the principles in (9) are motivated by facts about the English language, specifically the<br />

distribution of the two groups of pronouns.<br />

The approach just illustrated gets to the heart of the matter and the result is worth repeating.<br />

Grammatical facts are not the result of convention, whim or convenience. They are a necessity;<br />

indeed, they are a biological necessity. The sentences of every human language are broken up into<br />

phrases like subject and object because the human brain cannot process unstructured material very<br />

well. Try, for example, to recall the numbers in (10) after just one reading.<br />

(10) 1 - 4 - 9 - 2 - 2 - 0 - 0 -1 - 1 - 8 - 1 - 2<br />

Now try to recall the same numbers in (11).<br />

(11) 1492 - 2001 - 1812<br />

The numbers in (11) are much easier to recall and process because they have structure. In a similar<br />

way, the sentences of human languages must be composed of structured units like subject and object.<br />

Unstructured sentences without phrases are incomprehensible to human brains. Just try processing<br />

the last sentence backwards. In short, languages have grammar, because human biology demands<br />

9


10<br />

it. Phrases which teachers of grammar arbitrarily call “subject” and “object” would exist even if<br />

there were no teachers around to name them and describe them.<br />

Again, we need to take stock at this point to see what we have done. We began with a relatively<br />

specific matter, namely, how to identify subjects and objects in English sentences. We then<br />

determined the following: first, that subjects and objects are phrases; second, that phrases are<br />

<strong>structures</strong>; third, that the sentences of all languages have such <strong>structures</strong>; fourth, that sentence<br />

structure is an essential property of language; and fifth, that the properties of language are<br />

biologically determined. In short, the study of grammar is essentially a branch of biology. The<br />

transition here has been a bit abrupt to be wholly convincing; in the discussion below, the argument<br />

will be justified in further detail. At this point, however, it is possible to understand the<br />

methodology and to see what the overall objective is. Specifically, we are attempting to find the<br />

most generalized and comprehensive way to account for the data before us. At an abstract level, that<br />

is exactly what today’s workers must do on the job.<br />

The two approaches mentioned above have been called deductive and inductive. In the deductive<br />

approach, one begins with the principle (rule, theory, definition, etc.) and tries to apply it to the data.<br />

We began with (4) and applied it to (5). In the inductive approach, one begins with the data and tries<br />

to discover what the principle (rule, theory, definition, etc.) is. We looked at good sentences like<br />

(7) and bad sentences like (8) and then formulated (9).<br />

Since the principles in (9) are objective and explicit, they are verifiable. Testing them with other<br />

data reveals that they are, in fact, more robust than the definitions in (4), which fail in many cases:<br />

(12) a. The stewardess is cooking the meals. She is cooking them.<br />

b. The meals are cooking. They are cooking.<br />

(13) a. The laundress is ironing the shirts. She is ironing them.<br />

b. The shirts iron easily. They iron easily.<br />

(14) a. The waitress tasted the potatoes. She tasted them.<br />

b. The potatoes tasted fine. They tasted fine.<br />

(15) a. The girl broke the windows. She broke them.<br />

b. The windows broke. They broke.<br />

The inductive approach supplies students with an exercise in problem solving, critical thinking, and<br />

objective analysis. It has the potential of uncovering important generalizations like the principles<br />

in (9) and of helping students understand that such principles are justifiable and, in fact, inevitable<br />

when they are driven by an empirical investigation of the data. As a result, rather than learning<br />

something by rote, students can develop skills for life-long learning, skills that can help even when<br />

there are no teachers available.


In the above illustration, if students focus on the terms “subject” and “object,” they might conclude<br />

that the exercise is irrelevant to their life in the real world, that knowledge of grammatical terms will<br />

not help them on the job. Of course, that is probably correct: very few promotions depend on<br />

knowledge of grammar. But the criticism misses the point. The above illustration is an exercise in<br />

problem solving, in learning to think abstractly, and in formulating robust hypotheses. The solution<br />

to any problem begins with collecting, sorting, and organizing the data, no matter what the data<br />

involve. That step is followed by attempting to find generalizations and connections to account for<br />

the data, principles that will explain the data. In turn, those principles need to be tested on new data<br />

to see if they are robust. When they fail, alternative solutions need to be tried and retested to see if<br />

they are successful. In the end, one produces the best possible proposal. The people who produce<br />

the best proposals are the ones who advance in their careers.<br />

There is a TV commercial which ask the following question: “How can rice production in India<br />

affect wheat output in the U.S, the shipping industry in Norway, and the rubber industry in South<br />

America?” (T. Rowe Price ad; www.youtube.com/watch?v=Ae5BH5KdcI0) The underlying<br />

message of the commercial is that companies, workers, and people in general must be able to make<br />

such connections, because understanding connections that are important and discovering<br />

connections that no one has noticed before are crucial in finding solutions to problems. It is,<br />

therefore, essential that students make every effort to try to understand how the exercises they are<br />

asked to complete in their courses do, in fact, apply to the lives.<br />

Initially, many students find an inductive approach frustrating; they would prefer that teachers tell<br />

them what to memorize and then test them on their recall. Rather than trying to understand why one<br />

proposal is better than another, they just want to know which one will be on the next test. But<br />

memorization is not learning, and knowledge is not constant. Further, people do not succeed in a<br />

career just by knowing a lot of existing facts. We discover and uncover new phenomena every day<br />

which require changes in existing explanations, theories, practices, and methods. Education must<br />

emphasize the fact that there often are no right answers, only what we know at any given moment.<br />

The purpose of education is to bring students to the point where they can continue to learn on their<br />

own without teachers to guide them.<br />

In short, good teachers strive to make themselves unnecessary by making their students self-reliant.<br />

If a few courses that students take during their education attain that outcome, then students have a<br />

lasting model for life-long learning and for greater adaptability in the workplace. For that to happen,<br />

students need to be given exercises and problems that are new and different from what they have<br />

practiced before. It is useful to remember that the average workers will have ten different jobs<br />

during their working careers. Memorization of a lot of facts is not going to help students cope with<br />

a fluid and variable job market, one that is evolving so fast that it is difficult to keep up with the<br />

changes. The more practice students have with the greater varieties of problems, the broader their<br />

perspectives become. In turn, this broader experience will help them be more adaptable, more<br />

flexible, and more mobile. Although a diploma by itself will give students an edge in securing<br />

employment, they will fare much better over time if that diploma includes courses that give them<br />

the skills and perspectives they need to be responsive to the dynamic nature of today’s job market.<br />

11


12<br />

Another Linguistic Example: English Phonology<br />

Let us consider next another <strong>linguistic</strong> example, this time from phonology, the study of the sounds<br />

of language. Verbs in English come in a variety of tenses such as present tense (walks), past tense<br />

(walked), and future tense (will walk). When people are asked how to form the past tense of regular<br />

English verbs, they generally respond with a reference to written English and say something like,<br />

“Add an ed to the end.” Such a rule cannot be part of the natural grammar of any language.<br />

Children know how to correctly produce the past tense of regular verbs long before they learn to<br />

read and write, let alone spell correctly. Indeed, some adults are illiterate; still, they know how to<br />

form the past tense of regular verbs. Writing is based on convention, and learning to write is<br />

optional. There are hundreds of languages which have never been written down; conversely, there<br />

is no natural human language that exists only in written form. These are facts; they form part of our<br />

corpus of data that must be accounted for. They indicate that no language has any natural<br />

grammatical rule based on writing. Our discussion of English syntax above lead to a hypothesis that<br />

the rules of natural grammar are based on human biology. Language is a product of the human<br />

language apparatus, which includes the brain and the organs of speech and hearing. It is important<br />

to investigate whether this hypothesis can be sustained in other aspects of language like phonology.<br />

Now notice that there are actually three ways to pronounce the past tense of regular English verbs.<br />

First, the past tense is pronounced as the sound [t] in a verb like race (They raced from the house).<br />

Second, it is pronounced as the sound [d] in a verb like raise (They raised their hands) or raze (They<br />

razed the building meaning ‘They demolished the building’). And third, it is pronounced as a<br />

separate syllable with the reduced vowel [c] before [d] in a verb like rate (They rated the movies)<br />

or raid (They raided the refrigerator). So, we have the following three possibilities which clearly<br />

show that spelling does not determine the correct form of the past tense:<br />

(16) a. [t] raced and also coped, hiked, laughed, ached, etc.<br />

b. [d] raised, razed and also combed, hugged, loved, aged, etc.<br />

c. [cd] rated, raided and also coded, hunted, loaded, aided, etc.<br />

It is also clear from the above examples that the correct past tense for any given regular verb ([t],<br />

[d], or [cd]) cannot be random. Young children typically try to change irregular verbs into regular<br />

verbs, saying things like I goed there. Importantly, children make up such forms without ever<br />

having heard them. No matter how inelegant an adult’s speech is, no adult would ever say<br />

something like I goed there yesterday. Further, if go were a regular verb, its past tense would have<br />

to be pronounced goed, and children’s spontaneous production of forms like goed indicates that they<br />

know that. All this indicates clearly that children do not acquire their native language by simply<br />

imitating the people around them; there must be more to language acquisition that imitation.<br />

Second, when speakers coin new verbs, they always make them regular and pick the appropriate past<br />

tense marker from among the three possibilities given in (16). Consider, for example, the verb<br />

material girl in a sentence like Madonna has material girled her way to superstardom. Notice that<br />

the [d] variant in example (16b) is the only possible option. This means that when the verb material<br />

girl was first used, its past tense had to be pronounced with a [d] and not either a [t] or an [cd]. It


is worth noting here that people, including children, invent new words all the time and, when they<br />

do, they always make them regular with the expected variations. Consider the following examples:<br />

(17) a. I ketchuped up my French Fries. (A five-year-old child)<br />

b. She two-footed that landing. (A TV commentator on figure skating)<br />

c. We clearanced those dresses. (A department store sales person)<br />

Some new past tense verbs that have recently become common include transitioned, decontented,<br />

googled, texted, friended, etc. The essential fact is that native speakers automatically understand<br />

all these words the first time they hear them.<br />

If the form of regular past tenses is not random and the determining factor is not spelling, then there<br />

is an obvious question: What is it that governs the formation of the past tense of regular verbs? To<br />

answer that question, one must first gather the necessary data to see exactly where each of the three<br />

variants for the past tense occur. Note that this step is exactly the step one must take on the job<br />

when trying to solve any problem, namely, one must gather and organize the data. Doing so in the<br />

present case yields data like the following (ignore the spelling and listen to the sounds):<br />

(18) a. [t] occurs in verbs ending in the sounds [p] (hyped), [k] (cracked), [f] (cuffed), [s]<br />

(kissed), etc.<br />

b. [d] occurs in verbs ending in the sounds [b] (robbed), [g] (shrugged), [v] (moved), [z]<br />

(cruised), etc.<br />

c. [cd] occurs in verbs ending in the sounds [t] (granted) and [d] (guarded)<br />

Testing and verifying the data in (18) is the next step. One looks at as many different regular verbs<br />

as possible to see if the statements are correct. Such investigation reveals that the statements, in fact,<br />

are correct; however, the statements are no more than a list, and a list does not explain why the<br />

sounds are distributed as they are. In other words, why is [p] in (18a) and not (18b) or (18c)? These<br />

are very important steps in proposing solutions to any problem: one must not only gather, organize,<br />

and verify the data; one must explain why the data fall out the way they do if one is going to put<br />

forth the most robust proposal about the data. Although this is a theoretical example about English<br />

phonology, one can still discuss its effectiveness as a matter of cost. The analysis in (18) is not very<br />

cost-effective theoretically because it reveals no generalizations. It is not a very good way to<br />

account for the data because it is merely a list. We need to look for common features among the<br />

items in the list to see why they are in one list and not the other. We need to look for<br />

generalizations. To see what this means in a situation one is more likely to encounter in business,<br />

consider the following example.<br />

In the business world, cost is often a primary consideration. The choice of one car design over<br />

another will often depend on its cost-effectiveness. It is most cost-effective for a manufacturer to<br />

vary only the exterior of various models and to use the same underlying mechanical and electrical<br />

systems, the same chassis, the same engines, etc. If every vehicle in a manufacturer’s fleet is built<br />

in a completely different way from every other vehicle and there are no common features, costs will<br />

13


14<br />

increase. Thus, manufacturers look for designs that can be generalized over many different specific<br />

vehicles. It is not an accident that many vehicles look alike.<br />

Similarly, in designing homes in a subdivision, builders will use the same underlying floor plan and<br />

only vary the exterior elevations because that cuts down on costs. Architects will put bathrooms on<br />

the second floor above bathrooms on the first floor rather than on opposite sides of the house<br />

because that design is more cost effective. If you ask the architect why the upstairs bathroom is<br />

where it is and not somewhere else, the architect can give you the reason and that reason probably<br />

has to do with cost.<br />

In designing vehicles and buildings, engineers and architects will look for ways in which they can<br />

utilize as many of the same features as they can in all their products as a cost-saving measure. They<br />

will try to generalize. Of course, the same is true not only in the automobile and construction<br />

industries, but other businesses as well. At an abstract level, that is exactly what we need to do with<br />

the data in (18). We need to look for generalizations. Specifically, we need to determine why the<br />

data in (18) fall out the way they do. What do the members of each group have in common?<br />

Since language is a product of human biology, we can expect that the formation of the past tense is<br />

governed by a specific set of principles which are directly related to the nature of the human vocal<br />

apparatus, the part of human anatomy concerned with producing sounds. That expectation turns out<br />

to be correct. To see this, consider first, the verbs race and raise. Notice that the final sound of the<br />

verb race is [s] and the final sound of the verb raise is [z]. The difference between [s] and [z] is<br />

technical. When speakers make the sound [s], the vocal cords, which are located in the throat and<br />

help to produce different sounds, do not vibrate, which means that they do not produce a buzzing<br />

sound. There is no buzzing sound when one says [sssssss], for example. On the other hand, when<br />

speakers make the sound [z], the vocal cords do vibrate and produce a buzzing sound, which can be<br />

heard when one says [zzzzzzz]. Most native speakers do not consciously realize this difference, but<br />

they instinctively know when they should vibrate their vocals cords and when they shouldn’t.<br />

Actually, speakers can feel the difference between the sounds if they place a hand on their throat<br />

when they say [sssssss] and [zzzzzzz].<br />

Now notice that there is no vocal cord vibration in the sound [t], but that there is vocal cord vibration<br />

in the sound [d]. Again, speakers can actually feel the tension in their throat when they make the<br />

sound [d], and the tension is the same when they make the sound [z]. However, there is no similar<br />

tension in saying either [s] or [t]. Linguists call sounds which involve vibration of the vocal cords<br />

“voiced” sounds, and those which do not involve vibration of the vocal cords “voiceless” sounds.<br />

During the production of words, it is natural to put sounds together that have the same features, that<br />

is, put voiced sounds together and voiceless sounds together. There are lots of English words that<br />

end in the sounds [st] (raced, missed, passed, etc.) and lots that end in [zd] (raised, dazed, posed,<br />

etc.). However, there are no English words that end in either the sounds [sd] or the sounds [zt],<br />

because such words would join voiced and voiceless sounds together.<br />

Therefore, as a result of the nature of the vocal apparatus, a verb like race, which ends in [s]<br />

(voiceless), should have a past tense that is pronounced with a [t] (voiceless), and it does. A verb


like raise, which ends in a [z] (voiced), should have a past tense that is pronounced with a [d]<br />

(voiced), and it does. Using the technical terms, part of the rule for forming the past tense of regular<br />

verbs is as follows:<br />

(19) a. The past tense is pronounced [t], which is voiceless, in regular verbs that end in<br />

voiceless sounds (coped [pt], hiked [kt], laughed [ft], raced [st], etc.).<br />

b. The past tense is pronounced [d], which is voiced, in regular verbs that end in voiced<br />

sounds (rubbed [bd], hugged [gd], loved [vd], raised [zd], razed [zd], etc.).<br />

Consider now the third variant in (16), namely, the past tense [cd] in verbs like hunted, rated,<br />

handed, raided, etc. Notice that there are no words in English that end in the sounds [tt] or the<br />

sounds [dd]. Be careful not to think of spelling in such cases. A verb like putt in The golfer does<br />

not putt well ends in the sound [t], not the sounds [tt]. There is a good reason for this: English does<br />

not allow double consonants at the end of any word or syllable. So, the variants in (19) can’t apply<br />

when a verb already ends in [t] or [d]. In such cases, English uses the third form [cd], making the<br />

past tense a separate pronounceable syllable. The full set of rules is as follows:<br />

(20) a. The past tense is pronounced [t], which is voiceless, in regular verbs that end in<br />

voiceless sounds (coped [pt], hiked [kt], laughed [ft], raced [st], etc.).<br />

b. The past tense is pronounced [d], which is voiced, in regular verbs that end in voiced<br />

sounds (rubbed [bd], hugged [gd], loved [vd], raised [zd], razed [zd], etc.).<br />

c. The past tense is pronounced [cd] in regular verbs that end in a [t] or a [d] (hunted [tcd],<br />

rated [tcd], handed [dcd], raided [dcd], etc.)<br />

Notice that (20) is much more cost-effective theoretically than (18). Whereas (18) is merely a list<br />

of items without any principle, (20) explains clearly why each item is in the list that it is in. It is that<br />

kind of generalized solution that linguists are looking for. It is also the kind of generalized solution<br />

that employers are looking for from their employees.<br />

With generalizations such as those in (20), we can now begin to answer some fundamental questions<br />

regarding the acquisition of such principles by children, namely, how they mange to acquire them<br />

so quickly and why they make the kinds of mistakes they do. It is clear that the rules for forming<br />

the correct past tense of regular verbs are known unconsciously to all native speakers of English,<br />

including toddlers. Because the principles are based on the nature of the human vocal apparatus,<br />

they are natural and can be acquired relatively quickly. Furthermore, the past tense of irregular<br />

verbs – forms like went for the past tense of go – are unpredictable and, in a sense, unnatural. It<br />

takes children a long time to master such forms. That is why three-year-old children say things like<br />

He hurted me, which they have never heard; they haven’t yet realized that hurt is an irregular verb.<br />

Note that, if it were a regular verb, its past tense would have to be hurted, following (20c) and<br />

parallel to other regular past tenses like hunted, hoisted, handed, hoarded, etc.<br />

Given the above discussion, a child exposed to English must only figure out that the English past<br />

tense is signaled by adding a [t] or [d] type sound to the end of the verb. The distribution of the<br />

three variants ([t], [d], and [cd]) is not something that the child must worry about. That distribution<br />

15


16<br />

follows largely from the nature of the human vocal apparatus, which makes the distribution of the<br />

variants a matter of necessity, rather than free choice. In short, there is no guesswork involved in<br />

forming the past tense of regular verbs. As a result, we can account for the fact that children acquire<br />

knowledge of the past tense rapidly and without instruction. We also can explain why children<br />

invent forms such as hurted, which they have never heard. The principles prevent hurtt and hurtd.<br />

Most important, children do not need to hear the past tense of every regular verb in order to know<br />

which of the three possible endings is appropriate; from hearing a small number of forms, they can<br />

derive all the rest. These are some of the reasons why children acquire their native language so<br />

rapidly, and why language development can proceed normally even in cases of neglect, abuse,<br />

disease, poverty and other unfavorable circumstances. What makes language acquisition possible<br />

in children is this: the rules – the grammar – of all languages are not haphazard, unpredictable and<br />

random. Rather, they are based on the principles, capacities, and limitations of the human language<br />

apparatus, which all normal children share. As a result, in almost all cases, children can acquire any<br />

language as a native language without even realizing that they are doing it.<br />

Native speakers of English understand the grammar of English completely; yet, their knowledge of<br />

the grammar is generally unconscious. For example, it is safe to say that no one reading this<br />

discussion was consciously aware of the phonetic variations in the past tense ([t], [d], and [cd])<br />

unless he or she happened to have taken a course in English grammar taught by someone with<br />

expertise in <strong>linguistic</strong>s. Since the knowledge is unconscious, it follows that parents do not teach<br />

their children the rules of grammar. Quite clearly, parents cannot teach their children a set of rules<br />

if they are not consciously aware of what the rules are. So then, how do children acquire their native<br />

language if no one teaches it to them? The answer is quite simple. The rules of language are based<br />

on principles that are directly related to the nature of the human language apparatus which matures<br />

as children acquire their native language. Children acquire the rules of their native language as a<br />

natural part of their development because the rules, like those in (20), have a natural basis.<br />

Acquiring a native language is like acquiring the skills and coordination for walking. Even without<br />

specific help or prodding from parents, all normal children will eventually walk if they get the<br />

proper nourishment necessary for the physical requirements of the task such as strength and balance.<br />

Similarly, all normal children will eventually acquire a native language if they get the proper<br />

<strong>linguistic</strong> nourishment, which means only that they need to be exposed to some language or<br />

languages. That is why absence of the ability to acquire a native language as a child is so rare.<br />

Again, as before, notice what is going on here at an abstract level. We have some data, which<br />

happen to be about past tenses in English. We have a hypothesis which describes the data, namely,<br />

that past tenses are formed by adding ed to the end of the verb. We observe some further data which<br />

the hypothesis can’t handle, namely, that children know how to form past tenses before they know<br />

how to spell. Thus, we must revise the hypothesis and look for another proposal. The revision led<br />

to the list of alternatives in (18). We determined that lists like (18) are unsatisfactory; they are not<br />

cost-effective because they reveal no generalizations. What is needed is a set of principles that can<br />

explain the behavior of native speakers, in particular, the fact that they can produce and understand<br />

an unlimited number of new past tenses and can predict what the correct form will be. Accordingly,<br />

we revised (18) to (20) relating the data to human biology and giving a real explanation for why the<br />

examples fall out the way they do. In other words, what we have done with this problem in


phonology is exactly what we did with the problem in syntax, and, at an abstract level, exactly what<br />

Ford engineers did when they modified the design of the Villager.<br />

Linguistics<br />

It is hard to imagine spending one waking moment without language. Whether we are alone or<br />

among other people, whether we dream or daydream, whether we write poetry, follow a recipe,<br />

cheer for the home team, speak or sing, language is involved. All normal children acquire a native<br />

language, no matter where they are born, what the language is or what their home life is like.<br />

Absence of the ability to acquire language is very rare. People who are deaf have language; so do<br />

those who are blind, mute, completely paralyzed, intellectually disabled, or emotionally disturbed.<br />

Language can be disrupted by injury or disease, processed by machines, altered for special<br />

occasions, and exploited for ulterior motives. Despite this extraordinary presence, versatility and<br />

variability, every human language, whether Old English or Modern Japanese, shares universal<br />

features which are directly related to human biology.<br />

The goal of courses in <strong>linguistic</strong>s is to formulate a theory of language that explains what language<br />

is and how it is acquired and used. In particular, a theory of language must explain how all normal<br />

children can master any of the world’s languages as a native language and can do so without any<br />

specific instruction from parents or care-givers, whereas learning a language as an adult requires<br />

intense study and training. In fact, this problem is huge since it is ultimately concerned with the<br />

biological characteristics of human beings, specifically, with the characteristics of the human<br />

language apparatus which includes the brain and the organs of speech and hearing. Linguistics<br />

courses break down that huge problem into manageable subparts to find satisfactory explanations.<br />

Since many <strong>linguistic</strong> courses deal with English, which students already know, <strong>linguistic</strong>s is an<br />

excellent discipline for practicing the skills needed for success in the workplace. Students learn how<br />

to collect, organize, and analyze data in English and other languages, make hypotheses to account<br />

for the data, alter hypotheses to accommodate newly discovered data, and evaluate competing<br />

proposals to choose the most viable and robust analysis.<br />

Because language is so pervasive and so peculiarly human, students of <strong>linguistic</strong>s find careers in<br />

many different areas. Some, such as teachers, computer scientists, and speech therapists, use<br />

<strong>linguistic</strong>s directly; others such as market analysts, editors, and advertising executives, use it<br />

indirectly. Still others use their undergraduate major in <strong>linguistic</strong>s as a springboard to careers in law,<br />

education, business, artificial intelligence, medicine, and international relations, as well as graduate<br />

study in <strong>linguistic</strong>s and other fields. A list of career opportunities posted by the Linguistic Society<br />

of America is included as an Addendum to this Introduction. That list and other useful information<br />

can be found at lsadc.org. More job opportunities are available at linguistlist.org/jobs.<br />

Quite naturally, <strong>linguistic</strong>s courses are of direct benefit to language teachers, especially teachers of<br />

ESL (English as a Second Language). A typical ESL class has students who speak different native<br />

languages with varying levels of proficiency in both English and their native language. It is<br />

impossible for ESL teachers to know ahead of time what kinds of questions about English grammar<br />

17


18<br />

the students in such mixed classes will ask. The best preparation for ESL teachers is a solid<br />

understanding of English <strong>linguistic</strong>s, that is, a <strong>linguistic</strong> description of English grammar such as the<br />

description given in this book. This does not mean that ESL teachers should memorize the various<br />

analyses given here. Quite the opposite is the case: a formal <strong>linguistic</strong> description is not going to<br />

be very helpful to students learning English. What is important is that ESL teachers develop skill<br />

in <strong>linguistic</strong> analysis, that they learn how to look at languages properly, not as chaotic and whimsical<br />

collections of rules, but as systems rooted in human biology. In this way, ESL teachers can<br />

understand the facts and issues behind their students’ questions and know that there is a real<br />

explanation for those facts. As a result, they will be able to teach English and to answer students’<br />

questions in a way that is truly meaningful.<br />

Many <strong>linguistic</strong>s courses satisfy the general education requirement in formal reasoning because they<br />

emphasize objective methods of analysis, synthesis and evaluation. They are specifically designed<br />

to introduce students to systematic ways of organizing, processing, and analyzing data. The focus<br />

on all LIN courses is on formulating hypotheses explicitly and testing them rigorously. In these<br />

courses, students are asked to solve individual problems in English and a variety of languages as a<br />

means to developing strategies and expertise for solving any kind of problem. Overall, students<br />

learn how to develop explanatory models that can predict the phenomena they observe, that is,<br />

students learn how to propose solutions to problems that are rigorous enough to incorporate the ever<br />

expanding corpus of data. As this entire discussion has indicated, the skills that students acquire in<br />

<strong>linguistic</strong>s are exactly the skills needed in today’s workplace.<br />

Since courses in <strong>linguistic</strong>s typically involve investigation of data in a variety of different languages,<br />

they also help to give students a global, multi-cultural perspective. In today’s world, information<br />

can be almost instantly shared around the globe, as phenomena like the Arab spring testified so<br />

stunningly. Companies and businesses have global interests and must adapt their products and<br />

messages to widely divergent populations. They cannot afford to be egocentric or sociocentric.<br />

Now, more than ever before, it is important for students to understand different cultures and different<br />

ways of looking at the world. Linguistics by its very nature provides students with that global<br />

perspective.<br />

We began this discussion by noting that there are many myths and traditions surrounding options<br />

like the choice of a major in college, for example, that students often think it will be impossible to<br />

get a job in a specific discipline unless they study that discipline in depth in college. Another myth<br />

is that a college education ought to be quantifiable, that students ought to be able to hold up a bunch<br />

of books upon graduation and say, “I am educated because I know everything in these books.” But<br />

expertise in any area is not tangible; it is not something a person can weigh. Becoming a good<br />

golfer or a prima ballerina, for example, involves practice, false starts, and bad days. A good golfer<br />

may be under par one day and over it the next. A ballerina may perform flawlessly on one evening,<br />

and falter on another. Of course, what makes a golfer and a ballerina very good is that they are<br />

generally just that: very good. Over time, we can measure the success of a golfer and a ballerina<br />

with such quantifiable records as scores and box office receipts. But those measures are the effects<br />

of the expertise, not the expertise itself. There are thousands of excellent golfers who have never<br />

won a tournament and thousands of proficient ballerinas who have never made it to the big stage.


The ability to solve problems, to organize and analyze data, to come up with proposals that are<br />

innovative, creative, and robust takes insight, and insight is intangible. It cannot be weighed. The<br />

confidence and security that lead one to perform well on the job are a consequence of practice and<br />

training. Students should not look at their education as something that will give them a store of<br />

enumerable facts or an arsenal of memorized information. Education is about developing intuition,<br />

sensitivity, vision, and perspective, and those attributes are qualities that cannot be directly<br />

measured. Moreover, it is those kinds of attributes that will help students succeed in today’s<br />

variable and unpredictable job market.<br />

19


20<br />

ADDENDUM: CAREER OPPORTUNITIES IN LINGUISTICS<br />

Monica Macaulay and Kristen Syrett (Linguistic Society of America)<br />

Work in the computer industry: Training in <strong>linguistic</strong>s can equip you to work on speech<br />

recognition, text-to-speech synthesis, artificial intelligence, natural language processing, and<br />

computer-mediated language learning.<br />

Work in education: People with a background in <strong>linguistic</strong>s and education can develop materials<br />

for different populations, train teachers, design assessments, find effective ways to teach languagerelated<br />

topics in specific communities, or use the language of a community effectively in instruction.<br />

Many applied linguists are involved in teacher education and educational research.<br />

Teach English as a Second Language (ESL) in the United States or abroad: If you want to teach<br />

ESL in the US, you will probably need additional training in language pedagogy, such as credentials<br />

in Teaching English as a Second or Other Language (TESOL). Many teaching positions abroad<br />

require only an undergraduate degree, but at least some specialized training in the subject will make<br />

you a much more effective teacher. Linguistics can give you a valuable cross-language perspective.<br />

Teach at the university level: If you go on to get a graduate degree in <strong>linguistic</strong>s you might teach<br />

in departments such as Linguistics, Philosophy, Psychology, Speech/Communication Sciences,<br />

Anthropology, English, and departments focused on specific foreign languages.<br />

Work as a translator or interpreter: Skilled translators and interpreters are needed everywhere,<br />

from government to hospitals to courts of law. For this line of work, a high level of proficiency in<br />

the relevant language(s) is necessary, and additional specialized training may be required.<br />

Teach a foreign language: Your students will benefit from your knowledge of language structure<br />

and your ability to make certain aspects of the language especially clear. You will need to be very<br />

proficient in the relevant language, and you may need additional training in language pedagogy.<br />

Work on language documentation or conduct fieldwork: Some agencies and institutes seek<br />

linguists to work with language consultants in order to document, analyze, and preserve languages<br />

(many of which are endangered). Some organizations engage in language-related fieldwork,<br />

conducting language surveys, establishing literacy programs, and translating documents of cultural<br />

heritage.<br />

Work in the publishing industry, as a technical writer, or as a journalist: The verbal skills that<br />

linguists develop are ideal for positions in editing, publishing, and writing.<br />

Work for a testing agency: Linguists help prepare and evaluate standardized exams and conduct<br />

research on assessment issues.


Work with dictionaries (lexicography): The development of good dictionaries requires the help<br />

of qualified <strong>linguistic</strong> consultants. Knowledge of phonology, morphology, historical <strong>linguistic</strong>s,<br />

dialectology, and socio<strong>linguistic</strong>s is key to becoming a lexicographer.<br />

Become a consultant on language in professions such as law or medicine: The subfield of<br />

forensic <strong>linguistic</strong>s involves studying the language of legal texts, <strong>linguistic</strong> aspects of evidence,<br />

issues of voice identification, and so on. Law enforcement agencies such as the FBI and police<br />

departments, law firms, and the courts hire linguists for these purposes.<br />

Work for an advertising company: Companies that specialize in advertising often do extensive<br />

<strong>linguistic</strong> research on the associations that people make with particular sounds and classes of sounds<br />

and the kind of wording that would appeal to potential consumers.<br />

Work for the government: The federal government hires linguists for the Foreign Service, the<br />

Federal Bureau of Intelligence (FBI), the National Security Agency (NSA), the Central Intelligence<br />

Agency (CIA), the Department of Defense, the Department of Education, and so on. Similar<br />

opportunities may exist at the state level.<br />

Become an actor or train actors: Actors need training in pronunciation, intonation, and different<br />

elements of grammar in order to sound like real speakers of a language or dialect. They may even<br />

need to know how to make mistakes to sound like an authentic non-native speaker.<br />

http://www.lsadc.org/info/ling-faqs-whymajor.cfm<br />

21


CHAPTER ONE: FUNDAMENTALS OF LINGUISTICS<br />

1.1 GRAMMATICAL CHARACTERIZATION AND GRAMMATICAL REALIZATION<br />

The first language that children acquire during childhood is called their NATIVE LANGUAGE.*<br />

As they mature, children are considered NATIVE SPEAKERS of that language. Knowledge of<br />

one’s native language is quite special. It differs in many ways from the knowledge one gains<br />

studying a language in school, for example, in Spanish class. In particular, native speakers are not<br />

generally aware of what they know about their native language. Also, they usually cannot describe<br />

what they know or explain how they know it. Their knowledge is unconscious. To see this,<br />

consider the following sentences, which differ only in that (1b) contains the word that:<br />

(1) a. Do you think the judge will tell the truth?<br />

b. Do you think that the judge will tell the truth?<br />

Every native speaker of English knows that these two sentences are yes/no questions, that is,<br />

questions that can get either a positive or negative answer. Now suppose that a person does not<br />

know who will tell the truth and wants to find out. In such a case, the person could ask a<br />

WH–question, which is a question that begins with a WH–word like who, what, where, etc. Given<br />

sentences like those in (1), every native speaker unconsciously knows that the results of attempting<br />

to ask such a WH–question will be different. Sentence (2a), a WH–question related to (1a), is<br />

perfectly GRAMMATICAL, meaning it does not violate any rules. On the other hand, sentence<br />

(2b), a WH–question related to (1b) and containing the word that, is UNGRAMMATICAL,<br />

meaning it violates some rule (an asterisk at the beginning of a sentence indicates that it is<br />

ungrammatical).<br />

(2) a. Who do you think will tell the truth?<br />

b. *Who do you think that will tell the truth?<br />

There is a specific principle that rules out sentences like (2b), yet native speakers typically are not<br />

consciously aware of what that principle is. Nor can they explain why the word that can be left out<br />

of (3a) to produce the synonymous (3b), whereas a similar deletion in (4a) produces the<br />

ungrammatical (4b).<br />

(3) a. The lawyers that the judges admire will tell the truth.<br />

b. The lawyers the judges admire will tell the truth.<br />

(4) a. The lawyers that admire the judges will tell the truth.<br />

b. *The lawyers admire the judges will tell the truth.<br />

_______<br />

* Words and phrases in boldface capitals are important concepts. They are found in the index,<br />

which indicates the page(s) on which the concepts are introduced or reviewed. There is also a<br />

glossary of most of these concepts on Moodle in the files section under the folder HANDOUTS.


24<br />

Again, there is a specific principle that accounts for the ungrammaticality of (4b) which native<br />

speakers must know, at least unconsciously, because they all recognize that (4b) is not a well-formed<br />

sentence. About the best that the average native speaker can say about (4b) is that it doesn’t sound<br />

right. The same is true of (2b) and, in fact, all ungrammatical sentences. In general, native speakers<br />

cannot explain why grammatical sentences are grammatical and why ungrammatical sentences are<br />

ungrammatical. Yet they do know the difference between the two.<br />

The principle that predicts the ungrammaticality of (4b) is highly specific. Changing admire to<br />

know in (3) produces the pair of sentences in (5) which mean the same thing.<br />

(5) a. The lawyers that the judges know will tell the truth.<br />

(= The ones who will tell the truth are the lawyers that the judges know.)<br />

b. The lawyers the judges know will tell the truth. (=5a)<br />

On the other hand, changing admire to know in (4) produces the pair of sentences in (6) which mean<br />

very different things.<br />

(6) a. The lawyers that know the judges will tell the truth.<br />

(= The ones who will tell the truth are the lawyers that know the judges.)<br />

b. The lawyers know the judges will tell the truth. (=/6a)<br />

Notice also that (6b) looks a lot like (4b); however, (6b) is grammatical, but (4b) is not. Further,<br />

(5a) and (6a) can be expanded as in (7), but a similar expansion of (4a) produces (8) which is not<br />

grammatical.<br />

(7) a. The lawyers that the judges know will tell the truth are from Michigan.<br />

b. The lawyers that know the judges will tell the truth are from Michigan.<br />

(8) *The lawyers that admire the judges will tell the truth are from Michigan.<br />

These examples are not gimmicky or atypical; thousands of pairs of grammatical/ungrammatical<br />

sentences like them can be found in the <strong>linguistic</strong>s literature. Such abundant examples emphasize<br />

that native speakers unconsciously know a vast and detailed array of facts about their language, and<br />

that these facts are largely hidden from introspection and analysis. It is simply incorrect to say that<br />

the facts of language – the grammar – are well known to (even educated) speakers. This means, of<br />

course, that there is a difference between having knowledge of a language and being able to talk<br />

about that knowledge. Linguists refer to the unconscious knowledge that native speakers have of<br />

their native language as their LINGUISTIC COMPETENCE.<br />

Since native speakers do not consciously know what makes a sentence grammatical or<br />

ungrammatical in their native language, it follows that native speakers do not teach language to their<br />

children. While parents do correct children on occasion, it is hardly likely that all native speakers<br />

of English have been told by their parents that sentences like (2b), (4b), and (8) are ungrammatical<br />

and should never be uttered. If speakers required specific instruction of this type, no one would


acquire a native language because there is an infinite number of grammatical and ungrammatical<br />

sentences in every human language. In addition, even when native speakers have expert, fluent<br />

knowledge of grammatical principles, they can’t share this knowledge with their children because<br />

children are unable to comprehend even the most elementary statements about grammar. Most of<br />

one’s native language is acquired before one possesses the cognitive skills to discuss the<br />

grammatical principles which underlie the ability. For example, kindergartners clearly know the<br />

difference between statements and questions before their first day of school, yet none can discuss<br />

the difference in principled terms that reveal the facts behind the difference.<br />

In view of the above, modern <strong>linguistic</strong>s is principally concerned with two broad empirical problems<br />

which have often been referred to as the GRAMMATICAL CHARACTERIZATION<br />

PROBLEM and the GRAMMATICAL REALIZATION PROBLEM. Grammatical<br />

characterization entails describing the <strong>linguistic</strong> competence of native speakers, that is, discovering<br />

and generalizing the grammatical principles that constitute their unconscious knowledge of their<br />

native language. In grammatical characterization, a linguist describes what the principles are which<br />

determine the grammaticality of examples like (1) through (8).<br />

Grammatical realization, on the other hand, entails accounting for native speakers’ LINGUISTIC<br />

PERFORMANCE, that is, their acquisition and use of their unconscious knowledge. In<br />

grammatical realization, a linguist describes how such principles become part of the <strong>linguistic</strong><br />

competence of native speakers, in short, how children achieve mastery of their native language.<br />

Linguists must address both the grammatical characterization problem and the grammatical<br />

realization problem in formulating a theory of human language. Clearly, there are huge obstacles<br />

to doing so. Fundamentally, the <strong>linguistic</strong> competence of humans is a property of the human mind,<br />

and studying the nature of the human mind is as complex a task as studying the nature of the<br />

universe. The grammatical information that native speakers have unconsciously internalized about<br />

their native language is vast, detailed, and often extraordinarily subtle.<br />

One cannot emphasize enough the difference between the unconscious knowledge that native<br />

speakers have of their native language and the knowledge they learn about their language in school.<br />

For example, in school, children learn that English contains many words called homonyms which<br />

are spelled differently but pronounced the same, such as two, to, and too, all of which are<br />

pronounced [tu]. While this is something children consciously learn in school, it is clear that they<br />

already know the difference between these words even when they don’t know how to spell them.<br />

Consider the following sentences, remembering that children do not know how to read when they<br />

first encounter such sentences in speech:<br />

(9) a. I have to clean shirts.<br />

b. I have two clean shirts.<br />

When people read the sentences in (9), they can obviously see the difference between to and two.<br />

But even without reading those sentences or having any knowledge of English spelling or<br />

homonyms, it is clear that native speakers, including children, know the difference between to and<br />

25


26<br />

two. Thus, they know that they can say (10a) instead of (9a) contracting have and to into “hafta”,<br />

but they cannot say (10b) instead of (9b).<br />

(10) a. I hafta clean shirts. (where hafta = have to)<br />

b. *I hafta clean shirts. (where hafta = have two)<br />

Similarly, in elementary school, children learn to recognize and talk about the distinction between<br />

nouns and verbs. They learn that school is a noun and eat is a verb in sentences like the following:<br />

(11) a. I am going to school. (school is a noun)<br />

b. I am going to eat. (eat is a verb)<br />

Unconsciously, they already know that school is a noun and eat is a verb before the teacher ever<br />

brings the matter up, because they will give an answer like (12b), but never one like (13b).<br />

(12) a. Question: Where are you going to?<br />

b. Answer: School.<br />

(13) a. Question: Where are you going to?<br />

b. Answer: *Eat.<br />

Further, they know that the two uses of the word to in (11a) and (11b) are not the same. As a result,<br />

they know that they cannot contract going to into “gonna” in (11a) but they can make the contraction<br />

in (11b) as follows:<br />

(14) a. *I’m gonna school.<br />

b. I’m gonna eat.<br />

We know children know the difference because they frequently utter sentences like (14b) but never<br />

utter sentences link (14a). Lastly, children also know that (15a) is ambiguous, while (15b) is not.<br />

(15) a. I am going to work. (ambiguous: work is either a noun or a verb)<br />

b. I’m gonna work. (unambiguous: work is only a verb)<br />

In addition to knowing about two and to, children also know about too. They know, for example,<br />

that (16a) means ‘They came in order to clean the room,’ whereas (16b) means ‘They did so clean<br />

the room.’ That is why the interchange in (17) is grammatical, whereas the one in (18) is not.<br />

(16) a. They came to clean the room. (=They came in order to clean the room.)<br />

b. They did too clean the room. (=They did so clean the room)<br />

(17) a. Question: Why did they come?<br />

b. Answer: To clean the room.


(18) a. Question: Why did they come?<br />

b. Answer: *Too clean the room./*So clean the room.<br />

Children also know that too has a variety of uses like to, so that (19) is ambiguous meaning either<br />

‘They are overly clean’ or ‘They are definitely/emphatically clean.’<br />

(19) They are too clean.<br />

Lastly, children know that clean in (20a) is an adjective whereas clean in (20b) is a verb.<br />

(20) a. They were clean.<br />

b. They did clean.<br />

We know they know this because they will utter only the grammatical sentences in examples like<br />

the following:<br />

(21) a. They were very clean.<br />

b. *They did very clean.<br />

c. They were cleaner.<br />

d. *They did cleaner.<br />

e. *They were clean it.<br />

f. They did clean it.<br />

g. *They were so clean better than us.<br />

h. They did so clean better than us.<br />

In short, when children acquire their native language, they acquire unconscious knowledge of the<br />

parts of speech (nouns and verbs) and of word usage (two, to, and too) long before they go to school<br />

and learn to talk consciously about what they already unconsciously know. They unconsciously<br />

know what a noun is and what a verb is; they just don’t consciously know that a noun is called a<br />

“noun” and a verb is called a “verb.” They will correctly use all three words that are pronounced<br />

[tu] long before they learn to spell them. In fact, although they know the difference between the<br />

three words (two, to, and too) and do not misuse them in speech, many children often misspell them<br />

into adulthood writing sentences like He is to tall. We can tell what children unconsciously know<br />

by listening to what they say and observing whether or not they understand what is being said to<br />

them. It is the task of <strong>linguistic</strong>s to discover the exact nature of that unconscious knowledge and to<br />

formulate a theory that explains how children acquire that knowledge. As this discussion indicates,<br />

both tasks are formidable.<br />

27


28<br />

1.2 THE STUDY OF GRAMMAR<br />

In the preceding discussion, the word GRAMMAR was used in several distinct, yet interrelated<br />

senses. This is typical because the term has a variety of applications. Fundamentally and most<br />

commonly, it is used to mean a description of a language, that is, an explicit characterization of the<br />

structure of the sentences in a particular language. A grammatical characterization of English, for<br />

instance, isolates and categorizes the basic <strong>linguistic</strong> elements found in English sentences, indicates<br />

how these elements are related to each other, and specifies the manner in which they are arranged<br />

in larger units. Terms like noun and verb are examples of labels which grammarians have given to<br />

some of these elements, and a statement like the subject of an English sentence precedes the<br />

predicate is an example of the kind of rule usually found in a grammar of English.<br />

In a second more technical sense, the word grammar is used to mean a theory of language, that is,<br />

a system of hypotheses formulated to account for the various features of human language in general.<br />

For example, one of the outstanding features of all human languages is the fact that each one<br />

consists of a potentially infinite number of sentences. In effect, every human language allows for<br />

CREATIVITY. Although there are severe constraints on individual <strong>structures</strong> when they are<br />

combined to form complex sentences, every human language is RECURSIVE. This means that<br />

there are <strong>structures</strong> that can repeat themselves indefinitely. Thus, it is impossible to make a list of<br />

all of the sentences in the English language; additions to any such list can always be made by<br />

combining the sentences one has already thought of with words like and, but, or, etc. There is no<br />

longest English sentence. For example, (22) could, theoretically, be continued without end.<br />

(22) This is the cat that caught the rat that ate the mouse that lived in the house that Jack was<br />

in when he told Harry that Bill said that Mary wanted to know if Sue would be able to tell<br />

her father that Jane hates fairy–tales because they make her think of an unfortunate<br />

experience which occurred one day when she was visiting her aunt in Idaho and...<br />

These two uses of the word grammar, i.e., grammar as characterization of a particular language<br />

(e.g., English grammar) and grammar as a theory of human language generally (UNIVERSAL<br />

GRAMMAR), are basic to all of the other more specialized or expanded uses of the word. In most<br />

schools of modern <strong>linguistic</strong>s, for example, grammar, as a description of a language, includes the<br />

study of sounds and the way sounds are related to meaning. This usage is merely an expansion of<br />

the more common one in which a grammar only describes the classification and arrangement of the<br />

forms of a language, the syntax. Moreover, it is important to realize that, although there is a<br />

distinction between grammar as description and grammar as theory, nevertheless, each of these basic<br />

uses implies the other. On the one hand, a grammatical description is always written within the<br />

framework of some grammatical theory, however loosely formulated, and, on the other hand,<br />

grammatical theories are proposed so that correct grammatical descriptions can be written.<br />

In addition to this, linguists make a distinction between DESCRIPTIVE GRAMMAR and<br />

PRESCRIPTIVE GRAMMAR. In descriptive grammar, no value judgments are attached to the<br />

characterization, that is, the grammar characterizes whatever speakers say. In prescriptive grammar,<br />

on the other hand, value judgments are attached to the characterization, so that prescriptive


grammars prescribe what one should say and why, for example, that one should say It’s I and not<br />

It’s me, if one wishes to sound educated. Throughout the following discussion, we will be<br />

concerned with only descriptive grammar; therefore, our description must provide for utterances like<br />

It’s me as well as utterances like It’s I.<br />

1.3 SPEECH AND WRITING<br />

One of the most common misconceptions about language is the belief that writing is somehow more<br />

important than speech. It is not difficult to imagine how this misconception arose: writing has<br />

always been considered a sign of intelligence and of civilization; it is generally more permanent and<br />

durable than speech; and, through it, the artistic and scientific achievements of humankind have been<br />

recorded and preserved. Although there may be some justification for this cultural superiority of<br />

writing over speech, nevertheless, it is speech and not writing which is basic both to language itself,<br />

as a means of communication, and to <strong>linguistic</strong>s. There are several reasons for this.<br />

First, writing is a relatively recent invention. Even the most ancient examples of writing that have<br />

been preserved are only about seven thousand years old. On the other hand, it seems safe to say that<br />

humans have been speaking since the evolution of human society many hundreds of thousands of<br />

years ago.<br />

Second, writing is much less widespread than speech. Many languages, even today, exist only in<br />

spoken form. Furthermore, there are many extinct languages about which very little is known,<br />

except that they were spoken in a particular area at a particular time, because these languages were<br />

not written down.<br />

Third, it is speech and not writing which human beings are predisposed to learn. The acquisition<br />

of speech in children proceeds automatically and without conscious attention or specific instruction,<br />

unlike the acquisition of writing skills. Acquiring writing ability, on the other hand, is a voluntary,<br />

deliberate choice.<br />

Fourth, and most important, writing is a reflection of speech. All alphabetic writing systems such<br />

as English are based, in one way or another, on the sound systems they represent, that is, a particular<br />

sign or letter always represents some unit of sound or sounds in the spoken language. It is never the<br />

case that the sound system of a language is based on a particular system of writing.<br />

For all of these reasons, writing has only a marginal importance in most language studies. Linguists<br />

are primarily concerned with describing speech and ascertaining how it is acquired and used.<br />

29


30<br />

1.4 LINGUISTIC ARGUMENTATION<br />

Linguistic competence is clearly related to <strong>linguistic</strong> performance. The facts of grammar are not<br />

arbitrary but, in large part, are due to facts regarding the nature of human beings including their<br />

cognitive abilities and cognitive limitations. Human beings are able to acquire human languages<br />

because they are genetically constituted to do so. It is simply inconceivable that all native speakers<br />

arrive at the same internal understanding of their language on the basis of trial and error, given that<br />

the native acquisition of any language proceeds rapidly and uniformly and without instruction. In<br />

very specific ways, human languages reflect human abilities. For example, the rules of every human<br />

language are based on LINGUISTIC STRUCTURE, that is, on <strong>linguistic</strong> units. Consider the<br />

following sentences.<br />

(23) a. Eventually the president will resign.<br />

b. The president eventually will resign.<br />

c. The president will eventually resign.<br />

d. The president will resign eventually.<br />

e. *The eventually president will resign.<br />

The possible positions that the sentence adverb eventually can occupy are not unpredictable. This<br />

is because every English sentence consists of structural units. Using traditional terminology, these<br />

units might be labeled and diagramed as follows:<br />

(24)<br />

One can see from this diagram, that the sentence adverb eventually can occur among any of the units<br />

of the node SENTENCE. There are three such units attached directly to the node SENTENCE:<br />

SUBJECT, AUXILIARY, and PREDICATE. Accordingly, there are four possible positions for<br />

the sentence adverb in (23). Further, sentence (23e) is excluded from the infinite list of grammatical<br />

sentences in English because it violates a structural principle of English, and not for some arbitrary<br />

reason. In short, children do not have to be told that (23e) is ungrammatical: its status is predictable<br />

on the basis of other structural facts about English that they unconsciously know.<br />

Of course, the important question here is how to determine the structural units in the first place, that<br />

is, how to justify a diagram like (24). Such a diagram characterizes English in two ways. First, it<br />

states that English sentences consist of three structural units; second, it states that those units should<br />

have three different labels. Each of these statements must be justified before they can be accepted<br />

as an accurate characterization of English.


At this point, let us consider only the question of the number of units, putting aside the matter of<br />

labels until the chapter on syntax. Linguists determine structural units such as the units of a sentence<br />

by attempting to manipulate the words in that sentence in one of three ways: REFERENCE,<br />

OMISSION, and PLACEMENT. Great caution is needed during such investigations because, as<br />

we have seen, the facts of language are largely hidden. It is easy to be misled. Sometimes various<br />

manipulations produce conflicting results. This merely means that the matter is more hidden than<br />

first imagined and that other supporting data, perhaps even from other languages, must be looked<br />

at. For this reason, the more arguments that can be marshaled to support a particular<br />

characterization, the more justified it is.<br />

Introductory <strong>linguistic</strong>s students make a number of incorrect assumptions when they attempt to show<br />

that a characterization is justified. First, they assume that the analysis should be obvious or, at least,<br />

readily clear after a little thought. Second, they assume that there are unique, formulaic, infallible,<br />

and unambiguous procedures available for them to apply to the problem. Third, they assume that<br />

they do not know what the correct analysis is. All of these assumptions are wrong. The facts of<br />

language are not at all clear, and there are no procedures available by which one can quickly<br />

discover the best characterization of the data. If this were correct, the job of <strong>linguistic</strong>s would have<br />

been completed long ago. In truth, grammatical characterization is only in its infancy. Also, all<br />

native speakers, because they are native speakers, know which sentences, out of an infinite list of<br />

sentences, are grammatical and which are ungrammatical. Native speaker competence demands<br />

such knowledge. Therefore, the problem is to learn how to access the unconscious knowledge one<br />

has by asking the appropriate questions. In regard to (24), consider the following data:<br />

(25) Reference: the elements of sentences can be substituted as units.<br />

a. Who will resign? (Who replaces the president in a question.)<br />

b. The president will announce that he will resign. (He replaces the president in<br />

reference.)<br />

(26) Omission: the elements of sentences are omitted as units.<br />

a. The president will resign if the first lady asks him to _______.<br />

b. The president will resign, and the first lady will _______ too.<br />

(27) Placement: other elements cannot break up units.<br />

a. Eventually the president will resign.<br />

b. The president eventually will resign.<br />

c. The president will eventually resign.<br />

d. The president will resign eventually.<br />

e. *The eventually president will resign.<br />

31


32<br />

Notice that the three manipulations in (25) through (27) have varying results: sometimes<br />

grammatical sentences are produced; other times, ungrammatical ones. In each case, NATIVE<br />

SPEAKER INTUITION can verify the decisions on grammaticality. This does not mean that<br />

native speakers always agree on issues of grammaticality, nor is total agreement crucial. What is<br />

crucial is that, for most of the manipulations, most of the results are agreed upon by most of the<br />

speakers. This makes communication between people possible. Their internalized grammars of<br />

English are substantially the same.<br />

Now observe that the best characterization of the units in (25) through (27) is, in fact, (24); that is,<br />

the three unit structure diagramed in (24) predicts (25) through (27). There is no manipulation<br />

which, for example, demands that president will be analyzed as a unit. Therefore, most linguists<br />

today argue that English sentences have three basic units whatever they choose to call them. As a<br />

foundation for argumentation, linguists use the manipulations of reference, omission, and placement.<br />

This helps to distinguish sentences which superficially seem identical, but which are, in fact, very<br />

different, like the following (A=ambiguous; U=unambiguous):<br />

(28) a. He looked up the street. (A) He looked the street up. (U)<br />

b. He looked up the address. (U) He looked the address up. (U)<br />

c. He looked up her dress. (U) *He looked her dress up.<br />

d. He cleaned up her dress. (U) He cleaned her dress up. (U)<br />

Notice that manipulation of these sentences produces different results, indicating that their structure<br />

is not the same.<br />

1.5 UNIVERSAL GRAMMAR (UG)<br />

Turning to the issue of grammatical realization, an immediate question is, Why are the rules of all<br />

human languages based on <strong>linguistic</strong> units as opposed to something else? For example, rather than<br />

permuting a sentence adverb like eventually among structural units to produce paraphrases like (23a)<br />

– (23d), why don’t human languages permute units on the basis of some other criterion like<br />

counting? As it happens, there is no rule in any human language that is based on counting per se,<br />

e.g., there is no rule like (30) based on principle (29).<br />

(29) The rules of human language are based on counting.<br />

(30) Place sentence adverbs optionally after every two words.<br />

Rule (30) might predict that eventually could occur in every position marked with a # in (31).<br />

(31) The president # said that # he would # resign as # soon as # he found # the stationery # to<br />

write # with.


The obvious reason that human languages do not contain rules based on principle (29) is that human<br />

beings cannot count and speak at the same time. Try, for example, to reread the present sentence<br />

at normal speed and count the number of words as you reread it. What is the ninth word?<br />

Sometimes languages have rules that position elements initially or finally in sentences. For<br />

example, in a direct question in English, the auxiliary unit (helping verb) comes first as in Will he<br />

do it? Languages even contain rules that position elements in a specific order after an introductory<br />

structural unit. For example, German has a rule that says the verb must be the second structural<br />

element when a sentence begins with a unit other than the subject. But such rules as these are highly<br />

constrained. It is never the case that a language contains a rule for positioning a unit after, say, six<br />

other units. The reason is rooted in human memory constraints. The rules of human language are<br />

based on structural units because human short term memory (STM) is severely constrained.<br />

It is a well known fact that humans can only remember about five to seven bits of information<br />

immediately presented to them; for example, no more than the amount in a local telephone number.<br />

In early childhood, the amount is much less than in adulthood. Gradually, during early development,<br />

as children’s cognitive capacities mature, their ability to operate within STM constraints increases.<br />

But there is an upper limit for all humans. If the information is organized into units or chunks, then<br />

more can be remembered. Read each of the following strings of words at normal speed and then try<br />

to recall them from memory.<br />

(32) a. criteria performance high establish may institutions some<br />

b. some institutions may establish high performance criteria<br />

(32b) is much easier to remember than (32a), and the reason is clearly that (32a) has no structure;<br />

it is simply a list of words. (32b), on the other hand, contains units which chunk or organize the<br />

words. We can diagram (32b) as follows:<br />

(33)<br />

As a result of many considerations like these, linguists have concluded that the difference between<br />

grammatical and ungrammatical sentences in human languages is not generally arbitrary. The<br />

ungrammaticality of sentences like (23e) (*The eventually president will resign) is due to the fact<br />

that they violate some principle such as (34).<br />

(34) The rules of human language are structure dependent.<br />

33


34<br />

Principle (34) is directly related to the nature of human short term memory (STM): if languages did<br />

not have structure dependent rules which organized words into units, sentence length would have<br />

to be very short. Therefore, it follows that the nature of language is directly related to the nature<br />

of human beings, in particular, to human mental abilities and limitations. Notice that there is no a<br />

priori reason why humans should have evolved the capacity (34) rather than (29). Computers can,<br />

in fact, deal with rules based on principles like (29) and routinely do so. If extra-terrestrial beings<br />

were to land on earth speaking languages that contained principle (29), it is clear that humans would<br />

not be able to understand them without paper and pencil analysis.<br />

Modern <strong>linguistic</strong> theory has uncovered many principles like (34) which help to define the nature<br />

of language and, therefore, the nature of human beings. In <strong>linguistic</strong>s, a principle like (34) is called<br />

a LINGUISTIC UNIVERSAL, and the entire set of such <strong>linguistic</strong> universals is called CORE<br />

GRAMMAR or UNIVERSAL GRAMMAR (UG). UG defines what can and cannot form part<br />

of a human language; therefore, it forms part of a human’s genetic endowment. That means that<br />

children do not have to learn principles like (34); they are born with tacit knowledge of the fact that<br />

the rules in the language to which they have been accidentally exposed are based on (34) and not<br />

on (29). The reason is clear: human beings must operate within their capacities and limitations.<br />

They cannot spend the afternoon underwater, for example, without some artificial device. They<br />

cannot outrun cougars. They cannot understand languages that contain rules based on counting. It<br />

does not take much experience, if any, for children to learn that they have these limitations. They<br />

are part of the biological makeup of all humans.<br />

UG contains two types of universals: FORMAL UNIVERSALS and SUBSTANTIVE<br />

UNIVERSALS. A formal universal is a stipulation on the organization of grammar and on the form<br />

and functioning of grammatical rules. (34) is an example of a formal <strong>linguistic</strong> universal. It<br />

stipulates how the rules of natural language must work, in particular, they must be based on<br />

structure.<br />

The second type of <strong>linguistic</strong> universals, substantive universals, are stipulations on the elements or<br />

features which can occur in natural language. For example, the sounds of language are distinguished<br />

by a number of features like the following:<br />

(35) a. [m] [+CONSONANT, +BILABIAL, +VOICED, +NASAL]<br />

b. [b] [+CONSONANT, +BILABIAL, +VOICED, –NASAL]<br />

c. [p] [+CONSONANT, +BILABIAL, –VOICED, –NASAL]<br />

The letter m signifies the sound [m], which is really an abbreviation for a number of phonological<br />

features. Specifically, [m] is a consonant which means that it is formed by temporarily obstructing<br />

the air as it leaves the vocal apparatus. Further, the obstruction is made by the two lips<br />

([+BILABIAL]) while the vocal cords are vibrating ([+VOICED]). Lastly, the air exits through the<br />

nose in articulating [m], that is, it is a nasal sound ([+NASAL]). Changing any of these features<br />

changes [m] to some other sound. For example, if the air exits through the mouth rather than the<br />

nose, then [b] is produced. If the air exits orally without the vocal cords vibrating, then [p] is<br />

produced. The features given in (35), therefore, define the phonological structure of some English


consonant sounds. The number and types of these features is not arbitrary. For example, all sounds<br />

are either [+NASAL] or [–NASAL]; the air exits through the nose or the mouth.<br />

Air could potentially escape the human head from the lungs via three routes: the mouth, the nose,<br />

and the ears. In fact, when the tympanic membrane (eardrum) is not intact, people can blow smoke<br />

through all these orifices. Despite this, no human language contains a phonological feature<br />

opposition [+AURAL]/[–AURAL] meaning involving the ears/not involving the ears. The reason<br />

for this is transparent: humans cannot use their ears for the production of sounds. There is no a<br />

priori reason why the ear should have evolved in the way it did; conceivably, evolution could have<br />

produced an aural canal with an unimpeded connection to the outside. This would have made it<br />

possible to expel air through the ears normally; however, that did not occur. On the other hand, a<br />

separation of the nasal and oral passages did occur in the evolution of mammals. From the point of<br />

view of UG, human languages utilized this separation globally, so that most natural languages<br />

contain a phonological feature opposition [+NASAL]/[–NASAL]. This feature opposition is<br />

possible because humans have a velum which can be lowered to close off some of the oral passage<br />

and allow nasal modification of the air stream. Thus, we have a clear example of how natural<br />

languages are constrained by human anatomy.<br />

Like formal universals, substantive universals are part of the genetic endowment. They form part<br />

of the tacit <strong>linguistic</strong> competence that all humans innately possess, quite simply because they are the<br />

direct reflection of man’s capacities and limitations. Children don’t have to learn that the sounds<br />

of their native language won’t require modification through their ears, just as they don’t have to<br />

learn that the rules of their native language are not based on counting. They are born with the<br />

intuitive knowledge that [+AURAL] and [–AURAL] are not possible phonological features of<br />

human languages, just as they are born with intuitive knowledge of principle (34). Further, since<br />

all normal children can breathe either through their nose or their mouth, children intuitively know<br />

that their native language might contain the features [+NASAL] and [–NASAL].<br />

Notice however that every language does not have to contain the same set of universals. Not every<br />

language has the same rules and the same features. For example, English does not use the feature<br />

opposition [±NASAL] to distinguish its vowels, but French does. UG simply defines the limits of<br />

what can be part of a human language because of the capacities and limitations of the human<br />

language apparatus (the brain and the organs of speech and hearing). Therefore, a native speaker’s<br />

tacit <strong>linguistic</strong> competence consists of two kinds of knowledge: (i) innate knowledge or UG, which<br />

is part of a human being’s genetic endowment and consists of the kinds of rules and features which<br />

any language might contain; and (ii) acquired knowledge, which consists of the particular rules and<br />

features that occur in the native language(s) to which the speaker has been exposed as a child.<br />

In the specification of UG, the close association between grammatical characterization and<br />

grammatical realization becomes clear. Formal and substantive universals, which appear as the rules<br />

and features in the grammars of human languages, are grounded in the <strong>linguistic</strong> capacities of<br />

humans. Therefore, the discovery of a universal in the course of grammatical characterization can<br />

often lead to a hypothesis about the way humans process information. An example of this is the<br />

postulated formal universal (36a) which, it might be argued, leads to the perceptual strategy (36b).<br />

35


36<br />

(36) a. The clause is the major structural unit in human language; that is, the maximal<br />

specification of the syntactic rules of language is the clause.<br />

b. The clause is the major perceptual unit in human language; that is, if a string of<br />

words can be interpreted as a clause, then it must be interpreted as one.<br />

(36a) claims that the major syntactic unit found in the characterization of human languages is the<br />

CLAUSE, which is a string of words that typically contains one subject and one tensed (present,<br />

past, future) verb. (36b) claims that ordinary language use centers around clause <strong>structures</strong>, so that<br />

a string of words that could possibly be a clause is probably a clause. Properly, (36a) is part of<br />

grammatical characterization, the result of attempting to characterize the structure of English and<br />

various other languages; (36b) is part of grammatical realization. We can see the operation of (36)<br />

in the following data.<br />

(37) a. The coach thought that John succeeded.<br />

b. The coach thought John succeeded.<br />

c. That John succeeded pleased the coach.<br />

d. * John succeeded pleased the coach.<br />

Notice that the word that can be left out of (37a) to produce (37b). We saw the same operation in<br />

(3). However, if that is left out of (37c), the ungrammatical (37d) results (cf. (4)).<br />

Faced with data like (37), a linguist can assume that the ungrammaticality of (37d) is either arbitrary<br />

or principled. We have argued above that languages would be unlearnable under the conditions<br />

which attend ordinary acquisition if the distinction between grammatical and ungrammatical<br />

sentences were always arbitrary. Recall that <strong>linguistic</strong> knowledge is unconscious; accordingly,<br />

children are not taught language by their parents. They must discover the grammar of their native<br />

language without the benefit of instruction. Furthermore, since children can learn ANY human<br />

language and do so effortlessly and rapidly, the facts of language acquisition demand that linguists<br />

assume that some process other than trial and error guides children. Data like (37) lead linguists to<br />

assume that (37d) is ruled out by some principle of UG, not by some arbitrary language convention.<br />

Data like (37) from many different languages suggest that the principle entails something like (36).<br />

Students new to <strong>linguistic</strong> analysis typically believe that a sentence like (37d) is ruled out because<br />

it doesn’t make any sense, that is, it doesn’t mean anything. But this is incorrect as the<br />

grammaticality of (37c) clearly shows (cf. John’s success pleased the coach). What is wrong with<br />

(37d) is not that its meaning is somehow bizarre; rather, it is syntactically ill–formed.<br />

Observe that, in (37d), John succeeded is a clause; it has both a subject (John) and a tensed verb<br />

(succeeded). Principle (36b) demands that it be interpreted as a clause. Since the string of words<br />

John succeeded already has a tensed verb, the clausal unit is fulfilled and pleased the coach, which<br />

contains another tensed verb (pleased), cannot be part of the same clause. The function of that in<br />

(37c) is, in fact, to separate the two clauses. Consider the following:


(38) a. [Something] pleased the coach.<br />

b. [That [John] succeeded] pleased the coach.<br />

c. [John] succeeded and pleased the coach.<br />

The bracketed elements in (38) are subjects. In (38a), the sentence consists of one simple clause<br />

with one subject (something) and one tensed verb (pleased). In (38b), on the other hand, the<br />

sentence consists of two clauses, where the subject of the main clause is itself another clause, John<br />

succeeded. The function of that in (38b) is to subordinate one clause to the other, to separate them.<br />

In (38c), the word and performs a similar function of separating two clauses, only in this case it<br />

coordinates the two tensed verbs (succeeded and pleased), rather than subordinating one to the other.<br />

(37d) eliminates the that, so the two clauses are no longer separated; accordingly, the sentence is<br />

ungrammatical. It contains two tensed verbs that are not separated by either a subordinator such as<br />

that (cf. (38b)) or a coordinator like and (cf. (38c)). More importantly, its ungrammaticality is not<br />

arbitrary: it is predictable from (36). Therefore, children do not have to learn not to say (37d), any<br />

more than they have to learn not to try to look through solid objects. They are born with intuitive<br />

knowledge of the principles in (36), which evidently derive from some as yet unknown fact(s) about<br />

human brain function. These principles predict that all sentences like (37d) will be ungrammatical<br />

in any human language. This includes (37d), as well as (39d) and any others which violate (36).<br />

(39) a. The player who(m) the coach picked won.<br />

b. The player the coach picked won.<br />

c. The player who won did a backflip.<br />

d. *The player won did a backflip.<br />

e. The player won and did a backflip.<br />

Despite these remarks, it is always possible that a language might allow some particular construction<br />

under highly specified conditions even when there is a general constraint against it. After all, it is<br />

a well–known fact that languages do have exceptions. In such cases, it is useful to distinguish what<br />

is expected in language on the basis of universal principles from what is unexpected.<br />

Linguists call rules and <strong>structures</strong> that are expected UNMARKED, and those that are unexpected,<br />

because they violate general principles, MARKED. The more tightly constrained a principle is by<br />

the nature of human beings, the less likely it is to have exceptions and the more highly marked such<br />

exceptions become. For example, if the equivalent of (39d) were found to be grammatical in some<br />

language, it would be highly marked. As one would expect, marked constructions take children<br />

much longer to acquire than unmarked ones.<br />

1.6 LEVELS OF ADEQUACY<br />

There are several levels of adequacy that a linguist can attain in grammatical characterization. The<br />

first level, called OBSERVATIONAL ADEQUACY, is attained when the facts are noted. The<br />

second level, called DESCRIPTIVE ADEQUACY, is attained when the facts are described with<br />

37


38<br />

generalized principles or rules. The third, highest level, called EXPLANATORY ADEQUACY,<br />

is attained when those principles are related to the nature of the language apparatus of humans. As<br />

a linguist moves from observational to explanatory adequacy, an ever higher level of generality is<br />

reached. At the highest level, linguists begin to relate individual languages like English to UG and,<br />

therefore, to offer a real explanation for <strong>linguistic</strong> phenomena. In attempting to attain explanatory<br />

adequacy, a linguist is also able to separate out what is arbitrary and language specific, from what<br />

is predictable in terms of UG. As a result, attaining explanatory adequacy in grammatical<br />

characterization helps to solve the grammatical realization problem. Our discussion of the data in<br />

(37) in the previous section was an illustration of this. As a further example, this time from<br />

phonology, consider the following data.<br />

At the level of observational adequacy, we observe that, in many languages, there are four major<br />

points of articulation for distinguishing consonant sounds. Looking again at nasal sounds, we find<br />

the following:<br />

(40) a. [m] articulated at the extreme front of the mouth<br />

b. [n] articulated against the alveolar ridge behind the upper teeth<br />

c. [ñ] articulated against the palate or roof of the mouth<br />

d. [õ] articulated at the extreme back of the mouth<br />

The four nasals occur in the following words:<br />

(41) a. [m] whim, met, simmer<br />

b. [n] win, net, sinner<br />

c. [ñ] Spanish words like mañana (‘tomorrow’)<br />

d. [õ] wing, singer<br />

At the level of descriptive adequacy, many phonological descriptions of these sounds classify the<br />

four nasals as follows:<br />

(42) a. [m] is bilabial [+BILABIAL]; produced with the two lips<br />

b. [n] is alveolar [+ALVEOLAR]; produced by raising the tip of the tongue to<br />

the alveolar ridge, i.e., the ridge behind the teeth<br />

c. [ñ] is palatal [+PALATAL]; produced by raising the front part of the tongue<br />

to a point on the hard palate just behind the alveolar ridge<br />

d. [õ] is velar [+VELAR]; produced by raising the back of the tongue toward<br />

the soft palate or velum<br />

Notice that this description requires four phonological features and a considerable amount of<br />

unnecessary redundancy. For example, in addition to saying that [n] is [+ALVEOLAR], one can<br />

say it is [–BILABIAL], [–PALATAL], and [–VELAR]. To correct this, and reach a higher level of<br />

descriptive adequacy, we can reduce the number of oppositions from four to two by reducing the<br />

number of features from four to two as follows:


(43) a. [+ANTERIOR] articulated in the front of the mouth (at or in front of the alveolar<br />

ridge)<br />

b. [–ANTERIOR] not articulated in the front of the mouth (behind the alveolar ridge)<br />

c. [+CORONAL] articulated with the blade of the tongue (the portion immediately<br />

behind the tip) raised from its neutral position<br />

d. [–CORONAL] not articulated with the blade of the tongue (the portion<br />

immediately behind the tip) raised from its neutral position<br />

With these two features, we describe nasals much more efficiently as follows, reaching a higher<br />

level of descriptive adequacy than (42), which requires four features:<br />

(44) a. [m] [+ANTERIOR, –CORONAL]<br />

b. [n] [+ANTERIOR, +CORONAL]<br />

c. [ñ] [–ANTERIOR, +CORONAL]<br />

d. [õ] [–ANTERIOR, –CORONAL]<br />

These sounds do not have equal frequency or distribution in English. The closest approximation to<br />

a palatal nasal in English occurs in a word like onion. The velar nasal, though it can occur medially<br />

and finally, cannot occur initially. The three primary positions in (44), namely, (44a), (44b), and<br />

(44d), are also the positions for the six stop consonants in English. Consider the following (recall<br />

that [+VOICED] means that the vocal cords are vibrating and [–VOICED] means they are not):<br />

(45) a. [p] [+ANTERIOR, –CORONAL, –VOICED]<br />

[b] [+ANTERIOR, –CORONAL, +VOICED]<br />

b. [t] [+ANTERIOR, +CORONAL, –VOICED]<br />

[d] [+ANTERIOR, +CORONAL, +VOICED]<br />

c. [k] [–ANTERIOR, –CORONAL, –VOICED]<br />

[g] [–ANTERIOR, –CORONAL, +VOICED]<br />

Notice the succinctness of this method of characterization. As we noted in previous sections, a letter<br />

like p is a representation for the sound [p], which itself is an abbreviation for a constellation of<br />

phonological features. Further, all those features relate to the structure of the human vocal apparatus<br />

so that they comprise natural classes of sounds. As it turns out, it is precisely those natural classes<br />

that are operative in phonological processes. For example, consider the following words:<br />

(46) a. impossible, imbalance, immeasurable<br />

b. intangible, indiscrete, innumerable<br />

c. incongruent, ingratitude<br />

Observe that the prefix meaning ‘not’ is pronounced in three ways:<br />

39


40<br />

(47) a. [im] before words beginning with sounds that are [+ANTERIOR, –CORONAL],<br />

namely, [p, b, m]<br />

b. [in] before words beginning with sounds that are [+ANTERIOR, +CORONAL],<br />

namely, [t, d, n]<br />

c. [iõ] before words beginning with sounds that are [–ANTERIOR, –CORONAL],<br />

namely, [k, g]<br />

This is, of course, not arbitrary. Sounds assimilate to each other, that is, they tend to become like<br />

each other, when they are adjacent. We can formulate the following rule for English:<br />

(48) If a prefix ends in a nasal, assimilate that nasal to the following consonant sound.<br />

(48) accounts for the occurrence of the bilabial nasal [m] before the bilabial stops [p] and [b], of the<br />

alveolar nasal [n] before the alveolar stops [t] and [d], and of the velar nasal [õ] before the velar<br />

stops [k] and [g]. Notice that this distribution corresponds to the natural classes formed by<br />

combinations of the features [±ANTERIOR] and [±CORONAL] in (44) and (45). We find<br />

verification for this distribution in the occurrences of the Latin prefix con– and the Greek prefix syn–<br />

both meaning ‘with’ or ‘together’:<br />

(49) a. [m] compatible, combustible, community<br />

b. [n] continue, condense, connect<br />

c. [õ] conclude, congruent<br />

(50) a. [m] sympathy, symbiosis, symmetry<br />

b. [n] syntax, syndrome, synnema<br />

c. [õ] synchrony, syngamy<br />

We also find other cases of assimilation in the phonology of English. For example, note the<br />

alternation of [p] and [b] in the root of inscription, scripture as opposed to scribe, scribble; the<br />

alternation of [s] and [z] to indicate the plural of taps, bets, picks as opposed to tags, beds, pigs.<br />

Similar examples are very common in the languages of the world. In view of this, we can formulate<br />

the following principle for UG, thereby reaching the level of explanatory adequacy:


(51) a. Assimilate [+NASAL] consonants to the place of articulation of a following stop,<br />

that is, to the features [ANTERIOR] and [CORONAL].<br />

b. Assimilate adjacent [–NASAL] consonants in voicing.<br />

Of course, (51) is directly related to the nature of the human vocal apparatus. It is more natural to<br />

make adjacent features similar because it is easier to articulate them when they are similar. Children<br />

engage in such simplification from the earliest stages of language acquisition when their vocal<br />

apparatus is still not completely formed. For example, they say things such as gig kig for big pig<br />

assimilating the stops to the same place of articulation because it is too difficult for them to<br />

articulate a syllable like big which begins with an anterior stop and ends with a nonanterior one; it<br />

is easier to make them both the same, so children say gig.<br />

With regard to levels of adequacy, the above characterization proceeds as follows. If it stops at<br />

simply noting the data in (46), then only observational adequacy would be attained. If it stops at the<br />

rule (48), which describes (44) in generalized terms applicable to other data (cf. (49)), then<br />

descriptive adequacy would be attained. If the characterization continues to principle (51) and<br />

relates (51) to the structure of the human vocal apparatus, then explanatory adequacy has been<br />

attained.<br />

The significance of the highest level is that one can separate what is expected to occur in natural<br />

language from what is not expected to occur. Also, at the level of explanatory adequacy, the real<br />

nature of apparent exceptions is often clarified. To see this, notice that the rule (48) is not always<br />

followed, even in English. Consider the following data involving the prefix non– meaning ‘not,’<br />

which is also of Latin origin:<br />

(52) a. [n] nonperson, nonbiodegradable, nonman<br />

b. [n] nontaxable, nondelivery, nonnative<br />

c. [n] noncombat, nongaseous<br />

Notice that non is always pronounced with a final [n]. We must say, therefore, that, if non is a<br />

prefix, it is an exception to (48). However, the matter does not stop there. The prefixes in– and<br />

con– are of Latin origin, and, in Latin, they also function as prefixes, though they are related to<br />

independent words (in and cum). Similarly, syn–, which is of Greek origin, functions as a prefix in<br />

Greek, though it is related to an independent Greek word (syn). The element non, on the other hand,<br />

never functions as a prefix in Latin; it occurs only as a separate word meaning ‘not’ and in a few<br />

compound words. Even in English, the merger of non with the following word is not as complete<br />

as the merger with in– or con– or syn–. Notice the slight pause and shift of articulatory posture after<br />

saying non in the examples of (52). Such hesitation and adjustment does not occur in the examples<br />

in (46), (49) and (50). This indicates that our characterization has missed something. Even in<br />

English, it is probably wrong to consider non a prefix, though it looks like one. If we treat words<br />

like nonman as compounds like snowman or manhole, then non is not a prefix and, accordingly, is<br />

not subject to rule (48). Thus, an apparent exception, after closer examination, is seen not to be an<br />

exception at all.<br />

41


42<br />

The significance of the above discussion is that it illuminates the nature of <strong>linguistic</strong> processes and<br />

clearly indicates that languages are not governed solely by arbitrary conventions. As a further<br />

example, consider the following.<br />

The past tense in English verbs is variously pronounced [t] as in kicked, [d] as in hugged, and [cd]<br />

as in hunted (the symbol [c] stands for the sound of “a” in sofa). The occurrence of each of these<br />

variants is predictable in terms of the phonetic environment in which the past tense occurs. If it<br />

occurs after a voiceless consonant, it is realized phonetically as [t], e.g., cooked, hoped, and laughed;<br />

if it occurs after a voiced consonant or after a vowel, it is realized phonetically as [d], e.g., begged,<br />

rubbed, and loved; and, if it occurs after [t] or [d] themselves, it is realized phonetically as [cd], e.g.,<br />

prodded, pointed, and suggested. We can state the following generalizations ([æ] = “a”in bat).<br />

(53) a. [t] after [–VOICED] (backed is pronounced [bækt])<br />

b. [d] after [+VOICED] (bagged is pronounced [bægd])<br />

c. [cd] after [+STOP, +ANTERIOR, +CORONAL], i.e, after [t, d] (batted is<br />

pronounced [bætcd])<br />

This distribution is, of course, largely an assimilatory process (and notice, incidentally, how<br />

irrelevant and unrevealing the spelling of the past tense –ed is to the <strong>linguistic</strong> analysis). The<br />

exception in distribution is apparently the last environment (53c) where [t, d] do not completely<br />

assimilate in words endings in [t, d] (pointed and prodded). However, other facts of English indicate<br />

that this distribution is, in fact, not exceptional. English has no final long sounds; there is no<br />

difference between but and butt from a phonological point of view. Furthermore, final stops in<br />

English are unreleased, that is, they are articulated without full explosion (compare the p in pit with<br />

the p’s in tiptop). Therefore, in order to keep the past tense suffix as a recognizable and<br />

pronounceable entity in a word, English must give it the status of a separate syllable in words like<br />

pointed and prodded where it would otherwise not be possible (*pointt and *prodd).<br />

It is clear from the above examples that the correct formation of the past tense in English is not<br />

arbitrary for regular verbs (that the past tense of go is went is irregular and unpredictable and<br />

therefore marked). Of course, it is completely accidental that English should choose the alveolar<br />

stop consonant series [t]/[d]/[cd] to signal past tense. However, given the choice of alveolar stops,<br />

the distribution of these three sounds is not arbitrary. As we have seen, the nature of the human<br />

vocal apparatus makes certain combinations of sounds difficult or impossible to articulate. For<br />

example, it is not possible to articulate a long unreleased final stop. If the past tense is signaled by<br />

an alveolar stop, and that suffix is added to a verb whose root already ends in an alveolar stop, then<br />

there is no choice but to affix the [cd] option. The past tense of hunt cannot be [huntt] or [huntd],<br />

both of which end in consonant clusters that are impossible for English. It must be [huntcd]. For<br />

this reason, children often say hurted and even goed or goded (rather than went), although they have<br />

never heard such forms. If these verbs were regular, the past tense would be exactly what children<br />

invent. In language acquisition children immediately overapply a rule. Later, they begin the process<br />

of making finer and finer distinctions, including learning the marked exceptions. In short, for a good<br />

many verb forms, the past tense is completely predictable given the choice of alveolar stop and the


constraints on human articulation. Children do not have to learn the past tense of every verb<br />

separately, only of the irregular verbs.<br />

This analysis offers a real explanation for the rapidity with which children acquire knowledge of the<br />

past tense in English. The explanation is given in terms of UG, which is simply a reflection of the<br />

human language apparatus. Not only does this description of past tense explain the rapidity of<br />

acquisition, it also explains why children regularly utter forms they never could have heard like<br />

hurted and goed and goded. Children do not know yet that these are irregular verbs. They have<br />

realized that English arbitrarily signals past tense by the suffixation of an alveolar stop to the verb<br />

root. Their intuitive <strong>linguistic</strong> competence dictates that the distribution of the various alveolar stops<br />

must obey the constraints on articulation. Therefore, children say hurted and goed. In fact, irregular<br />

forms take children a long time to master, precisely because they violate general principles.<br />

1.7 LANGUAGE VARIATION<br />

All humans languages are based on UG, a specification of the kinds of rules and features that can<br />

exist in human languages. As we have seen, this specification directly reflects the nature of the<br />

human language apparatus, which includes the organs of speech and hearing and the brain. The<br />

existence of UG accounts for the fact that any human being can acquire any human language as a<br />

native language with equal facility.<br />

The principles in UG are available to virtually all humans; in fact, there are only three groups of<br />

children who fail to acquire language normally. The first group includes those children who have<br />

been kept severely isolated: one cannot acquire a language if one is not exposed to a language. The<br />

second group includes the profoundly disabled intellectually, children who fail to attain a mental age<br />

above two. Lastly, psychotic children show severe limitations in native language acquisition,<br />

usually because they do not attend to language when they are exposed to it. Since all of these groups<br />

are extreme cases, absence of the ability to acquire language is very rare in the overall population.<br />

It is important to note also that language can develop quite normally even in cases of severe sensory<br />

and motor deprivation. Children who are deaf, mute, and blind can acquire language, as the<br />

accomplishments of Helen Keller attest.<br />

Given the nature of children who fail to acquire a native language and the presence of language in<br />

deaf, mute, and blind children, it is clear that the major component of UG is neurological. There is<br />

something about the nature and functioning of the human brain that makes human language possible.<br />

For this reason, general principles of grammar are very difficult to discover. It is well to keep this<br />

in mind, as we explore the mysteries and intricacies of grammar in later chapters.<br />

In the search for the grammatical principles which underlie all human languages, it is easy to be<br />

mislead. There are many superficial differences among the world’s languages, and even among<br />

dialects of the same language. Cultural and ethnic diversity among different groups of people add<br />

even more superficial complexities. Students new to <strong>linguistic</strong>s are quick to focus on these<br />

43


44<br />

superficial variations and tend to overestimate their importance. For example, because different<br />

languages sound so different, students often think that some are easier to pronounce than others.<br />

This may be true when one acquires a second language as an adult, but it is not true for native<br />

language acquisition: all other things being equal, no language is harder for a child to pronounce<br />

than another. Also, although different languages organize objects in the world differently, there is<br />

no organization that cannot be acquired by every child. The fact that nomadic tribes living in deserts<br />

have many words for different kinds of wind and sand simply tells us that wind and sand are an<br />

important feature of desert life. That is hardly surprising news.<br />

Despite the enormous variety among the world’s languages and the people who speak them, any<br />

child could potentially acquire any language as a native language. This fact is of crucial significance<br />

in modern <strong>linguistic</strong> theory. While there is currently much debate over what the principles of UG<br />

are and what grammatical model best expresses them, virtually all linguists agree that the grammars<br />

of human languages reflect innate, biologically determined characteristics of human beings.<br />

1.8 LANGUAGE AND CULTURE<br />

Culture and language are totally different objects of inquiry. Culture is conventional, subject to<br />

whim and fancy, and alterable by consensus. For example, what is considered appropriate attire on<br />

a airplane or in a concert hall today would not have been accepted twenty years ago. The number<br />

of taboo words and taboo subjects has dropped precipitously in the same period. It is possible to<br />

decide whether or not we can burn the flag, address elders by their first names, eat meat on Friday,<br />

or publicly breast-feed an infant. These aspects of culture, like all others, endure or change at the<br />

whim of the society that institutionalizes them.<br />

The structure of language, on the other hand, is not conventional, not subject to whim and fancy, and<br />

not alterable by decree. Consider, for example, the following differences between statements and<br />

direct questions:<br />

(54) Statements Direct Questions<br />

John is going. Is John going?<br />

John has gone. Has John gone?<br />

John will go. Will John go?<br />

Clearly, direct questions in English are formed by inverting the order of the subject and the auxiliary<br />

or helping verb (verbs like is, has, and will). If a sentence lacks an auxiliary, then an appropriate<br />

form of the verb do must be inserted and the tense must be taken off the main verb and put on the<br />

form of do:


(55) Statements Direct Questions Ungrammatical Direct Questions<br />

John went. Did John go? *Do John went? *Went John?<br />

John snores. Does John snore? *Do John snores? *Snores John?<br />

It takes children a relatively long time to work out the details of forming direct questions in English,<br />

and the insertion of do causes people learning English as a second language considerable difficulty.<br />

So, why not get rid of these processes? After all, in indirect questions, these processes don’t apply.<br />

Consider the following indirect questions:<br />

(56) a. Ask Mary if John is going.<br />

b. Ask Mary if John has gone.<br />

c. Ask Mary if John will go.<br />

d. Ask Mary if John went.<br />

e. Ask Mary if John snores.<br />

Why not form direct questions in the same way, i.e., simply prefix statements with a word like if as<br />

many other languages do? For example, let us decree that all the following will be grammatical<br />

direct questions from now on:<br />

(57) a. If John is going? (Replaces Is John going?)<br />

b. If John has gone? (Replaces Has John gone?)<br />

c. If John will go? (Replaces Will John go?)<br />

d. If John went? (Replaces Did John go?)<br />

e. If John snores? (Replaces Does John snore?)<br />

Think of the aggravation that people would be spared. Of course, the idea is absurd. We cannot<br />

change how we form direct questions in English by legislation, mutual consent, or even conspiracy.<br />

Language reflects culture in only the most superficial ways. For example, specific kinship<br />

terminology is influenced by culture. In ancient Rome, there were two different words for uncle,<br />

avunculus (mother’s brother) and patruus (father’s brother) because the distinction was important<br />

in Roman society. In the evolution of Latin to the modern Romance Languages, e.g., French, the<br />

distinction was lost because it was no longer relevant. Such subtleties and changes in usage are<br />

common in languages, as are the societal conventions that dictate what is proper (whether to say I<br />

need to use the bathroom or I gotta take a leak, for example). Thus, the fact that a language has two<br />

words for uncle is entirely conventional and based on societal concerns, whereas the structure of<br />

languages conforms to the capacities and limitations of human cognitive ability, which is entirely<br />

independent of social conventions. It is not an accident, for example, that the sentences of every<br />

human language can be broken up into phrases. The fact is that the human brain cannot process<br />

unstructured material very well so sentences must be organized according to structural principles<br />

that all languages share. The manipulation of phrases is also dictated by such structural principles.<br />

Notice that it is phrases that invert to form direct questions in English, not words:<br />

45


46<br />

(58) Statements Direct Questions<br />

John is going. Is John going?<br />

That man is going. Is that man going?<br />

The man laughing is going. Is the man laughing going?<br />

The man who is laughing is going? Is the man who is laughing going?<br />

The man who is laughing is going? *Is the man who laughing is going?<br />

Every native speaker of English knows that the italicized sequences in (58) are phrases. Of course,<br />

their knowledge is generally unconscious as we have seen. If asked to identify the subjects in those<br />

sentences they might even get the answer wrong. But, at an unconscious level, they know exactly<br />

what all the subjects are because they know it is possible to replace all of them with the pronoun he.<br />

Further, they know they can replace the man laughing with he, but not just the man. The<br />

ungrammaticality of *He laughing is going has nothing to do with English per se; it is<br />

ungrammatical because it violates the structural principles on which all human languages are based.<br />

The structural principles that apply when the phrases in (58) are replaced with pronouns operate in<br />

other uses of pronouns. Consider the following sentences and notice that the first them in (59b)<br />

refers to the children while the second them refers to the matches; further, the interpretation of the<br />

pronouns parallels (59c), which is grammatical, not (59d), which is ungrammatical.<br />

(59) a. The children should not play with the matches.<br />

b. Why did you give them them?<br />

c. Why did you give the children the matches?<br />

d. *Why did you give the matches the children?<br />

Perhaps more interesting, is the fact that the reduction of the word them to [cm] in rapid speech also<br />

follows general principles. Note that (60a) and (60b) are grammatical, but (60c) is not.<br />

(60) a. Why did you give cm them?<br />

b. Why did you give cm cm?<br />

c. *Why did you give them cm?<br />

Grammatical principles dictate how pronouns are interpreted even when the interpretation varies in<br />

sentences that look almost identical like the following:<br />

(61) a. John appeared to Bill to behave himself. (himself = John)<br />

b. John appealed to Bill to behave himself. (himself = Bill)<br />

The referent for himself in these sentences is corroborated in the following:<br />

(62) a. *She appeared to him to behave himself. (himself = she)<br />

b. She appealed to him to behave himself. (himself = him)


Given data like the above, it is clear that cultural matters do not underlie the principles that apply<br />

in the formation of questions, in the replacement of phrases with pronouns, in the reduction of words<br />

and phrases during rapid ordinary speech, and in grammatical processes generally. Rather, such<br />

principles are based on grammatical structure, which, in turn, is based on the nature of the human<br />

language apparatus.<br />

1.9 SUMMARY<br />

As we have seen, there is a high level of abstractness associated with the characterization of<br />

<strong>linguistic</strong> competence; principle (34) – that the rules of human language are structure dependent –<br />

is hardly a subject of discussion among five–year–olds. Trying to explain it even to an educated<br />

adult is not easy. Also, there is a large measure of creativity associated with <strong>linguistic</strong> performance;<br />

most of the sentences children experience are novel. Despite this, many psychologists and linguists<br />

believed, until quite recently, that the <strong>linguistic</strong> abilities of human beings could be attributed to a<br />

complex interaction of elementary learning mechanisms, such as imitation, conditioning,<br />

association, and the like. Biologists have also shared this belief and attempted to document the<br />

separate skills needed to explain human language by citing antecedents found elsewhere in the<br />

animal kingdom. However, it has now become quite clear that the acquisition and use of language<br />

by ordinary human beings cannot be explained as the product of simple learning mechanisms, each<br />

with a precedent elsewhere in the animal kingdom. This is substantiated by a number of<br />

observations which we summarize here.<br />

First, human beings are capable of learning any of the world’s languages. Obviously, a child is not<br />

predestined to acquire a specific language but learns the language of the community into which he<br />

has been placed by chance.<br />

Second, from the inception of speech, a child does not merely imitate his parents or respond to<br />

stimuli but produces entirely novel sound sequences, most of which he has not specifically heard.<br />

One of the outstanding characteristics of both language acquisition and use is their productivity.<br />

Children say things like I goed there, which they clearly have never heard.<br />

Third, all normal children learn their language with remarkable rapidity and uniformity; and, even<br />

non–normal children, such as those who suffer from severe sensory deprivation, acquire <strong>linguistic</strong><br />

proficiency. A human can be deaf, mute, and blind and still acquire a human language.<br />

Fourth, the data on the basis of which children learn their language is of a highly fragmentary sort;<br />

many of the sentences they hear deviate considerably from perfect well–formedness. Despite this,<br />

all children learn to distinguish those utterances which are grammatical sentences from those which<br />

are not. And all children, despite their particular home environment, arrive at essentially the same<br />

internalized grammar.<br />

Fifth, while the members of the <strong>linguistic</strong> community do correct children on occasion, the level of<br />

instruction never approaches the order of complexity and abstractness which must be assumed to<br />

account for the normal use of language.<br />

47


48<br />

Sixth, there is no one–to–one correspondence between sound and meaning in any human language,<br />

whereas all known animal communication systems have very restricted one–to–one correspondences<br />

between signals and meaning. Human languages all have sound sequences that mean more than one<br />

thing, i.e., ambiguities like (63); they also have multiple sound sequences that can mean the same<br />

thing, i.e., paraphrases like (64).<br />

(63) a. It’s too hot to eat.<br />

b. Each of the sisters said that they turned on their brothers yesterday.<br />

(64) a. The boy called up the girl.<br />

b. The boy called the girl up.<br />

On the basis of these observations and many others, it appears that language acquisition is possible<br />

in children because all human languages, despite their superficial diversity, are of a universally<br />

well–defined type and because all children have an innate mental capacity to learn this particular<br />

type of communication system. Consequently, the essential problem for <strong>linguistic</strong>s is to construct<br />

a theory of human language which is sufficiently rich to account for the diversity among the world’s<br />

languages, but which, at the same time, is constrained enough to account for the facts of ordinary<br />

language acquisition. The formal representation of such a theory entails a grammar of <strong>linguistic</strong><br />

universals or UG, the investigation of which necessarily links the study of language structure to the<br />

study of human psychology and biology, and ultimately, to the study of the nature of man. The<br />

innateness hypothesis of language acquisition claims only that children are able to learn their native<br />

language because human languages all reflect innate human abilities.<br />

A beginning student of <strong>linguistic</strong>s must realize that it is of crucial importance to study the structure<br />

of sentences with a view toward describing what can and can not be said in a language, rather than<br />

prescribing what should and should not be said, and to approach the problem of grammatical<br />

characterization with a view toward discovering the underlying principles upon which languages are<br />

based. The approach in theoretical <strong>linguistic</strong>s is consequently very different from the approach<br />

taken in most language classes in the schools, including language arts classes and English classes,<br />

even though some of the same terminology is used.<br />

Theoretical linguists do not generally do grammatical analysis to help improve a teacher’s ability<br />

to teach languages or a student’s ability to learn languages. Theoretical linguists deal with native<br />

speakers who already completely know their native language. Theoretical linguists do grammatical<br />

analysis in an effort to characterize native <strong>linguistic</strong> competence which they believe is directly<br />

related to the nature of human beings. Thus, it is crucially important to try to find out what exactly<br />

causes some sentences to be grammatical and others, ungrammatical.<br />

This approach to the study of language seeks to explain <strong>linguistic</strong> phenomena, not merely observe<br />

and describe their existence. As we saw above in the characterization of the past tense in English,<br />

it is possible to attain the level of explanatory adequacy by relating the distribution of [t]/[d]/[cd]<br />

in regular English verbs to principles of UG which are based on the structure and function of the<br />

human vocal apparatus. As a result, this characterization of the past tense attains the level of


explanatory adequacy because it relates <strong>linguistic</strong> phenomena to the nature of man. Further, it offers<br />

an explanation for why children learn the past tense so rapidly despite their lack of instruction and<br />

why they regularly produce forms they never could have heard. In actuality, the characterization<br />

predicts that children will say hurted and goed. Of course, explanation leading to prediction is<br />

precisely what all science is about.<br />

49


EXERCISES FOR CHAPTER ONE<br />

1. What must a descriptive grammar of English say about the word up in the following<br />

sentences? Can you justify your opinions?<br />

a. The price has been upped.<br />

b. They can’t handle the ups and downs of life.<br />

c. He stood up his date.<br />

d. Bob has to be the upest guy on the team.<br />

e. He lives up the street.<br />

f. Let’s up the ante.<br />

g. Sue gets up her children at six.<br />

h. It’s up for grabs.<br />

I. The surf is up.<br />

j. (1) He put up the money.<br />

(2) He put the money up.<br />

(3) He put the money up there.<br />

(4) He put the money up in that case.<br />

2. All of the following sentences are ambiguous. How can you disambiguate them?<br />

a. The thief hit the lady with the hat.<br />

b. The repair man will look up the street.<br />

c. John left the house messy.<br />

d. The prisoner of war spoke foolishly.<br />

e. John slipped on the boots in the kitchen.<br />

f. They hired Spanish teachers.


g. They are all finished.<br />

h. They do so love a good meal.<br />

I. We made them idols.<br />

j. They made idols.<br />

3. The following are grammatical English sentences. Why are they so difficult to understand?<br />

a. Spain was where district and provincial administrators were concerned a country of<br />

corrupt officials.<br />

b. The horse raced past the barn fell.<br />

c. Where Al had had had Sue had had had had had had had had the teacher’s approval.<br />

d. Americans Italians and Germans really like.<br />

e. That that is is that that is not is not that it it is.<br />

4. The following excerpts are from songs, games, magazines, and various other sources. What<br />

makes them special? Turn them into sentences that are unremarkable.<br />

a. They need to adore me so Christian Dior me; it’s vital you sell me, so Machiavell’ me.<br />

b. Freedom from incrustations of grime is contiguous to rectitude.<br />

c. Like my mother is a total space cadet, she like makes me do the dishes and clean the cat<br />

box, I am sure, that’s like gross, barf out!<br />

d. I have hear of yo and your classes on languages for foreigner people. I am very<br />

interesting about take some courses on your school. I have the necessity to learn<br />

English for development very well in my profession in Mexico City. Gratefully<br />

beforehand any information.<br />

e. Nowadays, the only sexuality about which journalese is coy tends to be homosexuality,<br />

and that is adequately covered by he has no close female friends or he is not about to<br />

settle down.<br />

51


52<br />

5. Find the words which express the main idea in each of the following sentences. If you can,<br />

do this by identifying the subject and the main verb.<br />

a. When the dancer faces the audience and with one foot describes a rond de jambe à terre<br />

en dedans so that the foot describes on the ground a semi–circle from back to front, the<br />

head should be inclined to the same side as the foot that makes the movement.<br />

b. To be born, or at any rate bred, in a hand–bag, whether it had handles or not, seems to<br />

me to display a contempt for the ordinary decencies of family life that reminds one of<br />

the worst excesses of the French Revolution.<br />

c. It was from these missions the Jesuit fathers carried the word of God to the high and<br />

undiscovered plateau to those indians still existing in their natural state and received in<br />

return martyrdom.<br />

d. When in the Course of human Events, it becomes necessary for one People to dissolve<br />

the Political Bands which have connected them with another, and to assume among the<br />

Powers of the Earth, the separate and equal Station to which the Laws of Nature and of<br />

Nature’s God entitle them, a decent Respect to the Opinions of Mankind requires that<br />

they should declare the causes which impel them to the Separation.<br />

e. In vertebrates, mechanisms for maintaining body temperature by adjusting heat<br />

production and heat loss, a feat lower animals, who are at the mercy of their<br />

environment, cannot achieve, have evolved.<br />

f. In looking forward to the moment which is intended to terminate the career of my public<br />

life, my feelings do not permit me to suspend the deep acknowledgment of that debt of<br />

gratitude which I owe to my beloved country for the many honors it has conferred upon<br />

me.<br />

g. As we are now entering upon a book in which the course of our history will oblige us<br />

to relate some matters of a more strange and surprising kind than any which have<br />

hitherto occurred, it may not be amiss in the prologomenous or introductory chapter to<br />

say something of that species of writing which is called the marvelous.<br />

6. Why do linguists make a distinction between <strong>linguistic</strong> competence and <strong>linguistic</strong><br />

performance? Why is competence the focus of <strong>linguistic</strong> description? Should it be?<br />

7. Itemize some of the differences between native language acquisition and second (foreign)<br />

language acquisition. Consider characteristics of the learner and the circumstances of<br />

learning.


8. Here are two typical definitions from traditional grammar:<br />

The SUBJECT of a sentence is the phrase which specifies the topic of the sentence.<br />

The DIRECT OBJECT of a verb specifies the person or thing directly affected by the action<br />

described in the verb.<br />

What problems arise when these definitions are applied to the subjects and direct objects in<br />

the following sentences?<br />

a. John burned the money.<br />

b. John earned the money.<br />

c. Sue suffered a blow to the head.<br />

d. This book reads well.<br />

e. Bill received a promotion.<br />

9. Here are some further definitions from traditional grammar of three parts of speech:<br />

A VERB is a word that expresses an action, occurrence, or state of being.<br />

A NOUN is the name of a person, place, or thing.<br />

An ADJECTIVE is a word that describes a noun.<br />

Using these definitions, find the verbs, nouns and adjectives in the following sentences:<br />

a. They won on their final at–bat.<br />

b. Do–it–yourself–ers get things done.<br />

c. He Fred Astaired her around the ballroom.<br />

d. The River is not your average save–the–farm film.<br />

e. All carry–on luggage must be stowed.<br />

f. These French fries are so ketchuped–up, they’re soggy.<br />

53


54<br />

Can you think of other ways of defining the parts of speech? Try to find criteria like the<br />

following:<br />

A VERB is a word that can carry time distinctions (play, played).<br />

A NOUN is a word that can carry number distinctions (book, books).<br />

An ADJECTIVE is a word that can be compared (tough, tougher, toughest).<br />

10. Each of the following pairs of unpunctuated sentences consists of a statement and a yes/no<br />

question, which is a question to which one can get a yes or no answer. As a native speaker of<br />

English you know which member of each pair is the yes/no question. How do you recognize<br />

a yes/no question? Formulate a rule for forming a yes/no question.<br />

a. (1) will that man go<br />

(2) that man will go<br />

b. (1) the little girl has gone<br />

(2) has the little girl gone<br />

c. (1) the boy with the red hair isn’t going<br />

(2) isn’t the boy with the red hair going<br />

d. (1) all of them went<br />

(2) did all of them go<br />

e. (1) could there be more than one right answer<br />

(2) there could be more than one right answer<br />

Having formulated a rule for forming yes/no questions in English, consider how you might<br />

teach a four–year–old child that rule.


CHAPTER TWO: PHONETICS AND PHONOLOGY<br />

PHONETICS and PHONOLOGY are the two branches of grammar which are concerned with the<br />

study of the sounds of human language. The distinction between the two fields is as follows:<br />

phonetics deals primarily with the speech sound itself, including the way in which it is produced,<br />

transmitted, and perceived; phonology deals more with the organization of speech sounds into sound<br />

systems. The difference is similar to the difference between studying the materials out of which<br />

buildings are constructed (e.g., bricks, concrete, steel, etc.) and studying the way in which a building<br />

is constructed out of these materials (e.g., by alternating a layer of brick with a layer of concrete, by<br />

encasing the steel in concrete, etc.). PHONETICIANS study the raw materials, the sounds;<br />

PHONOLOGISTS study the systems formed from these sounds.<br />

2.1 PHONETICS<br />

PHONETICIANS describe and classify the sounds of human language in the following three ways:<br />

(i) in terms of the way in which they are produced by the vocal apparatus; (ii) in terms of the<br />

physical properties of the sound wave emanating from the speaker; and (iii) in terms of the effect<br />

the sound wave has on the various parts of the ear. These three methods of description and<br />

classification are known respectively as ARTICULATORY phonetics, ACOUSTIC phonetics, and<br />

AUDITORY phonetics. By far, the most common of the three is articulatory phonetics; hence, in<br />

the discussions which follow, the terminology of articulatory phonetics will be employed.<br />

The diagram in Figure One represents a cross–section of the human head, showing the parts of the<br />

vocal apparatus. In the production of speech sounds, the most important of these parts are the vocal<br />

cords. These are two elastic membranes located in the larynx or Adam’s Apple.<br />

In normal breathing, air is forced from the lungs, up the trachea, through the vocal cords, and out<br />

of the mouth or the nose or both. If the air is not obstructed in any way by the parts of the vocal<br />

apparatus, then no sound will be produced. Conversely, when one or more of the parts of the vocal<br />

apparatus form an obstacle in the path of the air, then a sound results.<br />

2.1.1 VOWELS<br />

There are two basic types of sound segments in human speech: VOWELS and CONSONANTS.<br />

Vowels are typically produced when the air is modified by the vibration of the vocal cords and when<br />

the tongue is held in specific positions in the mouth. The vibration of the vocal cords is known as<br />

VOICING. Sounds articulated with the vocal cords vibrating are [+VOICED]; those without, are<br />

[–VOICED]. Voicing is a feature of all English vowels, whereas the position of the tongue is what<br />

distinguishes one vowel from another. For example, the sound of a in father is produced when the<br />

tongue is in a low position in the back of the mouth, and the sound of i in machine is produced when<br />

the tongue is in high position in the front of the mouth. In the production of both vowels, the vocal<br />

cords are vibrating.


56<br />

FIGURE ONE: THE VOCAL APPARATUS<br />

A traditional chart of some vowel sounds specified by the relative positions of the tongue in the<br />

mouth is given in Figure Two, which is the kind of representation one is likely to find in various online<br />

sources. The symbols in brackets are those used by many phoneticians all over the world. Each<br />

PHONETIC SYMBOL is independent of specific languages and spelling conventions. Thus, the<br />

symbol [i] represents the sound of i in the English word machine, of eo in the English word people,<br />

of ie in the German word sieben, of ie in the French word vie, of i in the Spanish word hijo, etc.<br />

The vowels in Figure Two are distinguished by three horizontal tongue positions from the front of<br />

the mouth to the back (FRONT, CENTRAL, and BACK) and three vertical tongue heights (HIGH,<br />

MID, and LOW). In addition, vowels produced with considerable muscular effort (TENSE) are


distinguished from those that don’t involve such effort (LAX). If these differences are considered<br />

features, then Figure Two amounts to a claim that eight difference feature contrasts are necessary<br />

to distinguish the twelve English vowels: [±FRONT], [±CENTRAL], [±BACK], [±HIGH], [±MID],<br />

[±LOW], [±TENSE], and [±LAX]. That claim must be examined to see if it is justified.<br />

FIGURE TWO: ENGLISH VOWELS<br />

FRONT CENTRAL BACK<br />

[i] as in beat [u] as in boot TENSE<br />

[w] as in bit [] as in put LAX<br />

[e] as in bait [o] as in boat TENSE<br />

[e] as in bet [c] as in butted []] as in bought LAX<br />

[a] as in pot TENSE<br />

[æ] as in bat [] as in but LAX<br />

HIGH<br />

MID<br />

LOW<br />

In the Introduction above, we talked about the importance of providing solutions to problems that<br />

are the most cost-effective. Also, in Chapter One, we discussed the importance of attaining<br />

descriptive adequacy, that is, in describing language with the most generalized principles possible<br />

to cover all the data. These two matters, cost-effectiveness and descriptive adequacy, are directly<br />

related. Employers are looking for employees who can provide them with solutions to problems that<br />

satisfy the most factors or constituents in the most effective way (see Page 5). Linguists are looking<br />

for descriptions of language that account for all the data in the most generalized way. Given Figure<br />

Two, the question is this: is it necessary to have eight contrasting features to describe the twelve<br />

English vowels. Is that the most cost-effective description? The answer is, No.<br />

The features [±HIGH], [±FRONT], etc. in Figure Two contain a number of redundancies, that is,<br />

unnecessary duplications. For example, there seems to be no difference between [–BACK] and<br />

[+FRONT], [+BACK] and [–FRONT], [+TENSE] and [–LAX], [–TENSE] and [+LAX], and so on.<br />

Furthermore, it seems excessive to have three horizontal positions, three vertical positions, as well<br />

as the features TENSE and LAX, to describe the twelve English vowels (note the six empty cells<br />

in Figure Two). In an attempt to reach the highest possible level of descriptive adequacy, linguists<br />

seek to remove such unnecessary redundancies and excesses from their descriptions. Therefore, it<br />

is more common today to replace the classification in Figure Two with the one in Figure Three.<br />

Using the terminology from the Introduction (see page 14), Figure Three is more cost-effective than<br />

Figure Two because it uses a fewer number of features to distinguish all the vowel sounds. In Figure<br />

Three, we have eliminated the feature contrasts [±FRONT], [±CENTRAL], and [±MID], reducing<br />

the number of features to describe tongue position from six to three. In addition, we have added the<br />

57


58<br />

feature [±ROUND] to distinguish rounded vowels from unrounded vowels, specifically, the vowel<br />

[]] from the vowel [c].<br />

FIGURE THREE: DISTINCTIVE FEATURES FOR ENGLISH VOWELS<br />

i w e e æ u o ] a c<br />

HIGH + + – – – + + – – – – –<br />

LOW – – – – + – – – – + + –<br />

BACK – – – – – + + + + + + +<br />

ROUND – – – – – + + + + – – –<br />

TENSE + – + – – + – + – + – –<br />

There is more involved in choosing the feature inventory in Figure Three over Figure Two than just<br />

simplicity. The number of features is, of course, important. But more important is whether or not<br />

the feature inventory will be sufficient to describe all the data. In <strong>linguistic</strong>s, that means all the<br />

vowels in all the languages of the world. It is, therefore, an empirical issue. We must take the above<br />

feature inventory and test it against other data in other languages to see if it is satisfactory. Notice<br />

that is exactly what has to be done in the workplace. For example, if a manufacturer decides to<br />

make a change in the number of options available for a product (size, shape, color, weight, etc.), the<br />

effects of that change must be studied against all the relevant issues that could be impacted by the<br />

change (customer satisfaction, cost, distribution, marketing, etc.). Such extensive study minimizes<br />

unforseen consequences which can be very costly to a business. Theoretical changes work in the<br />

same way, whether one is dealing with <strong>linguistic</strong>s, psychology, physics, or any other discipline. For<br />

just this reason, <strong>linguistic</strong> theory, like all other theories in all other disciplines, is a constantly<br />

evolving theory in which changes are proposed and subsequently modified, extended, abandoned,<br />

and so on. It is important for students to see that the choice of the features in Figure Three above<br />

those in Figure Two is an entirely empirical issue that must be tested and justified; therefore, we will<br />

return to this matter at several points below.<br />

The technical definitions for the distinctive features of English vowels are as follows:<br />

• HIGH – NONHIGH — High sounds are produced by raising the body of the tongue above<br />

the level that it occupies in neutral position; nonhigh sounds are not produced with such a<br />

raising of the body of the tongue.<br />

• LOW – NONLOW — Low sounds are produced by lowering the body of the tongue below<br />

the level that it occupies in neutral position; nonlow sounds are produced without such a<br />

lowering of the body of the tongue.


• BACK – NONBACK — Back sounds are produced by retracting the body of the tongue from<br />

the neutral position; nonback sounds are produced without such a retraction.<br />

• ROUND – NONROUND — Rounded sounds are produced with a narrowing of the lips;<br />

nonrounded sounds are produced without such narrowing.<br />

• TENSE – NONTENSE (LAX) — Tense sounds are produced with a deliberate, accurate, and<br />

maximally distinct articulatory gesture that involves considerable muscular effort; lax sounds<br />

are produced rapidly and somewhat indistinctly.<br />

In addition to the unitary sounds charted above in Figure Three, English contains a number of<br />

DIPHTHONGS, which are vowels followed by a GLIDE ([w] or [y]). The true diphthongs are []y]<br />

as in soy and soil; [ay] as in sigh, nice, guy, lie, lye, sign, aisle, and choir; and [aw] as in cow, house<br />

and doubt. In most dialects, the [–LOW, +TENSE] vowels of English are also articulated with a<br />

glide, particularly in word final position: [siy] see, [sey] say, [suw] sue, [sow] sew.<br />

The glide portion of these examples is not equivalent phonetically to a [w] or [y] as these sounds<br />

would appear in words like wet ([wet]) and yet ([yet]). Therefore, other texts may represent the<br />

above examples as follows: []w] as in soy, [aw] as in sigh, [a] as in cow, [iw] as in see, [ew] as in<br />

say, [u] as in sue, and [o]as in sew. For simplicity, in this book, all glides are represented as [w]<br />

and [y], e.g., [wet] wet, [kaw] cow, [suw] sue, [sow] sew; [yet] yet, [s]y] soy, [siy] see, [sey] say.<br />

2.1.2 CONSONANTS<br />

Consonants are produced in a variety of different ways. They are classified in terms of the place in<br />

the oral cavity (Figure One) where they are articulated and also the manner of their articulation. A<br />

chart of some consonants specified according to this method of classification, as well as the features<br />

[±CORONAL] and [±ANTERIOR] discussed in Chapter One, is given in Figure Four.<br />

2.1.2.1 STOPS<br />

Some involve the complete stoppage of the air flow at some point in the vocal tract. Such<br />

consonants are known appropriately as STOPS. These include [p h ] (the sound of p in pan), [t h ] (the<br />

sound of t in tan), and [k h ] (the sound of c in can and k in keen).<br />

The point in the vocal tract at which the stoppage of air occurs is used to distinguish one stop<br />

consonant from another. [p h ], which is produced by stopping the air with both lips, is called a<br />

BILABIAL stop; [t h ], which is produced by placing the tongue against the alveolar ridge (see Figure<br />

One), is called an ALVEOLAR stop; and [k h ], which is formed with the tongue against the velum,<br />

is called a VELAR stop.<br />

59


60<br />

MANNER OF<br />

ARTICULATION<br />

STOP<br />

[–VOICED]<br />

[–VOICED]<br />

[+VOICED]<br />

FRICATIVE<br />

[–VOICED]<br />

[+VOICED]<br />

AFFRICATE<br />

[–VOICED]<br />

[+VOICED]<br />

NASAL<br />

FIGURE FOUR: ENGLISH CONSONANTS, LIQUIDS, AND GLIDES<br />

PLACE OF ARTICULATION<br />

ANTERIOR NONANTERIOR<br />

NONCORONAL CORONAL NONCORONAL<br />

BILABIAL<br />

p h (pun)<br />

p (spun)<br />

b (bun)<br />

LABIO–<br />

DENTAL<br />

f (fie)<br />

v (vie)<br />

INTER–<br />

DENTAL<br />

› (thigh)<br />

ð (thy)<br />

ALVEOLAR<br />

t h (ton)<br />

t (stun)<br />

d (done)<br />

s (sue)<br />

z (zoo)<br />

(ALVEO)<br />

PALATAL<br />

š (shoe)<br />

ž (beige)<br />

č (chew)<br />

:9 (Jew)<br />

VELAR GLOTTAL<br />

k h (come)<br />

k (scum)<br />

g (gum)<br />

[+VOICED] m (sum) n (sun) õ (sung)<br />

LIQUID<br />

[+VOICED]<br />

[+VOICED]<br />

GLIDE<br />

[–VOICED]<br />

[+VOICED]<br />

l (lay)<br />

D (cater)<br />

(whey)<br />

w (way) y (yea)<br />

r (ray) ł (ail)<br />

§ (cotton)<br />

h (hay)


The superscript “h” in the transcription of stops indicates a puff of air called ASPIRATION that<br />

is emitted when the stops are released; this puff of air is missing when these stops follow [s]. The<br />

distinction is apparent by placing a tissues in front of the mouth and noticing first that the tissue<br />

moves when saying pan [p h æn], tan [t h æn], and can [k h æn] and second that the tissue does not move<br />

when saying span [spæn], Stan [stæn], and scan [scæn]. Compare similar pairs like pit/spit, pin/spin,<br />

tall/stall, cool/school, etc.<br />

In the production of [p h ], [p], [t h ], [t], [k h ], and [k], the vocal cords do not vibrate; hence, these<br />

sounds are called VOICELESS ([–VOICED]) stops. Other stops, for example, [b] as in bet, [d] as<br />

in debt, and [g] as in get, are formed by a complete stoppage of the air flow with an accompanying<br />

vibration of the vocal cords. These stops are called VOICED ([+VOICED]). The symbol [§]<br />

represents a glottal stop that appears in a few words like button [b§cn] and cotton [ka§cn] or, in<br />

some dialects, a word like bottle [ba§cl].<br />

2.1.2.2 FRICATIVES<br />

A second group of consonants, called FRICATIVES, is formed by a closure in the vocal tract,<br />

which, though not complete as in the articulation of stops, is sufficiently constricted to cause<br />

turbulence in the air flow, thereby producing a hissing sound. This group includes the following<br />

sounds: [f] (wafer), [v] (waiver), [›] (ether), [ð] (either), [s] (racer), [z] (razor), [š] (mesher), an<br />

[ž] (measure).<br />

Like stops, fricatives are classified according to the point in the vocal tract at which the obstruction<br />

in the air flow occurs: [f] and [v] are produced by a constriction formed with the lower lip and upper<br />

teeth; they are called LABIODENTAL fricatives; [›] and [ð], produced by a constriction behind<br />

the upper teeth, are INTERDENTAL; [s] and [z], produced by a constriction against the alveolar<br />

ridge, are ALVEOLAR; [š] and [ž], produced by a constriction against the palate, are PALATAL.<br />

The sound [ž] occurs initially only in the word genre which was borrowed from French. Though<br />

relatively uncommon in English, [ž] does appear medially (vision, measure, usual, Asian, etc.) and<br />

finally (beige, massage, camouflage, etc.).<br />

2.1.2.3 AFFRICATES<br />

Closely allied to the articulation of stops and fricatives is a group of consonants called<br />

AFFRICATES. These consonants combine a complete closure at some point in the vocal tract, as<br />

in the articulation of stops, with a turbulent release that produces a hissing sound, as in the<br />

articulation of fricatives. Examples of these consonants are [č], the underlined sounds in chunk,<br />

lecher, and search, and [:9], the underlined sounds in junk, ledger, and surge. These are the only<br />

affricates in English, but there are several more in the other languages of the world.<br />

61


62<br />

2.1.2.4 NASALS<br />

A fourth group of consonants, called NASALS, are produced by a closure in the mouth and a<br />

simultaneous lowering of the velum so that the air escapes through the nasal passage (see Figure<br />

One). English has three nasal consonants. They are distinguished from each other by the point in<br />

the mouth where the closure is made. [m], the sound of m in Kim, is a bilabial nasal; [n], the sound<br />

of n in kin, is an alveolar nasal; and [õ], the sound of ng in king is a velar nasal. Each of the English<br />

nasals is a voiced consonant. The velar nasal [õ] never occurs initially in a word or syllable.<br />

2.1.3 LIQUIDS AND GLIDES<br />

In addition to consonants and vowels, languages contain two other classes of sounds, LIQUIDS and<br />

GLIDES.<br />

2.1.3.1 LIQUIDS<br />

LIQUIDS include [l], the sound of l in low, and [r], the sound of r in row. [l] is produced with a<br />

closure made by the center of the tongue at the alveolar ridge, in such a way that the air is allowed<br />

to pass out of the mouth along the sides of the tongue. Since the air passes along the sides of the<br />

tongue, l–sounds are often referred to as LATERAL consonants. In contrast to the articulation of<br />

[l], [r] usually involves a closure, or near–closure, made with the sides of the tongue, so that the air<br />

escapes from the mouth over the central portion of the tongue. A liquid sound can also be produced<br />

by making the tongue FLAP against the alveolar ridge. This sound, represented as [D] or [], is<br />

heard instead of [t h ] or [d] in words like water and ladder.<br />

2.1.3.2 GLIDES<br />

The last group of sounds includes [y], the sound of y in yell, and [w], the sound of w in well. These<br />

consonants are either called GLIDES or, because of their similarity to the vowels [i] and [u],<br />

SEMIVOWELS. Typically, they are produced like vowels since they do not involve a complete<br />

stoppage of the air flow, but they are distributed like consonants since they occur before and after<br />

vowels, as in the word wow.<br />

The four groups of sounds (vowels, consonants, liquids and glides) are distinguished by the<br />

following distinctive features:<br />

FIGURE FIVE: THE MAJOR PHONOLOGICAL CATEGORIES<br />

FEATURES CONSONANTS VOWELS GLIDES LIQUIDS<br />

CONSONANTAL + – – +<br />

VOCALIC – + – +


The definitions for the remaining distinctive features are as follows:<br />

• SONORANT – NONSONORANT (OBSTRUENT) — Sonorants are sounds produced with<br />

a vocal tract cavity configuration in which spontaneous voicing is possible; obstruents are<br />

produced with a cavity configuration that makes spontaneous voicing impossible. [Note:<br />

sonorants are usually hummable.]<br />

• CONSONANTAL – NONCONSONANTAL — Consonantal sounds are produced with a<br />

sustained vocal tract constriction at least equal to that required to produce fricatives;<br />

nonconsonantal sounds are produced without such a constriction.<br />

• VOCALIC – NONVOCALIC — Vocalic sounds are produced with an oral cavity in which<br />

the most radical constriction does not exceed that found in the high vowels [i] and [u], and<br />

with the vocal cords positioned so as to allow spontaneous voicing; in producing nonvocalic<br />

sounds one or both of these conditions are not satisfied.<br />

• CONTINUANT – NONCONTINUANT (STOP) — In the production of continuant sounds,<br />

the primary constriction in the vocal tract is not narrowed to the point where the air flow past<br />

the constriction is blocked; in stops the air flow through the mouth is effectively blocked.<br />

• NASAL – NONNASAL — Nasal sounds are produced with a lowered velum which allows<br />

the air to escape through the nose; nonnasal sounds are produced with a raised velum so that<br />

the air from the lungs can escape only through the mouth.<br />

• SIBILANT – NONSIBILANT — Sibilant sounds are produced by forcing the air through<br />

a narrow opening produced by a groove in the midline of the tongue. Typically, sibilant<br />

sounds have a hissing quality; non–sibilant sounds do not have this quality.<br />

• CORONAL – NONCORONAL — Coronal sounds are produced with the blade of the<br />

tongue (the portion immediately behind the tip) raised from its neutral position; noncoronal<br />

sounds are produced with some other articulator than the blade of the tongue.<br />

• ANTERIOR – NONANTERIOR — Anterior sounds are produced with an obstruction that<br />

is located in front of the palato–alveolar region of the mouth; nonanterior sounds are produced<br />

without such an obstruction.<br />

• VOICED – NONVOICED (VOICELESS)— Voiced sounds are produced with the vocal<br />

cords vibrating; voiceless sounds are produced without such vibration.<br />

Figure Six categorizes English consonants using these nine distinctive features; it also includes the<br />

four relevant features discussed above with vowels. Again, in terms of cost-effectiveness, Figure<br />

Six is preferred to Figure Four because it removes redundancies and contradictions and, at the same<br />

time, appears to be adequate to describe the data investigated so far.<br />

63


FEATURES<br />

FIGURE SIX: DISTINCTIVE FEATURES FOR ENGLISH CONSONANTS, LIQUIDS & G<br />

STOPS NASALS FRICATIVES AFF* L<br />

p b t d k g § m n õ f v › ð s z š ž č :9 l<br />

SONORANT – – – – – – – + + + – – – – – – – – – – +<br />

CONSONANTAL + + + + + + + + + + + + + + + + + + + + +<br />

VOCALIC – – – – – – – – – – – – – – – – – – – – +<br />

CONTINUANT – – – – – – – – – – + + + + + + + + – – +<br />

NASAL – – – – – – – + + + – – – – – – – – – – –<br />

SIBILANT – – – – – – – – – – – – – – + + + + + + –<br />

ANTERIOR + + + + – – – + + – + + + + + + – – – – +<br />

CORONAL – – + + – – – – + – – – + + + + + + + + +<br />

VOICED – + – + – + – + + + – + – + – + – + – + +<br />

HIGH – – – – + + – – – + – – – – – – + + + + –<br />

LOW – – – – – – + – – – – – – – – – – – – – –<br />

BACK – – – – + + + – – + – – – – – – – – – – –<br />

ROUND – – – – – – – – – – – – – – – – – – – – –<br />

*AFFRICATES


2.1.4 REVIEW OF ISSUES<br />

At this point, it is important to examine the choices we have made in the feature inventories above.<br />

For vowels, we noted that Figure Two involved eight feature oppositions: [±FRONT],<br />

[±CENTRAL], [±BACK], [±HIGH], [±MID], [±LOW], [±TENSE], and [±LAX]. Figure Three<br />

involved five: [±HIGH], [±LOW], [±BACK], [±TENSE], and [±ROUND]. We determined that the<br />

reduced number of features in Figure Three was preferable. The argument was largely about<br />

simplicity, but other factors are also relevant. For example, the feature opposition [±ROUND] must<br />

be part of the inventory to account for phenomena that exist in the world’s languages. There is no<br />

way to know this ahead of time; one must test the hypothesis by examining new data. In Turkish,<br />

for example, an unrounded vowel in a word cannot be followed by a rounded vowel. The<br />

phenomenon, called VOWEL HARMONY, requires that only certain combinations of vowels in<br />

a word are possible. Clearly, we cannot account for the data in Turkish without the feature<br />

[±ROUND]. Thus, quite apart from issues of simplicity, the empirical evidence demands that our<br />

feature inventory includes the opposition [±ROUND]. Even in English the feature is important:<br />

only vowels that are [+BACK, –LOW] are [+ROUND] ([u, , o, ]]).<br />

The chart of consonants in Figure Four specifies two sets of features to indicate place of articulation.<br />

One set includes only the two oppositions [±ANTERIOR] and [±CORONAL]. The other includes<br />

seven oppositions: [±BILABIAL], [±LABIODENTAL], [±INTERDENTAL], [±ALVEOLAR],<br />

[±PALATAL], [±VELAR], and [±GLOTTAL]. On the basis of simplicity alone, we would naturally<br />

choose the set with two as opposed to the one with seven. But again, this is an empirical issue. In<br />

our discussion of levels of adequacy in Chapter One (page 38 ff.), we saw that the data favor the first<br />

set with just [±ANTERIOR] and [±CORONAL]. We observed that the prefix meaning ‘not’ is<br />

pronounced in three ways in English ([wm] as in impossible, [wn] as in intangible, and [wõ] as in<br />

incurable):<br />

(1) a. [wm] before sounds that are [+ANTERIOR, –CORONAL], namely, [p, b, m]<br />

b. [wn] before sounds that are [+ANTERIOR, +CORONAL], namely, [t, d, n]<br />

c. [wõ] before sounds that are [–ANTERIOR, –CORONAL], namely, [k, g]<br />

We also saw that the distribution is not arbitrary. Sounds assimilate to each other, that is, they tend<br />

to become like each other, when they are adjacent. The rules in (1) account for the occurrence of<br />

the bilabial nasal [m] before bilabial sounds, of the alveolar nasal [n] before alveolar sounds, and<br />

of the velar nasal [õ] before velar sounds. The distribution is succinctly accounted for with the<br />

features [±ANTERIOR] and [±CORONAL]. In Latin, the roots of nouns undergo different rules<br />

depending on whether they end in a consonant that is [+CORONAL] ([t] and [d]) or [–CORONAL]<br />

([p], [b], [k], and [g]). In many places below, we will find additional empirical support for the two<br />

feature oppositions [±ANTERIOR] and [±CORONAL].<br />

The chart of consonants in Figure Four involves a set of six feature oppositions for manner of<br />

articulation: [±STOP], [±FRICATIVE], [±AFFRICATE], [±NASAL], [±LIQUID], and [±GLIDE].<br />

The chart of consonants in Figure Six also involves a set of six feature oppositions for manner of<br />

articulation, but they are different oppositions: [±SONORANT], [±CONSONANTAL],<br />

65


66<br />

[±VOCALIC], [±CONTINUANT], [±NASAL], and [±SIBILANT]. In this case, sheer number is<br />

not the issue. So, we need to see which set is more empirically justified. The data indicate that the<br />

second set is. First, notice that the second set includes the oppositions [±CONSONANTAL] and<br />

[±VOCALIC], which allowed us to generalize the differences between the four major types of<br />

sounds in natural languages, namely, vowels, consonants, liquids and glides (see Figure Five).<br />

Second, the inventory in Figure Six also includes the opposition [±SIBILANT]. This opposition<br />

operates in a number of phonological processes in English. For example, the plural of nouns is<br />

indicated by the suffix [cz] only in words that end with a sound that is [+SIBILANT], i. e., [s, z, š,<br />

ž, č, :9] as in bases, mazes, sashes, garages, arches, judges, etc. The data indicate that [±SIBILANT]<br />

must be included in the inventory. Thus, in terms of both simplicity and descriptive adequacy, we<br />

have elected to use the feature oppositions in Figure Three for vowels and Figure Six for consonants,<br />

liquids, and glides. We have eliminated redundancies and excesses and included additional feature<br />

oppositions that are empirically necessary like [±ROUND] and [±SIBILANT]. At the same time,<br />

the features we have chosen seem to be the minimum set required to account for all the data.<br />

As we have seen, the kinds of considerations made in <strong>linguistic</strong>s must also be made in many other<br />

areas. Let us consider an example from the retail business. It is generally thought that a store must<br />

provide customers with several different varieties of a product in several different sizes and shapes<br />

in order to satisfy the needs of as may different customers as possible. Thus, in the average<br />

supermarket, one finds, for example, many different brands of mayonnaise in containers of many<br />

different sizes and shapes. Jim Senegal, the founder of Costco, had a very different marketing<br />

strategy. He reasoned that cutting down on the number of choices would help customers make their<br />

selection more easily, and, in the end, they would purchase the items Costco sells. The result is that<br />

Costco only offers about 4,000 different items compared to the 16,000-150,000 items stocked by<br />

many competitors. Walmart offers over 100,000 different items. Senegal’s strategy has worked.<br />

“In the last 27 years Costco has become the fourth largest retailer in the United States and the eight<br />

largest in the world.” (Costco Case Study, 2011; http://themarketplaceoflife.blogspot.com/2011/01/)<br />

Senegal’s strategy was risky since is went against the conventional wisdom in retail about the<br />

number of choices customers want. Note that there are redundancies and excesses when a<br />

supermarket stocks many different brands of mayonnaise in containers of many different sizes and<br />

shapes. The questions are: If the supermarket gets rid of the redundancies (different brands with<br />

exactly the same ingredients) and the excesses (multiple shapes, sizes, and quantities), will the<br />

resulting selection satisfy as many customers? Will customers shop elsewhere? Or will customers<br />

simply make a choice from the selections they are given? Several studies have shown that<br />

customers report greater satisfaction when their original options are limited. The Costco business<br />

model is a case in point. It includes turnover on a very limited number of selections for each type<br />

of product, e.g., only one size and brand of mayonnaise. That strategy combined with the addition<br />

of other innovations – volume purchasing, efficient distribution practices, and reduced handling of<br />

merchandise – have helped to make Costco so successful. It is not an accident that Costco carries<br />

only a very limited number of items.


For many students, the study of language in a <strong>linguistic</strong>s course appears to involve exotic issues that<br />

have no relationship to events in the real world. As we have seen, this is not the case. The questions<br />

we have considered in this Chapter involve redundancy, consistency, adequacy, generality,<br />

efficiency, and cost, which are exactly the same questions that arise in real world problems such as<br />

the selection of brands and packaging of mayonnaise. When students can see this larger picture,<br />

they can also see that only the data are different. In the Introduction, we noted that it is exactly the<br />

larger picture – the ability to make connections at an abstract level between seemingly unrelated<br />

matters – that is crucial to adaptability, to flexibility, to mobility, and to success.<br />

2.1.5 SUPRASEGMENTALS<br />

There are, of course, many more sounds in the world’s languages than the ones that have been<br />

described above. In addition, human speech is characterized by several SUPRASEGMENTAL<br />

features, that is, vocal modification executed along with the pronunciation of vowels and<br />

consonants. Two of these suprasegmental features are PITCH, i.e., the relative tone at which<br />

individual sound segments or groups of segments are produced, and STRESS, i.e., the relative<br />

emphasis (or accent) given to individual sound segments or groups of segments. Features like pitch<br />

and stress are as important in speech as vowels and consonants. Often, they serve to distinguish<br />

words from each other. For example, permit must be pronounced with heavy stress on the first<br />

syllable [pérmwt] if it is used as a noun, but with heavy stress on the second syllable [permw´t] if it<br />

is used as a verb. Notice that this variation of stress is an example of how the sound system of a<br />

language is directly related to the classes of forms in a language. It is impossible to describe this<br />

variation without reference to whether permit is used as a noun or as a verb. There are many similar<br />

cases in English, e.g., contract, pervert, present, and so on. Consider also pairs of examples like the<br />

following:<br />

(2) a. Look at the black bird. (white house, long horn, light weight, light year, etc.)<br />

b. Look at the blackbird. (White House, longhorn, lightweight, light-year, etc.)<br />

One cannot describe the stress given to sequences like black+bird, unless one considers whether the<br />

sequence is used as a compound noun or as an adjective–noun construction. Examples such as these<br />

attest to the interrelationship of sound and form in the grammar of a language.<br />

2.1.6 SYLLABLES<br />

There are as many syllables in a word as there are vowel sounds. Note the following paying<br />

attention to sound, not spelling:<br />

(3) a. One syllable: I my mine strengths<br />

b. Two syllables: enough pygmy mining strengthens<br />

c. Three syllables: Michigan Missouri Tennessee strengthening<br />

67


68<br />

As these examples show, a syllable must contain a vowel. It also can begin and end with no<br />

consonants or one or more consonants. Using the symbol “C” for consonant and “V” for vowel, the<br />

following are examples of one syllable words that begin and end with one consonant, a CVC pattern:<br />

(4) CVC: pin seam gain suit zoom beaut<br />

We could simply repeat Cs to indicate multiple consonants, but since the number of successive<br />

consonants can fairly large (cf. strengths [streõg›s]), linguists often use a superscript to indicate the<br />

most number of consonants and subscript to indicate the least number of consonants. In the<br />

following notations, the superscript on the symbol “C” indicates the maximum number of<br />

consonants (n=any number greater than 1); the subscript indicates the minimum number (0=none).<br />

(5) a. All one syllable words: # C n<br />

0 V C n<br />

0<br />

b. All two syllable words: # C n<br />

0 V C n<br />

0 V C n<br />

0<br />

c. All three syllable words: # C n<br />

0 V C n<br />

0 V C n<br />

0 V C n<br />

0<br />

Here are some examples of one, two, and three syllable words using this notation:<br />

(6) a. All one syllable words: # Cn 0 V Cn I: a<br />

0<br />

y<br />

I’m: a ym<br />

my: m a y<br />

mine: m a yn<br />

streams: str i mz<br />

strengths: str e õg›s<br />

Flint: fl w nt<br />

b. All two syllable words: # C n<br />

0 V C n<br />

0 V C n<br />

0#<br />

enough i n f<br />

pygmy: p w gm i<br />

mining: m a yn w õ<br />

strengthens: str e õg› c nz<br />

Utah: y u ta<br />

Milford: m w lf c rd<br />

c. All three syllable words: # Cn 0 V Cn 0 V Cn 0 V Cn Michigan: m w š c g c<br />

0<br />

n<br />

Missouri: m c z u r i<br />

Tennessee: t e n c s i<br />

instructive: w nstr kt c v<br />

strengthening: str e õg› c n w õ<br />

fiasco: f i y æ sk o<br />

#<br />

#<br />

#<br />

#<br />

#


The last syllable is called the ULTIMA; the next to last syllable, the PENULT; the third to last<br />

syllable ANTEPENULT. Words with accents on each of these syllables are given in the following<br />

examples where the X indicates the position of the accent; the exact phonetic value for unaccented<br />

vowels may vary from speaker to speaker ([c], [w], [], etc.):<br />

(7) a. Accent on the ANTEPENULT: X<br />

Michigan: m w´ š c g c n<br />

buffalo: b ´ f c l o<br />

asterisks: æ´ st c r c sks<br />

America: c m é r c k c<br />

asparagus: c sp æ´ r c g c s<br />

b. Accent on the PENULT: X<br />

pygmy: p w´ gm i<br />

Utah: y ú t a<br />

Missouri: m c z ú r i<br />

aroma: c r ó m c<br />

verenda: v c r æ´ nd c<br />

chianti: k i y á nt i<br />

c. Accent on the ULTIMA: X<br />

streams: str í mz<br />

enough: i n ´ f<br />

Tennessee: t e n c s í<br />

Illinois: w l c n ]´y<br />

For practice, there are additional examples of stress placement in English words on pages 95 and<br />

96. The answers to those practice examples are on pages 106 and 107.<br />

2.2 PHONOLOGY<br />

With a complete phonetic system for the identification and classification of speech sounds available,<br />

phonologists can begin their work. Essentially, their task is to discover the ways in which the<br />

sounds of language are systematized. This includes finding out (i) which sounds, out of all the<br />

sounds a speaker of some language utters, are the <strong>linguistic</strong>ally significant sounds for that language,<br />

and (ii) which rules govern the organization and distribution of these sounds with respect to each<br />

other.<br />

In analyzing English, for example, phonologists observe that all English speakers pronounce p in<br />

several different ways. As we have seen, the sound [p h ] is followed by a perceptible puff of air,<br />

called ASPIRATION; this occurs in the articulation of a word like pin. In a word like spin, on the<br />

other hand, the p is not aspirated. As before, we use a superscript “h” for aspiration: the aspirated,<br />

voiceless, bilabial stop in English is [p h ], and the unaspirated, voiceless, bilabial stop is [p].<br />

69


70<br />

In examining English, phonologists also observe that there are no pairs of words which are<br />

distinguished by aspiration, in the way that there are many pairs which are distinguished by other<br />

phonetic features, such as [–VOICED] ([p h ]) and [+VOICED] ([b]), e.g., plank and blank, tap and<br />

tab, rapid and rabid, and so on. Lastly, they observe that [p] occurs only after the sound [s] and that<br />

[p h ] occurs everywhere else. Thus, in spot, spin, spoke, and Spain, the p is unaspirated, but in pot,<br />

pin, poke, and pain, the p is aspirated.<br />

These observations are important because they reveal that the distinction between [p] and [p h ], i.e.,<br />

unaspirated versus aspirated, is not a significant distinction in the phonology of English, unlike the<br />

distinction between [p h ] and [b], i.e., voiceless versus voiced. Thus, while it is possible to predict<br />

when [p], as opposed to [p h ], will occur in English words, it is not possible to predict when [p h ], as<br />

opposed to [b], will occur. This distinction is crucial in phonological analysis.<br />

Phonologists often call the distinctive classes of sounds in a language the PHONEMES of that<br />

language, and refer to the positional variants of phonetically similar sounds as the ALLOPHONES<br />

of a particular phoneme. To distinguish phonemes from allophones, the former are placed in slanted<br />

lines, e.g., /p/ and /b/, and the latter retain their phonetic symbolization, e.g., [p] and [p h ]. The<br />

relationship between a phoneme and its allophonic variants is expressed in the form of a rule<br />

included in the grammar of a language. For example, the relationship between /p/, [p], and [p h ] in<br />

English is expressed in two rules as follows:<br />

(8) a. The phoneme /p/ is realized phonetically as its allophone [p] when it occurs in the<br />

environment after [s], e.g., in the word spot.<br />

b. The phoneme /p/ is realized phonetically as its allophone [p h ] in most other<br />

environments, e.g., in the word pot.<br />

It is important to realize that sounds which are phonemic, i.e., distinctive, in one language may be<br />

allophonic, i.e., non–distinctive, in another language. For example, while [p h ] and [p] are allophones<br />

of the same phoneme /p/ in English, they are two different phonemes in Chinese. To put it<br />

differently, while [p h ] and [p] do not distinguish pairs of words in English, they do distinguish pairs<br />

of words in Chinese. The Chinese word pai, if pronounced with a [p h ], means ‘branch,’ and, if<br />

pronounced with a [p], means ‘weeds.’ It is very difficult for English speakers to master this<br />

distinction when they attempt to learn Chinese; very often, they confuse the two sounds.<br />

Conversely, speakers of many Asian languages have great difficulty in distinguishing the phonemes<br />

/l/ and /r/ in English, because these two sounds are not phonemic in their native language. Without<br />

considerable practice, a native speaker of Japanese, for example, might say rorripop when she<br />

means lollipop. When English speakers hear rorripop, they find it hard to believe that the Japanese<br />

speaker can’t easily hear the difference between what she’s said and lollipop. Similarly, a Chinese<br />

speaker will find it hard to believe that an American cannot easily distinguish between the distinct<br />

sounds [p h ] and [p].<br />

Continuing with their analysis of English, phonologists observe that the other voiceless stop<br />

phonemes in English, namely, /t/ and /k/, show the same allophonic variations as /p/. Thus, in stop,


stub, skin, school, the t and k sounds are unaspirated, but in top, tub, kin, and cool, they are aspirated.<br />

This is not unexpected, since /p/, /t/, and /k/ form a NATURAL CLASS of sounds, which is a class<br />

that shares the same set of distinctive features. In this case, the three sounds form the natural class<br />

of [+CONSONANT, –CONTINUANT, –NASAL, –VOICED]. Furthermore, the same natural class<br />

has another allophonic variation. In final position or at the end of a syllable, they become<br />

unreleased. Notice that the final sounds in cap, pat, and tack are not fully exploded in the way the<br />

initial sounds of the same words are; similarly, the p sound at the end of the first syllable in captain<br />

and the k sound at the end of the second syllable in refracted are also not fully exploded. We will<br />

use the symbol "°" to indicate lack of release. For example, we have [kæp°] (cap) and [kæp°t h wv]<br />

(captive). The environment in which "°" occurs is predictable by rule: voiceless stops are<br />

unreleased in final position of a syllable or word. Since the feature RELEASED is predictable in<br />

English, it is not distinctive.<br />

In Chapter One, we discussed the classification of several distinctive features for English, such as<br />

[±NASAL], [±VOICED], [±ANTERIOR], and [±CORONAL]. We now have two nondistinctive<br />

features in English: [± ASPIRATION] and [±RELEASE]. Summarizing, we have contrasts<br />

between distinctive and nondistinctive features like the following:<br />

(9) DISTINCTIVE FEATURES.<br />

a. [± VOICED]<br />

1. [–VOICED] [p], [t], [k]<br />

2. [+VOICED] [b], [d], [g]<br />

b. [± ANTERIOR]<br />

1. [–ANTERIOR] [k], [g]<br />

2. [+ANTERIOR] [p], [b], [t], [d]<br />

c. [± CORONAL]<br />

1. [–CORONAL] [p], [b], [k], [g]<br />

2. [+CORONAL] [t], [d]<br />

(10) NONDISTINCTIVE FEATURES.<br />

a. [± ASPIRATED]<br />

1. [–ASPIRATED] little breathiness<br />

(i) [p] spade [sped]<br />

(ii) [t] steam [stim]<br />

(iii) [k] school [skul]<br />

71


72<br />

2. [+ASPIRATED] considerable breathiness<br />

b. [± RELEASED]<br />

(i) [p h ] paid [p h ed]<br />

(ii) [t h ] teem [t h im]<br />

(iii) [k h ] cool [k h ul]<br />

1. [–RELEASED] no explosion<br />

(i) [p°] mop [map°]<br />

(ii) [t°] rate [ret°]<br />

(iii) [k°] nook [nk°]<br />

2. [+RELEASED] explosion<br />

(i) [p h ] paid [p h ed]<br />

(ii) [t h ] teem [t h im]<br />

(iii) [k h ] cool [k h ul]<br />

Phonologists discover the distinctive features of a language by looking for a pair of words<br />

distinguished by one and only one sound. Such a pair is called a MINIMAL PAIR. If two sounds<br />

occur in a minimal pair, then they occur in identical environments. This means that the two sounds<br />

are distinctive and distinguish words. (11) contains examples of minimal pairs; (12) does not.<br />

(11) MINIMAL PAIRS Good Examples (SPELLING IRRELEVANT):<br />

a. mace/base [mes]/[bes]<br />

b. ether/either [i›cr]/[iðcr]<br />

c. known/sewn/shone [non]/[son]/[šon]<br />

d. phlegm/Clem [flem]/[k h lem]<br />

e. who’d/hood [hud]/hd]<br />

f. bird/heard [bcrd]/[hcrd]<br />

(12) Not Examples (SPELLING IRRELEVANT):<br />

a. buff/bluff [bf]/[blf]<br />

b. choose/loose [čuz]/[lus]<br />

c. though/tough [ðo]/[tf]<br />

d. chef/chief [šef]/[čif]<br />

e. great/heart [gret]/[hart]<br />

f. beard/heard [bird]/[hcrd]


As we have had occasion to notice many times in this book, an important objective of <strong>linguistic</strong>s is<br />

the construction of formal grammars. A formal grammar is simply one that is perfectly explicit and<br />

testable. Precision is essential in <strong>linguistic</strong>s, as it is in all other sciences. Without precision,<br />

hypothetical principles and rules cannot be evaluated and tested with confidence. If hypotheses<br />

cannot be tested, then substantive conclusions cannot be drawn. Rules such as those in (8) are too<br />

informally written to satisfy scientific criteria. Therefore, linguists usually replace them with a<br />

SLASH–DASH notation as follows:<br />

FORMAL PHONOLOGICAL RULES:<br />

(13) a. [+STOP, –VOICED] ÷ [–ASPIRATED] / [s] ___<br />

a voiceless stop is unaspirated after [s]<br />

b. [+STOP, –VOICED] ÷ [–RELEASED] / {+, #}<br />

a voiceless stop is unreleased before a syllable boundary or a<br />

word boundary<br />

Each symbol in this notation has a precise meaning. As a result the rules are explicit and testable.<br />

The slash–dash notation, which will be used throughout this text, observes the following<br />

conventions:<br />

THE SLASH–DASH NOTATION:<br />

(14) a. ÷ means ‘is’<br />

b. (...) items in parentheses are optional<br />

c. {...} items in curly brackets or braces are alternatives<br />

d. / means ‘in the environment of’<br />

e. ___ means ‘before’ or ‘after’ or ‘between’<br />

f. / ___x means ‘before x’<br />

g. / x___ means ‘after x’<br />

h. / x___y means ‘between x and y’<br />

i. # means ‘word boundary’<br />

j. #___ means ‘after a word boundary,’ that is, ‘at beginning of word’<br />

k. ___# means ‘before a word boundary,’ that is, ‘at end of word’<br />

l. + means ‘syllable boundary’ or ‘morpheme boundary’<br />

m. +___ means ‘after a syllable or morpheme boundary’<br />

n. ___+ means ‘before a syllable or morpheme boundary’<br />

Summarizing the theoretical apparatus developed so far, we say that phonological representations<br />

occur in pairs: a phonemic or abstract representation coupled with a phonetic or real representation.<br />

The two representations are related by phonological rules.<br />

The necessity for both levels of representation can be illustrated further in the following way (see<br />

Figure Seven below). Suppose one English speaker utters the sentence If you hit me, I’ll hit you.<br />

73


74<br />

What the speaker actually says in the second part of this sentence is [ayl hwču]. The verb, therefore,<br />

appears to be hitch [hwč]. But, although the listener has heard [hwč], what the listener understands<br />

is /hwt/ (hit). The real or superficial or phonetic representation, the one actually spoken and heard,<br />

is [hwč]; the abstract or underlying or phonemic representation, the one intended and understood, is<br />

/hwt/. The relationship between the two is accounted for by phonological rules like those in (13),<br />

specifically, (15a) and (15b).<br />

(15) a. [t] ÷ [č] / ___ [y]<br />

b. [y] ÷ Ø / [č]___<br />

(15a) changes a [t] to a [č] before [y]; (15b) deletes a [y] after [č]. The symbol "Ø" means ‘zero’;<br />

so (15b) says that a [y] becomes zero (is deleted) after [č]. These rules represent the change of the<br />

sound [t] to [č]. The derivation from underlying form to surface form proceeds as follows:<br />

(16) UNDERLYING FORM: /hwt yu/<br />

APPLICATION OF RULE (15a): hwč yu<br />

APPLICATION OF RULE (15b): hwč u<br />

SUPERFICIAL FORM: [hwču]<br />

This derivation is intended to represent the native speaker’s knowledge (competence) of the intended<br />

meaning of what is actually uttered, namely, [hwču].<br />

To an introductory <strong>linguistic</strong>s student, a derivation like (16) often appears to be the result of<br />

hocus–pocus. This is not the case. The derivation proceeds from facts: in the example cited, there<br />

is a discrepancy between what is uttered and heard ([hwču]), on the one hand, and what is intended<br />

and understood (/hwt/), on the other. Further, all native speakers of English know this unconsciously;<br />

it is part of their <strong>linguistic</strong> competence. If this were not the case, the person hearing [hwču] in the<br />

context given, would not understand the intended meaning. These facts are givens; there is nothing<br />

that a linguist can do but attempt to describe and explain them. It is not the job of <strong>linguistic</strong>s to alter<br />

the way people communicate (a hopeless task, incidentally). The postulation of an abstract<br />

underlying form, related by rule to a real superficial form, is merely an effort to describe observed<br />

phenomena. Again, <strong>linguistic</strong> theory proceeds in the appropriately scientific manner. Notice that<br />

the example here is not isolated; in ordinary speech, the spoken form rarely matches the intended<br />

meaning word for word:<br />

(17) Spoken Form Intended Meaning Written Form<br />

a. [:9uwancgo] /du yu want tu go/ Do you want to go?<br />

b. [ičycdwnc] /it y]r dwncr/ Eat your dinner.<br />

c. []lcvcmcvleft] /]l f ðem hæv left/ All of them have left.<br />

d. [kwigcwawt] /kd wi go awt/ Could we go out?


FIGURE SEVEN: PHONOLOGICAL AND PHONETIC REPRESENTATIONS<br />

PHONEME ALLOPHONE<br />

DISTINCTIVE FEATURES<br />

[±VOICED]<br />

[±ANTERIOR]<br />

NONDISTINCTIVE FEATURES<br />

[±ASPIRATED]<br />

[±RELEASED]<br />

NOT PREDICTABLE BY RULE PREDICTABLE BY RULE<br />

NONREDUNDANT REDUNDANT<br />

FOUND IN MINIMAL PAIRS NOT FOUND IN MINIMAL PAIRS<br />

FOUND IN OVERLAPPING<br />

DISTRIBUTION (IN THE SAME<br />

ENVIRONMENTS)<br />

SLANTED LINE NOTATION<br />

/spat/ spot<br />

FOUND IN COMPLEMENTARY<br />

DISTRIBUTION (NOT IN THE SAME<br />

ENVIRONMENTS)<br />

SQUARE BRACKET NOTATION<br />

[spat°] spot<br />

UNDERLYING (DEEP) SUPERFICIAL (SURFACE)<br />

ABSTRACT REAL<br />

Examples: Examples:<br />

Will he hit me?<br />

/wwl hi hwt mi/<br />

Will he hit you?<br />

/wwl hi hwt yu/<br />

Willie hit you?<br />

/wwli hwt yu/<br />

Will he hitch you up?<br />

/wwl hi hwč yu p/<br />

Willie hitched you up?<br />

/wwli hwč+d yu p/<br />

Will he hit me?<br />

[wwli hwt° mi]<br />

Will he hit you?<br />

[wili hwču]<br />

Willie hit you?<br />

[wwli hwču]<br />

Will he hitch you up?<br />

[wwli hwču p°]<br />

Willie hitched you up?<br />

[wwli hwčt°ču p°]<br />

75


76<br />

2.3 PHONOTACTICS<br />

Further investigation of English phonology reveals that there are general restrictions on the<br />

sequences of sounds that are permissible in the language. There are ACCIDENTAL GAPS,<br />

sequences of sounds that just don’t happen to occur, and, NONACCIDENTAL GAPS, sequences<br />

of sounds that are not possible. The permissible sequences are specified in the PHONOTACTIC<br />

RULES of the language, that is the rules concerned with the sequential arrangements of sounds in<br />

larger units. Consider the following:<br />

(18) ACCIDENTAL GAP (possible words): [blwd], [stæno], [sprim]<br />

(19) NONACCIDENTAL GAP (impossible words): [ftwd], [zdæno], [spnim]<br />

In analyzing the PHONOTACTICS of English, phonologists would observe that an English word<br />

cannot end with two nasal consonants even if it is spelled with two. We see this in a root such as<br />

/kalmn/ which loses the second nasal in the word column [kalm], but retains it before the suffix<br />

–ist in the word columnist [kalmnwst]. Compare also autumn/autumnal and hymn/hymnal. The loss<br />

of the second nasal at the end of a word is accounted for by the following phonotactic rule:<br />

(20) [+NASAL] ÷ Ø / [+NASAL]___#<br />

In addition to (20), the phonotactic rules of English do not permit other consonants to occur before<br />

nasals at the beginning of a word. Notice that both consonants are pronounced only when they occur<br />

in separate syllables:<br />

(21) a. mnemonic [nemánwk] ‘helping the memory’<br />

amnesia [æmnéža] ‘loss of memory’<br />

b. pneumonia [ncmónya] ‘respiratory disease’<br />

apnea [æ´ pniya] ‘temporary loss of breathing’<br />

c. know [nó] ‘grasp in the mind’<br />

acknowledge [æknálc:9] ‘recognize’<br />

The data in (21) indicate that English also has the following rule:<br />

(22) [+CONSONANT] ÷ Ø / #____[+NASAL]<br />

The presence of rules like (22) is what makes some words retaining their foreign spelling look so<br />

strange as compared to their pronunciation, e.g., mnemonic, pneumonia, and pterodactyl, which<br />

come to English from Ancient Greek. Still, the deleted consonant must be considered part of the<br />

root so that the words can be related. Thus, the root for know must be /kno/ in order to relate know<br />

and acknowledge. As before, we must appeal to an abstract level of representation to do so.


In addition to specific phonotactic rules such as those above involving nasals, there are more<br />

generalized phonotactic rules. For example, if an English word begins with three consonants (CCC),<br />

the first one must be [s], the second one must be a voiceless stop ([p], [t], or [k]), and the third one<br />

must be a liquid ([l] or [r]).<br />

(23) a. spl- splash [splæš] spr- spread [spred]<br />

b. stl- * str- stream [strim]<br />

c. skl- sclaff [sklæf] skr- scream [skrim]<br />

Notice that, so far, there are no English words that begin with [stl]. Given the other possibilities,<br />

that gap should probably be considered an accidental gap.<br />

2.4 MORPHOLOGY<br />

As one might expect, the study of the sound system of a language cannot be carried out in complete<br />

isolation from the other components of grammar. The phonological rules, in particular, very often<br />

involve reference to MORPHEMES, which are the minimal units of meaning in a language.<br />

Consider the following (ignoring details involving aspiration and release):<br />

(24) MORPHEME: a minimum unit of distinctive meaning.<br />

a. [spikcr] ‘speaker’; 2 syllables; 2 morphemes:<br />

/spik/ ‘to utter words’<br />

/cr/ ‘agent’<br />

b. [kriyetcr] ‘creator’; 3 syllables; 2 morphemes.<br />

/kriyet/ ‘to bring into existence’<br />

/cr/ ‘agent’<br />

c. [dalcr] ‘dollar’; 2 syllables; 1 morpheme.<br />

d. [æntlcr] ‘antler’; 2 syllables; 1 morpheme<br />

e. [bwgcr] ‘bigger’; 2 syllables; 2 morphemes<br />

/bwg/ ‘large in size’<br />

/cr/ ‘more’<br />

As the examples in (24) show, morphemes are not necessarily equivalent to either words or<br />

syllables. Further, a particular sequence of sounds can be a morpheme in one word and not another:<br />

notice [cr] in speaker is a morpheme, whereas the [cr] in antler is not. Similarly [pik] is a<br />

morpheme in peeks [piks], but not in speaks [spiks]. Lastly, observe that the morpheme /cr/ either<br />

indicates an agent or expresses the comparative (more).<br />

77


78<br />

Morphemes have different phonetic variants in different contexts just as phonemes do. Paralleling<br />

the PHONEME/ALLOPHONE relation, we have the MORPHEME/ALLOMORPH relation.<br />

An ALLOMORPH is a conditioned phonetic variation of a morpheme. Consider the following:<br />

(25) ALLOMORPH: a conditioned PHONETIC variation of a morpheme:<br />

a. Negative Prefix:<br />

[wm]: impossible, imbalance<br />

[wn]: intangible, indiscrete<br />

[wõ]: incorrigible, ingratitude<br />

b. The indefinite article:<br />

[]: a book, a use, a hotel<br />

[æn]: an owl, an honor<br />

For the grammarian, one point of particular interest in morphological analysis concerns the nature<br />

of the variations which specific morphemes show in their phonetic shape. Occasionally, this<br />

variation is peculiar and reflects the idiosyncratic speech habits of individual speakers. For example,<br />

some English speakers pronounce abdomen with heavy stress on the first syllable, while others<br />

pronounce it with heavy stress on the second syllable. In such cases as this, the rival forms are said<br />

to be in FREE VARIATION.<br />

More commonly, a variation in the pronunciation of a morpheme is predictable and reflects specific<br />

rules in the grammar of a particular language, sometimes called MORPHOPHONEMIC or<br />

MORPHOPHONOLOGICAL RULES. For example, the plural morpheme in English nouns is<br />

variously pronounced [cz] as in busses, [s] as in bucks, and [z] as in bugs.<br />

The occurrence of each of these allomorphic variants is predictable in terms of the phonetic<br />

environment in which the plural morpheme occurs. If the morpheme occurs after [s], [z], [š], [ž],<br />

[č], or [:9], it is realized phonetically as [cz], e.g., dresses, sizes, ashes. Otherwise, if it occurs after<br />

a voiceless consonant, it is realized phonetically as [s], e.g., tanks, pipes, slots; if it occurs after a<br />

voiced consonant or after a vowel, it is realized phonetically as [z], e.g., bulbs, trees, eggs. Utilizing<br />

the theory of distinctive features, we can formally represent these rules as follows (where PL means<br />

‘plural’):<br />

(26) a. PL ÷ [cz] / [+SIBILANT] ___<br />

b. PL ÷ [s] / [–VOICED] ___<br />

c. PL ÷ [z] / [+VOICED] ___<br />

These same variations are also found in the morpheme which indicates the third person singular<br />

present tense of verbs, e.g., [cz] as in blesses and pleases, [s] as in attempts and pollutes, and [z] as<br />

in confides and specifies. They also appear in contractions (he’s for he is) and in possessives, e.g.,<br />

[cz] as in Bess’s and Josh’s, [s] as in Pat’s and Skip’s, and [z] as in Budd’s and Don’s.


2.5 THE BIOLOGICAL BASIS OF PHONOLOGY<br />

In Chapter One, we discussed two fundamental problems for <strong>linguistic</strong> theory, the grammatical<br />

characterization problem and the grammatical realization problem. We pointed out that the ultimate<br />

objective of <strong>linguistic</strong> research is to uncover the specifications of UG, the collection of features and<br />

principles which are potential characteristics of any human language. This goal is achieved by<br />

relating the facts of grammatical characterization to the facts of grammatical realization.<br />

The rules we have considered so far are descriptively adequate (see Chapter One) as far as the<br />

examples cited are concerned; however, they are not general enough. We can attain a higher level<br />

of descriptive adequacy. In this regard, <strong>linguistic</strong>s is not different from any other discipline,<br />

business, or enterprise. Everyone is searching for the most cost-effective solution to problems.<br />

Consider, first, rule (15a) and notice that both members of the pair [t]–[č] are voiceless. If our<br />

theory is correct, we expect the other members of this natural class to behave similarly, that is, we<br />

expect the grammar to contain (27).<br />

(27) [d] ÷ [:9] / ___ [y]<br />

In fact, English does have (27), as (28) shows.<br />

(28) a. If you hide me, I’ll hide you.<br />

b. If you hide me, /ay wwl hayd yu/<br />

c. If you hide me, [ayl hay :9u].<br />

Since the sounds involved form a natural class, we can collapse (15a) and (27) to (29), thereby<br />

attaining a higher level of descriptive adequacy.<br />

(29) [–SIBILANT, +ANTERIOR] ÷ [+SIBILANT, –ANTERIOR] / ___[y]<br />

This rule appears to be correct; however, we have gone too far. The feature constellation<br />

[–SIBILANT, +ANTERIOR] includes many consonants other than [t] and [d]; specifically, it<br />

includes [p], [b], [m], [n], [›], [ð], [l], [r], and [y]. None of these sounds becomes an affricate before<br />

[y]; therefore, we amend (29) to (30):<br />

(30)<br />

79


80<br />

Notice that (30) involves a change of two distinctive features; the other features remain unchanged.<br />

The result is that an alveolar stop ([t] or [d]) followed by the anterior glide ([y]) becomes an affricate<br />

([č] or [:9], respectively). It is important to realize that one letter or sound does not turn into another.<br />

The letter t and the sound [t] are merely abbreviations for constellations of distinctive features<br />

derived from characteristics of the human vocal apparatus. It is these features that change in the<br />

operation of phonological rules. In (30), two of the features in the feature cluster change value; the<br />

others remain unchanged.<br />

Notice also that our concern for formalism, that is, precision, now pays off, because only now can<br />

we ask the really important questions: Why does the grammar of a human language contain a rule<br />

like (30)? Do children born in an English speaking environment have to learn this rule specifically,<br />

as a peculiar fact about English, in the way that they must learn that the past tense of go is went?<br />

The answer to these questions involves a dynamic that exists between the structure of the human<br />

vocal apparatus and the general phonology of English. This dynamic is influenced by a number of<br />

factors.<br />

First, notice that rapid articulation of the sound sequence [tyu] sounds very much like [ču], and the<br />

articulation of [dyu] sounds very much like [:9u]. The reason for this is due to the position the<br />

tongue must assume during the articulation of the sequences [tyu] and [dyu]. Thus, it would be quite<br />

natural for speakers to merge [t]/[d] and [yu] across a word boundary, substituting [ču] for [tyu] and<br />

[:9u] for [dyu] in rapid articulation.<br />

Second, this substitution would be particularly likely under two conditions: (i) if the phonology of<br />

the language includes the sounds [č] and [:9] as phonemes, and (ii) if the language does not have a<br />

phonological distinction between [ty] and [č], or [dy] and [:9]. These two conditions both exist in<br />

English. The sounds [č] and [:9] are common in all dialects (chew, church, chat, chair, cheer; Jew,<br />

judge, jet, jam, jeer, etc.). Furthermore, most dialects of English do not have phonetic sequences<br />

of [t] or [d] followed by [y] unless there is a pause in pronunciation. The usual pronunciation of<br />

tune, for example, is [tun], not [tyun].<br />

For these reasons, in rapid speech, it is natural for an English speaker, knowing the overall<br />

phonology of English, to apply (30). What this means is that, in the overall phonology of any given<br />

language, some phonological rules may follow naturally given other factors. The suggestion,<br />

therefore, is that an English speaking child does not have to learn (30) specifically as a peculiar,<br />

isolated fact about English.<br />

This analysis clearly indicates that some phonological processes are at least partially predictable.<br />

In other words, children learning a language are not faced with the task of acquiring a set of rules<br />

that are isolated, idiosyncratic, and arbitrary. Apparently, language acquisition is possible precisely<br />

because a significant portion of the grammar of all natural languages is a direct reflection of the<br />

nature of the apparatus used to produce them, that is, of the articulatory and auditory organs and the<br />

brain.


This issue is important enough to require careful scrutiny. Therefore, let us consider a more<br />

extended example and return to the rules for forming the plural given in (26). As we discussed in<br />

the Introduction (Page 12 ff.), there is an alternation in the allomorph which signals past tense in<br />

English that is similar to the rules in (26). Consider the following (where PST means ‘past tense’):<br />

(31) a. PST ÷ [cd] / {[t], [d]} ___<br />

b. PST ÷ [t] / [–VOICED] ___<br />

c. PST ÷ [d] / [+VOICED] ___<br />

Rule (31a) correctly specifies past tense forms like relented ([rilentcd]) and applauded<br />

([cplawdcd]); (31b), disliked ([dwslaykt]) and laughed ([læft]); (31c), nagged ([nægd]), riled<br />

([rayld]), and relayed ([riled]). Notice that all past tenses of regular verbs in English are spelled<br />

either –ed or –d; but, this is not relevant to their pronunciation. Compare riled ([rayld]) and relayed<br />

([riled]). As we have seen, the rules of language are based on speech, not writing.<br />

The important question now is, Can the characterizations in (26) for the plural and (31) for the past<br />

tense be related to universal grammar? The answer is, Yes. The following sections specify that<br />

relationship.<br />

2.5.1 FIRST SET OF OBSERVATIONS<br />

Notice that (26) and (31) are very similar. Both sets of rules begin with a rule that deals with the<br />

allomorphic variant that occurs when the morpheme and the stem to which it is suffixed are<br />

HOMORGANIC, that is, share the same or very similar set of distinctive features.<br />

(26a) deals with the suffixation of a [+SIBILANT, +CORONAL] morpheme to a word which ends<br />

in a sound that is [+SIBILANT, +CORONAL]. (31a) deals with the suffixation of an alveolar stop<br />

([–CONTINUANT, –NASAL, +ANTERIOR, +CORONAL]) to a word which ends in an alveolar<br />

stop. In both sets of rules, a separate syllable is created by inserting the neutral vowel [c] in order<br />

to distinguish the morpheme from the stem to which it is being attached. Furthermore, if this were<br />

not done, some sequences violating English (if not, universal) phonotactics would be the result, e.g.,<br />

*[æss] and *[cplawdd].<br />

In the remaining rules in both sets, a very common phonological process occurs. This process,<br />

called ASSIMILATION, involves making adjacent sound segments similar in distinctive feature<br />

composition. In (26) and (31) the assimilation involves the feature [±VOICED]. Assimilation in<br />

natural languages is so common that it is considered the UNMARKED or expected case. Lack of<br />

assimilation in suffixation is the MARKED or atypical case.<br />

Given these remarks, we specify the morphemes in question as (32), and we replace (26) and (31)<br />

with the more general principles in (33).<br />

81


82<br />

(32) a. The PST morpheme in English is the suffix [d].<br />

b. The PL morpheme in English is the suffix [z].<br />

(33) a. If a suffix and the final segment to which it is attached are homorganic, insert the<br />

neutral vowel [c] between the stem and the suffix.<br />

b. In all other cases, assimilate the suffix and the final segment in voicing.<br />

In order to express principles like (33) formally, we must have a way to represent a variable feature<br />

value. This is done using Greek letters in the spot in front of a feature where a “+” or “–” usually<br />

occurs. For example, we express voicing assimilation (33b) as follows:<br />

(34) [+CONSONANT] ÷ [αVOICED] / [αVOICED] + ___<br />

This rule says that a consonant beginning a suffix gets a value of voicing (either “+” or “–”) that is<br />

the same as the final segment before the morpheme boundary. Notice that “+” has two meanings:<br />

before a feature as in [+VOICED], it indicates a positive value for the feature; by itself in a rule like<br />

(34), it indicates a morpheme boundary.<br />

Sometime, several features assimilate at the same time. In this case, more than one Greek letter is<br />

necessary to separate the assimilating features from each other. For example, consider again the<br />

negative prefix given in (25a), repeated here:<br />

(35) a. [wm]: impossible, imbalance<br />

b. [wn]: intangible, indiscrete<br />

c. [wõ]: incorrigible, ingratitude<br />

In this set of data, there is an assimilation of the features ANTERIOR and CORONAL to those of<br />

segment beginning the word. This means that the value (“+” or “–”) of the features ANTERIOR and<br />

CORONAL of the consonant beginning the word must be the same as the prefix. We can express<br />

this as follows:<br />

(36) [+NASAL] ÷ [αANTERIOR, βCORONAL] / ___+ [αANTERIOR, βCORONAL]<br />

In this rule, we must keep the assimilating values for ANTERIOR separate from those of<br />

CORONAL; hence, two Greek letters are needed. The value of “α” and “β” must be the same in<br />

both places where each occurs in the rule. In short, (36) abbreviates the following four rules:<br />

(37) [+NASAL] ÷ [+ANTERIOR, –CORONAL] / ___+ [+ANTERIOR, –CORONAL]<br />

(38) [+NASAL] ÷ [–ANTERIOR, +CORONAL] / ___+ [–ANTERIOR, +CORONAL]<br />

(39) [+NASAL] ÷ [+ANTERIOR, +CORONAL] / ___+ [+ANTERIOR, +CORONAL]<br />

(40) [+NASAL] ÷ [–ANTERIOR, –CORONAL] / ___+ [–ANTERIOR, –CORONAL]


Clearly, a rule like (36) will be needed to express the homorganicity in (33a). For example, if we<br />

wish to express the insertion of [c] before the past tense morpheme [d], then (41) is needed.<br />

(41)<br />

Similarly, (42) is needed for the insertion of [c] before the plural morpheme [z]:<br />

(42)<br />

Using the α–notation, we can collapse these to (43), the formal expression of (33a) .<br />

(43)<br />

2.5.2 SECOND SET OF OBSERVATIONS<br />

We have now correctly identified the morphemes for the plural and for the past tense (cf. (32)),<br />

repeated here as (44).<br />

(44) a. The PST morpheme in English is the suffix [d].<br />

b. The PL morpheme in English is the suffix [z].<br />

We have also formally expressed the distribution of the allomorph in (33a)/(43) and (33b)/(34),<br />

repeated here together as (45).<br />

83


84<br />

(45) a. If a suffix and the final segment to which it is attached are homorganic, insert the<br />

neutral vowel [c] between the stem and the suffix.<br />

b. In all other cases, assimilate the suffix and the final segment in voicing.<br />

[+CONSONANT] ÷ [αVOICED] / [αVOICED] + ___<br />

How does this characterization in (44) and (45) relate to what speakers know? It is clear that native<br />

speakers of English know what the two morphemes are and how they are distributed. English<br />

speakers do not have to hear the plural of every noun and the past tense of every verb in order to<br />

produce the correct forms. In fact, if speakers are given nonsense words and asked to make them<br />

plural or past tense, they produce forms which obey (44) and (45). Moreover, speakers make up<br />

words in the correct number and tense all the time. For example, on a recent TV commentary of the<br />

US Figure Skating Championships, Peggy Fleming said, She two–footed that landing. Members of<br />

the television audience did not wince at the new verb two–foot; everyone routinely understood it.<br />

Further, the correct allomorph was uttered and understood, even though the expression must have<br />

been a neologism to most who heard it. Examples like this occur very frequently.<br />

Young children also produce forms that they never could have heard: past tenses like [god] ‘goed’<br />

and [›rod] ‘throwed’; plurals like [mænz] ‘mans’ and [fts] ‘foots.’ These overgeneralizations give<br />

clear evidence that the substance of (44) and (45) is unconsciously known to native speakers of<br />

English from a very early age.<br />

Do native speakers (unconsciously) know (44) and (45) in the form given? The answer is not clear.<br />

While the substance of (44) and (45) can be expressed in many different ways, the characterization<br />

given is the most generalized. Science usually tries to account for natural phenomena with the most<br />

generalized descriptions possible. But there is no way to determine whether or not people do the<br />

same when they learn their native language. In fact, it may be the case that the rules of language are<br />

redundantly specified. Future psycho<strong>linguistic</strong> and neuro<strong>linguistic</strong> investigations may help to settle<br />

this issue.<br />

At this point, <strong>linguistic</strong>s is in the same position as other disciplines, businesses, and enterprises. We<br />

have produced the best possible product our ingenuity and science have allowed, namely, (44) and<br />

(45). It remains to be seen how well our product fares upon further scrutiny.


2.5.3 THIRD SET OF OBSERVATIONS<br />

Summarizing, we can say that (44) and (45) reach a very high level of descriptive adequacy. They<br />

adequately account for all the known cases, and do so in a highly generalized way. Further, the<br />

substance of (44) and (45) is unconsciously known to every native speaker.<br />

Consider next the question whether children have to learn both (44) and (45). It seems clear that<br />

children are not born with unconscious knowledge of (44), because (44) contains facts peculiar to<br />

English. There is no reason in principle why, say, the meanings of the morphemes couldn’t be<br />

reversed in some other language. The rule (45a) is also peculiar to English; however, its effect is<br />

to differentiate morphemes, so we would expect other languages to have rules of similar design.<br />

The status of (45b) is another matter. The rule (45b) is a good candidate for UG status, that is, it is<br />

possible that (45b) is part of every human being’s genetic makeup. This would mean that it follows<br />

directly and naturally from the nature of the human language apparatus, and that a particular form<br />

in a particular language violating (45b) would be MARKED in the sense described above. Human<br />

languages generally have a voicing assimilation rule, apparently because it is easier for a human<br />

vocal apparatus to articulate adjacent sounds with the same voicing than with opposite voicing. This<br />

is particularly true at the end of a word. As a result, we say that children do not have to learn (45b);<br />

it is part of their genetic endowment; it is the UNMARKED case.<br />

While this discussion is far from conclusive, it does show that all the facts in the characterization<br />

of a language are not equal. Some facts may be highly marked, and, therefore, take children a long<br />

time to master. Other facts may reflect inner characteristics of man, and, therefore, be part of the<br />

innate knowledge that children bring to native language acquisition. Because children have a human<br />

language apparatus, some features and principles are more likely to occur in a human language than<br />

others.<br />

2.6 THE PHONOLOGICAL AND LEXICAL COMPONENTS OF A GRAMMAR<br />

The PHONOLOGICAL COMPONENT of a grammar consists of the list of phonological rules.<br />

These are rules like (34), (36), and (43), which relate underlying forms to superficial forms. Also<br />

included in the phonological component are phonotactic rules like (20) and phonological<br />

REDUNDANCY RULES like (46).<br />

(46) a. [+HIGH] ÷ [+HIGH, –LOW]<br />

b. [+LOW] ÷ [+LOW, –HIGH]<br />

(46a) accounts for the fact that a segment that is [+HIGH] cannot also be [–LOW], and (46b)<br />

account for the reverse. These are redundantly specified features, that is, features that are<br />

predictable given other features.<br />

85


86<br />

Vowels have many redundant features. Since only vowels are [+TENSE], we can specify the<br />

redundancies as follows:<br />

(47) [+TENSE] ÷ [+TENSE, +SONORANT,–CONSONANTAL, +VOCALIC,<br />

+CONTINUANT, –NASAL, –SIBILANT, –ANTERIOR,<br />

–CORONAL, +VOICED]<br />

Since all the features except TENSE in (47) are redundant, they are generally left out of charts of<br />

distinctive features for vowels (cf. Figure Three on Page 58).<br />

The LEXICAL COMPONENT (LEXICON) of a grammar is the dictionary of morphemes and<br />

words, as well as lexical redundancy rules and rules of word formation. (38) is an example of<br />

lexical redundancy.<br />

(48) [+HUMAN] ÷ [+HUMAN, +ANIMATE, +CONCRETE]<br />

The rule (48) accounts for the fact that all HUMAN nouns are also ANIMATE and CONCRETE.<br />

The lexicon also contains morphemes like (49).<br />

(49) Morphemes:<br />

a. /trst/ trust, trusts, trusted, mistrust, mistrustful, entrust, untrustworthy, etc.<br />

b. /red/ raid, raids, raided, raiding, raider, raiders<br />

From these components, we can produce underlying representations like (50).<br />

(50) Underlying phonological representations:<br />

a. /trst+s/<br />

b. /trst+d/<br />

c. /mws+trst/<br />

d. /mws+trst+fl/<br />

Application of various phonological rules to (50) produces the following phonetic representations,<br />

respectively:<br />

(51) Phonetic representations (ignoring details involving aspiration and release):<br />

a. [trsts]<br />

b. [trstcd]<br />

c. [mwstrst]<br />

d. [mwstrstfl]


To these forms, various stress rules must apply assigning the appropriate intonation contours to<br />

words. We will return to a discussion of the lexicon in subsequent chapters.<br />

2.7 ENGLISH SPELLING<br />

It is no secret that English words are not spelled phonetically. In fact, lists of spelling nightmares<br />

like the following can be found in every student’s notebook:<br />

(52) a. rafter / laughter / slaughter<br />

b. slay / sleigh / sleight / slight<br />

c. ear / earn / urn / earth / hearth<br />

d. though / thought / through / tough<br />

e. for / fore / four / fourteen / forty<br />

Often, the same sound has many different spellings:<br />

(53) a. heard / word / bird / curd / nerd<br />

b. rays / raise / raze / weighs / phase / obeys<br />

c. weird / feared / veered / adhered<br />

d. birth / berth / worth / earth<br />

Likewise, similar spellings can signify widely different sounds:<br />

(54) a. beard [bird] / heard [hcrd]<br />

b. comb [kom] / tomb [tum] / bomb [bam]<br />

c. meat [mit] / great [gret] / threat [›ret] / heart [hart]<br />

d. cough [k]f] / bough [baw] / dough [do] / rough [rf] / through [›ru]<br />

One frequently hears desperate cries for reform of the English spelling system. While there are<br />

many peculiarities, it is clear that a system of phonetic spelling would undermine the considerable<br />

regularity between English spelling and English morphology. For example, consider the various<br />

spellings of the reduced vowel schwa (c) in the second syllable of fallacy, remedy, family, history,<br />

luxury. In these, as in other cases, the spelling derives from the spelling of the root word as<br />

comparisons reveal:<br />

(55) a. Spelled a: fallacy/fallacious; comparable/compare; legacy/allegation<br />

b. Spelled e: remedy/remedial; manager/managerial; competent/compete<br />

c. Spelled i: family/familial; president/preside; immigrate/migrate<br />

d. Spelled o: history/historian; consolation/console; janitor/janitorial<br />

e. Spelled u: luxury/luxurious; injury/injurious; mercury/mercurial<br />

87


88<br />

Similarly, silent letters frequently show up in related words:<br />

(56) a. Silent n: hymn/hymnal; column/columnar, columnist; damn/damnation<br />

b. Silent g: resign/resignation; sign/signal, designate; phlegm/phlegmatic<br />

c. Others: muscle/muscular; bomb/bombard; soften/soft; know/acknowledge<br />

There are also many regularities. For example, consider the vowel alterations in (47) where the<br />

silent e indicates that the preceding vowel must be tense.<br />

(57) Lax/Tense Vowel Alternations<br />

a. [ay]/[w]: divine/divinity; ignite/ignition; wide/width; type/typical<br />

b. [ey]/[æ]: profane/profanity; sane/sanity; bathe/bath; shade/shadow<br />

c. [iy]/[e]: serene/serenity; redeem/redemption; sleep/slept; meter/ metric<br />

d. [aw]/[]: profound/profundity; abound/abundant; south/southern<br />

e. [ow]/[a]: verbose/verbosity; know/knowledge; nose/nostril; phone/phonic<br />

These vowel alternations are rule governed as are the consonant alternations in (58) and (59).<br />

(58) Stop/Fricative Alternations<br />

a. [t/[s]: democrat/democracy; president/presidency; pirate/piracy<br />

b. [k/[s]: electric/electricity; public/publicity; medical/medicine<br />

c. [s]/[š]: express/expression; digress/digression; race/racial; space/spatial<br />

d. [z]/[ž]: revise/revision; infuse/infusion; excise/excision; confuse/confusion<br />

e. [t/[š]: relate/relation; ignite/ignition; native/nation; president/presidential<br />

f. [k/š]: logic/logician; magic/magician; practical/practitioner<br />

g. [d]/[ž]: persuade/persuasion; corrode/corrosion; decide/decision<br />

h. [d]/[s] persuade/persuasive/; corrode/corrosive; divide/divisive<br />

I. [z]/[s] abuse (verb)/abusive; diffuse/diffusive; advise/advice; choose/choice<br />

(59) Stop/Affricate Alternations<br />

a. [d]/[:9]: grade/gradual; residue/residual; fraud/fraudulent; proceed/procedure<br />

b. [t/[č]: right/righteous; Christ/Christian; quest/question; moist/moisture<br />

c. [g]/[:9]: allegation/allege; regal/regicide; rigor/rigid; gregarious/egregious<br />

Basically, changing English spelling to a system that is phonetic would obscure many of the regular<br />

allomorphic variations in the language. A much better approach would be to teach students<br />

something about English phonology and morphology pointing out that English spelling reveals<br />

underlying regularities. Discussion of the rules governing these alternations requires considerable<br />

technical mastery and is beyond the capabilities of elementary school children trying to cope with<br />

English spelling. However, it would certainly be both possible and helpful to point out the<br />

regularities as the words entered children’s vocabulary studies.


2.8 SUMMARY OF RULE FORMALISM<br />

SYMBOL MEANING<br />

1. [x] x is a PHONETIC symbol or feature<br />

2. /x/ x is a PHONEMIC symbol or feature<br />

3. Ø null<br />

4. ÷ is<br />

5. / in the environment of<br />

6. ___ before, after, or between<br />

7. / ___ x before x<br />

8. / x ___ after x<br />

/ x ___ y between x and y<br />

9. # word boundary<br />

/ # ___ at beginning of word<br />

/ ___ # at end of word<br />

10. + morpheme boundary<br />

/ + ___ after a morpheme boundary<br />

/ ___ + before a morpheme boundary<br />

11. C CONSONANT<br />

12. V VOWEL<br />

13. (x) x is an OPTIONAL element<br />

14. {x, y, z} x, y, and z are ALTERNATIVE elements<br />

15. [x, y, z] x, y, and z are a cluster of features<br />

2.9 NOTES ON SYLLABLES<br />

A word has as many syllables as it has vowels. Each vowel can be preceded and followed by any<br />

number of consonants. The superscript on the symbol “C” indicates the maximum number of<br />

consonants (n=any number greater than 1); the subscript indicates the minimum number (0=none).<br />

1. All one syllable words: # C n<br />

0 V C n<br />

0<br />

2. All two syllable words: # C n<br />

0 V C n<br />

0 V C n<br />

0 #<br />

3. All three syllable words: # Cn 0 V Cn 0 V Cn 0 V Cn 0<br />

4. Vowel in the last syllable (ULTIMA): / __ C n<br />

0<br />

5. Vowel in the next to last syllable (PENULT): / __ C n<br />

0<br />

6. Vowel in the third to last syllable (ANTEPENULT): / __ C n<br />

0<br />

VC n<br />

0<br />

VC n<br />

0<br />

VC n<br />

0<br />

#<br />

#<br />

#<br />

#<br />

#<br />

89


90<br />

VOWELS:<br />

SUMMARY OF ENGLISH SOUNDS AND SPELLING<br />

[i] [iy] [iw] beat, beet, Caesar, people, we, machine, receive, believe<br />

[w] bit, into, been, abyss, fountain, button, language<br />

[u] [uw] [u] boot, who, duty, through, too, to, two, new, nuisance, blue<br />

[] put, wood, would, butcher, woman<br />

[e] [ey] [ew] bait, fate, great, eight, rain, reign, rein, they, hay, gauge<br />

[e] bet, dead, said, guest, many, friend, says, jeopardy<br />

[c] butted, roses, alone, sofa, the<br />

[o] [ow] [o] boat, so, sew, own, though, plateau, toe, soul, brooch<br />

[]] bought, caught, chalk, saw, awful, author, sore, soar, four<br />

[æ] bat, laugh, plaid<br />

[] but, does, tough, flood, ton, country<br />

[a] [Y] pot, palm, far, sergeant, ox<br />

DIPHTHONGS:<br />

[]y] []w] boy, soil<br />

[ay] [aw] sigh, nice, guy, lie<br />

[aw] [a] cow, house<br />

GLIDES:<br />

[w] wish, queen, weather, wear (for some, also when, whether, where)<br />

[ ] when, whether, where<br />

[y] [j] yes, beyond, use, feud<br />

[h] high, whole<br />

LIQUIDS:<br />

[l] live, along<br />

[ł] drill, willing<br />

[r] [‹] rich, car, bury, furry<br />

[D] [] water, later, latter, ladder, writer, rider, party


NASALS:<br />

SUMMARY OF ENGLISH SOUNDS AND SPELLING<br />

[m] mess, hymn, hum, swimming<br />

[n] neat, kin, winning, pneumonia, knife<br />

[ñ] [ny] [nj] onion, union<br />

[õ] sing, think, tongue<br />

STOPS:<br />

[p h ] pain, prune, plaque, appear, shrimps<br />

[p] spit, spun, spring, expose<br />

[b] broom, crabs, rubber<br />

[t h ] tip, tough, pterodactyl, intend, attack<br />

[t] stick, stun, string, extend<br />

[d] dig, bad, killed, heard, mending<br />

[k h ] keep, cat, chord, quite, pickle, accommodate<br />

[k] skit, scum, school, screw, excuse<br />

[g] give, bag, egg, rogue<br />

FRICATIVES:<br />

[f] first, stuff, telephone, rough<br />

[v] value, sliver, of<br />

[›] thin, breath, teeth, ether, both, thing<br />

[ð] then, breathe, teethe, either<br />

[s] sin, this, cross, science, ceiling, race, psychology<br />

[z] zoo, drizzle, was, xylophone, scissors<br />

[š] [•] show, chute, flash, issue, conscious, sure, mansion, racial<br />

[ž] [¥] measure, azure, prestige, illusion<br />

AFFRICATES:<br />

[č] [t•] chin, kitchen, question, righteous, much<br />

[:9] [d¥] jig, judgment, ridge, gem, graduation, region<br />

91


EXERCISES FOR CHAPTER TWO<br />

1. Transcribe the following English words (Answers in Appendix A):<br />

rich ridge ring wring wrist<br />

bush butch budge box buzz<br />

gem Jim sham chum gum<br />

ice eyes east eased oozed<br />

race raise rays rise rose<br />

lose loose louse chose choose<br />

cease seize seas says size<br />

chef chief chic sheik shack<br />

worth earth teethe bathe bath<br />

them this thumb thing then<br />

debt vex Scotch broth knot<br />

maize quiche squish queue shrew<br />

though cough rough bough through<br />

heard word bird curd nerd


weird feared veered cared cord<br />

meat great threat heart cart<br />

chair jeer share shear cheer<br />

wheel whale weigh who how<br />

witch which watch wretch wedge<br />

coat code root rude read<br />

laud loud laid led lewd<br />

knifed sighed prized healed shipped<br />

view dew do poor pour<br />

latch loaf roof tune pure<br />

car oar her hear whore<br />

George vague vast don’t they’re<br />

oath both moth mouth myth<br />

tit Tut tat toot tot<br />

who’d wood would wooed hood<br />

93


94<br />

2. Transcribe the following English words (Answers in Appendix A):<br />

music physics psychic sonic helix<br />

passion cashier cushion caption cashmere<br />

thistle thimble tumble dangle dinghy<br />

champagne cartoon Khartoum careen gangrene<br />

immune impugn impinge syringe obscene<br />

racial racer razor sugar quota<br />

pleasure pledger leisure azure seizure<br />

scissors vision fusion ocean mission<br />

beauty booty purely poorly pearly<br />

quitter water rider writer raider<br />

joining whining singing finger languor<br />

cavil navel ravel gable squabble<br />

Mary marry merry quarry query<br />

numbskull zigzag homegrown deathblow shipshape<br />

outboard marshlands whiplash pastime pitchfork<br />

cutthroat whetstone hangman onslaught crabgrass


3. Transcribe the following words including placement of primary stress (´). You can ignore<br />

aspiration and release. (v) = verb; (n) = noun.<br />

agree debris ennui Pawnee marquee<br />

angry money sunny gypsy litchi<br />

survey (v) Bombay bouquet inveigh parfait<br />

survey (n) bomb bay Tuesday foray subway<br />

review canoe shampoo construe eschew<br />

preview igloo curfew yahoo Zulu<br />

below outgrow plateau Bordeaux although<br />

bellow meadow hobo cocoa depot<br />

outcry (v) apply goodbye sky high untie<br />

outcry (n) ally cacti fish fry pigsty<br />

soda tchotchke bwana chutzpah geisha<br />

4. Transcribe the following words including placement of primary stress (´). You can ignore<br />

aspiration and release. (v) = verb; (n) = noun.<br />

broccoli apogee fricassee symphony pedigree<br />

shillelagh Chianti bologna confetti Hatari<br />

guarantee bourgeoisie chimpanzee Tennessee jamboree<br />

95


96<br />

runaway Saturday ricochet protégée workaday<br />

matinée San José Chevrolet Santa Fé overplay<br />

rendevous residue peekaboo honeydew avenue<br />

Timbuktu kangaroo misconstrue overthrew hitherto<br />

mistletoe Mexico embryo cameo Scorpio<br />

fiasco concerto soprano falsetto crescendo<br />

overflow (v) apropos status quo cheerio to-and-fro<br />

amplify rockaby occupy prophesy underlie<br />

subpoena agenda charisma pariah pagoda<br />

5. Transcribe the following words including placement of primary stress (´). You can ignore<br />

aspiration and release. (v) = verb; (n) = noun.<br />

apostrophe Menominee Penelope fraternity telegraphy<br />

Ypsilanti kamikaze Cincinnati insincerely poison ivy<br />

pistachio Arapaho imbroglio adagio portfolio<br />

armadillo Filipino virtuoso Sacramento lucky fellow<br />

Arabia azalea Bulgaria et cetera America<br />

hullabaloo Kalamazoo Tippecanoe


6. In each of the following, supply English words that contain the sound given in as many<br />

different spellings as you can. Underline the letters representing the sound in the answer.<br />

[f] Answer: physics, fish, enough<br />

a. [i] Answer:<br />

b. [r] Answer:<br />

c. [k] Answer:<br />

d. [š] Answer:<br />

e. [y] Answer:<br />

f. [e] Answer:<br />

g. [o] Answer:<br />

h. [:9] Answer:<br />

I. [e] Answer:<br />

j. []] Answer:<br />

7. Supply the symbol corresponding to each of the following phonetic descriptions.<br />

voiced velar stop consonant Answer: [g]<br />

a. lax mid back rounded vowel Answer:<br />

b. voiced alveolar liquid Answer:<br />

c. voiceless palatal affricate consonant Answer:<br />

d. tense low back unrounded vowel Answer:<br />

e. voiceless alveolar fricative consonant Answer:<br />

f. voiced palatal liquid Answer:<br />

g. voiceless bilabial stop consonant Answer:<br />

97


98<br />

h. tense high front unrounded vowel Answer:<br />

i. voiced velar nasal consonant Answer:<br />

j. voiced labiodental fricative consonant Answer:<br />

8. Write a phonetic description for each of the following symbols.<br />

[g] Answer: voiced velar stop consonant<br />

[o] Answer: tense mid back rounded vowel<br />

a. [h] Answer:<br />

b. [v] Answer:<br />

c. [e] Answer:<br />

d. [o] Answer:<br />

e. [ž] Answer:<br />

f. [›] Answer:<br />

g. [æ] Answer:<br />

h. [ñ] Answer:<br />

I. [č] Answer:<br />

j. [c] Answer:<br />

9. In each of the following, all but one of the sounds listed exhaustively comprise a natural class<br />

of sounds for English. Identify the sound that does not belong in the natural class AND name<br />

the feature or features that define the class.<br />

[k], [d], [g], [b] Choice: [k]<br />

Class: [+VOICED, +STOP]<br />

a. [a], [e], [], [æ] Choice:<br />

Class:


. [k], [õ], [h], [g] Choice:<br />

Class:<br />

c. [z], [č], [ð], [ž], [v] Choice:<br />

Class:<br />

d. [t], [›], [z], [ð], [s] Choice:<br />

Class:<br />

e. [u], [w], [o], [e], [i] Choice:<br />

Class:<br />

f. [w], [h], [y], [§] Choice:<br />

Class:<br />

g. [u], [o], [a], [], []] Choice:<br />

Class:<br />

h. [m], [w], [v], [b], [p] Choice:<br />

Class:<br />

I. [u], [i], [e], [w], [] Choice:<br />

Class:<br />

j. [õ], [m], [n], [h], [ñ] Choice:<br />

Class:<br />

10. State the following rules using formal devices (Answers in Appendix A).<br />

Example: A nasal consonant is deleted before another nasal consonant at the beginning of<br />

a word.<br />

Answer: [+CONSONANT, +NASAL] ÷ Ø / #___ [+CONSONANT, +NASAL]<br />

a. All intervocalic voiceless stops become voiced.<br />

99


100<br />

b. Nontense vowels in the final syllable of a word are stressed when they are followed by<br />

two or more consonants.<br />

c. Delete all final consonants when the following word begins with a consonant.<br />

d. Reduce all unstressed vowels to schwa.<br />

e. Palatalize all alveolar stops before [y].<br />

f. Devoice all final fricatives.<br />

g. Aspirate all initial voiceless stops.<br />

h. Nasalize all vowels before a nasal consonant.<br />

i. A lax vowel in the antepenultimate syllable of a word is stressed.<br />

j. Palatalize all alveolar stops before [y] when they are preceded by a vowel or when they<br />

are initial.


11. In Classical Latin, nouns have different endings (CASES) depending on their use in a<br />

sentence. For example, a noun functioning as the SUBJECT of a sentence has a<br />

NOMINATIVE CASE ending. One functioning as a POSSESSIVE phrase has a GENITIVE<br />

CASE ending. Consider the following, where a macron over a vowel means the vowel is long:<br />

NOMINATIVE GENITIVE MEANING<br />

arks arkis enclosure<br />

duks dukis leader<br />

daps dapis feast<br />

rēks rēgis king<br />

sēps sēpis snake<br />

falanks falangis phalanx<br />

urps urbis city<br />

pleps plebis people<br />

a. In terms of these data, what are the morphemes for the NOMINATIVE and the<br />

GENITIVE?<br />

b. What is the Latin morpheme for each of the following?<br />

(1) enclosure<br />

(2) leader<br />

(3) feast<br />

(4) king<br />

(5) snake<br />

(6) phalanx<br />

(7) city<br />

(8) people<br />

c. State any phonological rule(s) applicable in the above Latin data.<br />

101


102<br />

12. Consider the following additional Classical Latin data:<br />

NOMINATIVE GENITIVE MEANING<br />

li)s li)tis strife<br />

fraws frawdis deceit<br />

frōns frōntis brow<br />

frōns frōndis leaf<br />

dens dentis tooth<br />

sors sortis lot<br />

a. What are the morphemes for the NOMINATIVE and the GENITIVE?<br />

b. Give the Latin morphemes for each of the following:<br />

(1) strife<br />

(2) deceit<br />

(3) brow<br />

(4) leaf<br />

(5) tooth<br />

(6) lot<br />

c. State any phonological rule(s) in addition to those from the previous problem.


APPENDIX A: ANSWERS TO TRANSCRIPTION EXERCISES<br />

1. rich ridge ring wring wrist<br />

[rwč] [rw:9] [rwõ] [rwõ] [rwst]<br />

bush butch budge box buzz<br />

[bš] [bč] [b:9] [baks] [bz]<br />

gem Jim sham chum gum<br />

[:9em] [:9wm] [šæm] [čm] [gm]<br />

ice eyes east eased oozed<br />

[ays] [ayz] [ist] [izd] [uzd]<br />

race raise rays rise rose<br />

[res] [rez] [rez] [rayz] [roz]<br />

lose loose louse chose choose<br />

[luz] [lus] [laws] [čoz] [čuz]<br />

cease seize seas says size<br />

[sis] [siz] [siz] [sez] [sayz]<br />

chef chief chic sheik shack<br />

[šef] [čif] [šik] [šik] [šæk]<br />

worth earth teethe bathe bath<br />

[wcr›] [cr›] [t h ið] [beð] [bæ›]<br />

them this thumb thing then<br />

[ðem] [ðws] [›m] [›iõ] [ðen]<br />

debt vex Scotch broth knot<br />

[det] [veks] [skač] [br]›] [nat]<br />

maize quiche squish queue shrew<br />

[mez] [k h iš] [skwwš] [k h yu] [šru]<br />

though cough rough bough through<br />

[ðo] [k h ]f] [rf] [baw] [›ru]<br />

heard word bird curd nerd<br />

[hcrd] [wcrd] [bcrd] [k h crd] [ncrd]<br />

103


104<br />

weird feared veered cared cord<br />

[wird] [fird] [vird] [k h ærd] [k h ]rd]<br />

meat great threat heart cart<br />

[mit] [gret] [›ret] [hart] [k h art]<br />

chair jeer share shear cheer<br />

[čær] [:9ir] [šær] [šir] [čir]<br />

wheel whale weigh who how<br />

[wil] [wæl] [we] [hu] [haw]<br />

witch which watch wretch wedge<br />

[wwč] [wwč] [wač] [reč] [we:9]<br />

coat code root rude read<br />

[k h ot] [k h od] [rut] [rud] [rid]<br />

laud loud laid led lewd<br />

[l]d] [lawd] [led] [led] [lud]<br />

knifed sighed prized healed shipped<br />

[nayft] [sayd] [p h rayzd] [hild] [šwpt]<br />

view dew do poor pour<br />

[vyu] [du] [du] [p h ur] [p h ]r]<br />

latch loaf roof tune pure<br />

[læč] [lof] [ruf] [t h un] [p h yur]<br />

car oar her hear whore<br />

[k h ar] [or] [hcr] [hir] [hor]<br />

George vague vast don't they're<br />

[:9or:9] [veg] [væst] [dont] [ðer]<br />

oath both moth mouth myth<br />

[o›] [bo›] [m]›] [maw›] [mw›]<br />

tit Tut tat toot tot<br />

[t h wt] [t h t] [t h æt] [t h ut] [t h at]<br />

who'd wood would wooed hood<br />

[hud] [wd] [wd] [wud] [hd]


2. music physics psychic sonic helix<br />

[myuzwk] [fwzwks] [sayk h wk] [sanwk] [hilwks]<br />

passion cashier cushion caption cashmere<br />

[p h æšcn] [k h æšir] [khšcn] [k h æpšcn] [k h æžmir]<br />

thistle thimble tumble dangle dinghy<br />

[›wscl] [›wmbcl] [t h mbcl] [dæõgcl] [diõgi]<br />

champagne cartoon Khartoum careen gangrene<br />

[šæmp h en] [k h art h un] [k h art h um] [k h crin] [gæõgrin]<br />

immune impugn impinge syringe obscene<br />

[wmyun] [wmp h yun] [wmp h wn:9] [scrwn:9] [absin]<br />

racial racer razor sugar quota<br />

[rešcl] [rescr] [rezcr] [šgcr] [k h woDc]<br />

pleasure pledger leisure azure seizure<br />

[p h ležcr] [p h le:9cr] [ležcr]/[ližcr] [æžcr] [sižcr]<br />

scissors vision fusion ocean mission<br />

[swzcrz] [vwžcn] [fyužcn] [ošcn] [mwšcn]<br />

beauty booty purely poorly pearly<br />

[byuDi] [buDi] [p h yurli] [p h ]rli] [p h erli]<br />

quitter water rider writer raider<br />

[k h wwDcr] [w]Dcr] [rayDcr] [rayDcr] [reDcr]<br />

joining whining singing finger languor<br />

[:9]yniõ] [wayniõ] [siõiõ] [fiõgcr] [læõgcr]<br />

cavil navel ravel gable squabble<br />

[k h ævcl] [nevcl] [rævcl] [gebcl] [skwabcl]<br />

Mary marry merry quarry query<br />

[mæri] [mæri] [meri] [k h wari] [k h wiri]<br />

numbskull zigzag homegrown deathblow shipshape<br />

[nmskl] [zwgzæg] [homgron] [de›blow] [šwpšep]<br />

outboard marshlands whiplash pastime pitchfork<br />

[awtb]rd] [maršlændz] [wwplæš] [p h æst h aym] [p h wčf]rk]<br />

cutthroat whetstone hangman onslaught crabgrass<br />

[kt›rot] [wetston] [hæõmæn] [ansl]t] [kræbgræs]<br />

105


106<br />

3. agree debris ennui Pawnee marquee<br />

[cgrí] [dcbrí] [anwí] [p]ní] [markí]<br />

angry money sunny gypsy litchi<br />

[æ´ õgri] [m´ni] [s´ni] [:9ípsi] [líči]<br />

survey (v) Bombay bouquet inveigh parfait<br />

[scrvé] [bambé] [boké] [wnvé] [parfé]<br />

survey (n) bomb bay Tuesday foray subway<br />

[s´rve] [bámbe] [túzde] [f]´re] [s´bwe]<br />

review canoe shampoo construe eschew<br />

[rcvyú] [kcnú] [šæmpú] [kcnstú] [cšú]<br />

preview igloo curfew yahoo Zulu<br />

[prívyu] [w´glu] [kérfyu] [yáhu] [zúlu]<br />

below outgrow plateau Bordeaux although<br />

[bcló] [awtgró] [plætó] [b]rdó] [ólðó]<br />

bellow meadow hobo cocoa depot<br />

[bélo] [médo] [hóbo] [kóko] [dípo]<br />

outcry (v) apply goodbye sky high untie<br />

[awtkráy] [cpláy] [gdbáy] [skayháy] [cntáy]<br />

outcry (n) ally cacti fish fry pigsty<br />

[áwtkray] [æ´lay] [kæ´ktay] [fw´šfray] [pw´gstay]<br />

soda tchotchke bwana chutzpah geisha<br />

[sódc] [čáčkc] [bwánc] [h´tspc] [géšc]/[gíšc]<br />

4. broccoli apogee fricassee symphony pedigree<br />

[brákcli] [æ´pc:9i] [frw´kcsi] [sw´mfcni] [pédcgri]<br />

shillelagh chianti bologna confetti Hatari<br />

[šcléli] [kiyánti] [bclóni] [kcnféDi] [hctári]<br />

guarantee bourgeoisie chimpanzee Tennessee jamboree<br />

[gærcntí] [buržwazí] [čwmpænzí] [tencsí] [:9æmbcrí]<br />

runaway Saturday ricochet protégée workaday<br />

[r´ncwe] [sæ´Dcrde] [ríkcše] [prótc:9e] [w]´rkcde]<br />

matinée San José Chevrolet Santa Fé overplay<br />

[mætcné] [sænhozé] [ševrclé] [sæn(t)cfé] [ovcrplé]


endevous residue peekaboo honeydew avenue<br />

[rándevu] [rézcdu] [píkcbu] [h´nidu] [æ´vcnu]<br />

Timbuktu kangaroo misconstrue overthrew hitherto<br />

[twmbktú] [kæõgcrú] [mwskcnstrú] [ovcr›rú] [hwðcrtú]<br />

mistletoe Mexico embryo cameo Scorpio<br />

[mw´sclto] [mékscko] [émbriyo] [kæ´ miyo] [sk]´rpiyo]<br />

fiæsko concerto soprano falsetto crescendo<br />

[fiyæ´ sko] [kcnčéDo] [scpráno] [f]lséDo] [krcšéndo]<br />

overflow (v) apropos status quo cheerio to-and-fro<br />

[ovcrfló] [æprcpó] [stæDcskwó] [čiriyó] [tucnfró]<br />

amplify rockaby occupy prophesy underlie<br />

[æ´mplcfay] [rákcbay] [ákycpay] [práfcsay] [´ndcrlay]<br />

subpoena agenda charisma pariah pagoda<br />

[scpínc] [c:9éndc] [kcrw´zmc] [pcráyc] [pcgóDc]<br />

5. apostrophe Menomini Penelope fraternity telegraphy<br />

[cpástrcfi] [mcnáncmi] [pcnélcpi] [frctérncDi] [tclégrcfi]<br />

Ypsilanti kamikaze Cincinnati insincerely poison ivy<br />

[wpsclæ´ nti] [kamckázi] [swnscnæ´Di] [wnscnsírli] [p]yzcnáyvi]<br />

pistachio Arapahoe embroglio adagio portfolio<br />

[pcstæ´ šiyo] [cræ´pcho] [embróliyo] [cdážiyo] [p]rtfóliyo]<br />

armadillo Filipino virtuoso Sacramento lucky fellow<br />

[armcdw´lo] [fwlcpíno] [vcrčuwózo] [sækrcménto] [lkifélo]<br />

Arabia azalea Bulgaria et cetera America<br />

[crébiyc] [czéliyc] [bclgæ´riyc] [etséDcrc] [cmérckc]<br />

hullabaloo Kalamazoo Tippecanoe<br />

[hclcbclú] [kæl̀ m̀ zú] [twpckcnú]<br />

107


108<br />

APPENDIX B: PHONOLOGICAL RULES<br />

1. a. All intervocalic voiceless stops become voiced.<br />

b. Voiceless stops become voiced when intervocalic.<br />

c.<br />

d.<br />

e.<br />

2. a. Nontense vowels in the final syllable of a word are stressed when they are followed by<br />

two or more consonants.<br />

b. Nontense vowels become stressed when followed by two or more consonants in the<br />

final syllable of a word.<br />

c. [–TENSE] ÷ [+STRESS] / _____________ # C n<br />

2<br />

3. a. Delete all final consonants when the following word begins with a consonant.<br />

b. Consonants become zero when final and when the following word begins with a<br />

consonant.<br />

c. C ÷ Ø / _____________ C #<br />

4. a. Reduce all unstressed vowels to schwa.<br />

b. Unstressed vowels become schwa.<br />

c. [–STRESS] ÷ [c]


5. a. Palatalize all alveolar stops before [y].<br />

b. Alveolar stops become palatal before [y].<br />

c.<br />

d.<br />

e.<br />

6. a. Devoice all final fricatives.<br />

b. Fricatives become voiceless when final (before #).<br />

c.<br />

d.<br />

e.<br />

7. a. Aspirate all initial voiceless stops.<br />

b. Voiceless stops become aspirate when initial (after #).<br />

c.<br />

109


110<br />

d.<br />

e.<br />

8. a. Nasalize all vowels before a nasal consonant.<br />

b. Vowels become nasal before nasal consonants.<br />

c. V ÷ [+NASAL] / _______ [C, +NASAL]<br />

9. a. A lax vowel in the antepenultimate syllable of a word is stressed.<br />

b. Nontense vowels become stressed in antepenultimate syllables.<br />

c. [–TENSE] ÷ [+STRESS] / _______ C n<br />

0 V C n<br />

0 V C n<br />

0 #<br />

10. a. Palatalize all alveolar stops before [y] when they are preceded by a vowel or when they<br />

are initial.<br />

b. Alveolar stops become palatal before [y] when they are preceded by a vowel or by #.<br />

c.<br />

d.<br />

e.


1. Data.<br />

APPENDIX C: SLASH–DASH NOTATION<br />

ROOT MEANING EXAMPLES<br />

/skrwb/ write scribble /skrwb+cl/ [skrwbcl]<br />

script /skrwb+t/ [skrwpt]<br />

/fræg/ break fragment /fræg+ment/ [frægment]<br />

refract /ri+fræg+t/ [rifrækt]<br />

2. First Set of Rules.<br />

a. [bt] ÷ [pt]<br />

b. [gt] ÷ [kt]<br />

3. Revision One.<br />

4. Revision Two.<br />

5. Revision Three.<br />

[b] ÷ [p] / _________ [t]<br />

[g] ÷ [k] / _________ [t]<br />

111


112<br />

APPENDIX D: PHONOLOGY PROBLEM<br />

Data in phonetic transcription from the language Hip:<br />

SINGULAR PLURAL MEANING<br />

tip tiben girl<br />

pit piden boy<br />

kip kiben child<br />

pik pigen police<br />

tab taben teacher<br />

bid biden dogs<br />

gip giben car<br />

dag dagen cat<br />

tap _____ house<br />

___ giden lions<br />

1. What are the stop phonemes in Hip? Justify your answer with minimal pairs.<br />

2. What is the phonemic form for children?<br />

3. What is the phonetic form for houses?<br />

4. What is the phonemic form for lions?<br />

5. State the rules which accounts for the phonetic differences between the singular and the plural<br />

forms where they occur?<br />

6. What is the morpheme for PLURAL?<br />

7. What is the morpheme for SINGULAR?


APPENDIX E: MORPHOLOGY PROBLEM<br />

Consider the following phonetic transcriptions and translations of Blatin:<br />

pelam I wash nores you work katim I jump<br />

pelat he washes noret he works katis you jump<br />

pelabas you washed norebam I worked katibam I jumped<br />

pelabat he washed norebas you worked katibat he jumped<br />

pelabim I will wash norebis you will work katibim I will jump<br />

pelabis you will wash norebit he will work katibit he will jump<br />

Identify the following morphemes:<br />

first person (I) ______________________<br />

second person (you) ______________________<br />

third person (he) ______________________<br />

present tense ______________________<br />

past tense ______________________<br />

future tense ______________________<br />

What do the following mean:<br />

pelas ______________________<br />

norebim ______________________<br />

How does one say the following in Blatin:<br />

He will wash. ______________________<br />

I work. ______________________<br />

He jumps. _____________________<br />

113


114<br />

APPENDIX F: ENGLISH VOWEL SHIFT<br />

1. e [–HIGH, –LOW, –BACK, +TENSE] [beð] [sen] [eksplen]<br />

(bathe) (sane) (explain)<br />

æ [–HIGH, +LOW, –BACK, –TENSE] [bæ›] [sænwDi] [eksplænctori]<br />

(bath) (sanity) (explanatory)<br />

2. o [–HIGH, –LOW, +BACK, +TENSE] [noz] [fon] [telcskop]<br />

(nose) (phone) (telescope)<br />

a [–HIGH, +LOW, +BACK, +TENSE] [nastrcl] [fanwk] [telcskapwk]<br />

(nostril) (phonic) (telescopic)<br />

3. i [+HIGH, –LOW, –BACK, +TENSE] [slip] [mitcr] [ridim]<br />

(sleep) (meter) (redeem)<br />

e [–HIGH, –LOW, –BACK, –TENSE] [slept] [metrwk] [ridempšcn]<br />

(slept) (metric) (redemption)<br />

4. u [+HIGH, –LOW, +BACK, +TENSE] [luz] [gus] [fud]<br />

(lose) (goose) (food)<br />

] [–HIGH, –LOW, +BACK, –TENSE] [l]st] [g]sliõ] [f]dcr]<br />

(lost) (gosling) (fodder)<br />

**************<br />

5. ay [–HIGH, +LOW, +BACK, +TENSE] [wayd] [layn] [wgnayt]<br />

(wide) (line) (ignite)<br />

w [+HIGH, –LOW, –BACK, –TENSE] [ww›] [lwnicr] [wgwšcn]<br />

(width) (linear) (ignition)<br />

6. aw [–HIGH, +LOW, +BACK, +TENSE] [saw›] [cbawnd] [profawnd]<br />

(south) (abound) (profound)<br />

[–HIGH, +LOW, +BACK, –TENSE] [sðcrn] [cbndcnt] [profndcDi]<br />

(southern) (abundant) (profundity)


(1) Root /æg/ ‘do’:<br />

APPENDIX G: ENGLISH MORPHOLOGY<br />

/PHONOLOGICAL FORM/ [PHONETIC FORM] SPELLING<br />

a. /æg + ent/ > [e:9cnt] agent<br />

1. Vowel Shift: æ > e in certain contexts<br />

sanity/sane; profanity/profane; explanatory/explain; gratitude/grateful<br />

2. Velar Softening: g > j in certain contexts<br />

rigor/rigid; regal/regicide; allegation/allege; analogous/analogize<br />

b. /æg + ent + I/ > [e:9cnsi] agency<br />

president/presidency; democrat/democracy; pirate/piracy; regent/regency<br />

c. /æg + t/ > [ækt] act<br />

regal/direct; fragment/refract; segment/bisect; pigment/depict<br />

d. /æg + t + wv/ > [æktwv] active<br />

e. /æg + t + wv + wti/ > [æktwvcDi] activity<br />

f. /æg + t + wv + wti + z/ > [æktwvcDiz] activities<br />

g. /wn + æg + t + wv/ > [wnæktwv] inactive<br />

h. /æg + t + wcn/ > [ækšcn] action<br />

relate/relation; devote/devotion; omit/omission; complete/completion<br />

I. /trænz + æg + t + wcn + æl/ > [trænzækšcncl] transactional<br />

j /ri + æg + t + ]r + z/ > [riæktcrz] reactors<br />

(2) Root /reg/ ‘rule’:<br />

a. /reg + ent/ > [ri:9cnt] regent<br />

1. Vowel Shift: e > I in certain contexts<br />

serenity/serene; severity/severe; delicacy/delicious; metric/meter<br />

2. Velar Softening: g > j in certain contexts<br />

rigor/rigid; regal/regicide; allegation/allege; analogous/analogize<br />

b. /reg + ent + I/ > [ri:9cnsi] regency<br />

c. /di + reg + t/ > [dcrekt] direct<br />

d. /di + reg + t + wcn + z/ > [dcrekšcnz] directions<br />

e. /wn + reg + ul + ær + wti + z/ > [wregyulærwDiz] irregularities<br />

regular/regulate; tabular/tabulate; circular/circulate; particular/particulate<br />

115


116<br />

(3) Root /fræg/ ‘break’:<br />

a. /fræg + ment/ > [frægmcnt] fragment<br />

b. /fræg + wl/ > [fræ:9cl] fragile<br />

c. /ri + fræg + t/ > [rifrækt] refract<br />

(4) Root /leg/ ‘law’:<br />

a. /leg + æl/ > [ligcl] legal<br />

b. /leg + ws + let + wcn/ > [le:9cslešcn] legislation<br />

c. /wn + leg + wtwm + et/ > [wlc:9wDcmct] illegitimate<br />

(5) Root /leg/ ‘choose’:<br />

a. /I + leg + ebwl/ > [elc:9cbcl] eligible<br />

b. /I + leg + t + wcn/ > [ilekšcn] election<br />

c. /leg + end + æri/ > [le:9cndæri] legendary<br />

(6) Root /seg/ ‘cut’:<br />

a. /seg + ment/ > [segmcnt] segment<br />

b. /seg + t + wcn/ > [sekšcn] section<br />

c. /dis + seg + t/ > [daysekt] dissect<br />

(7) Root /pwg/ ‘paint’:<br />

a. /pwg + ment/ > [pwgmcnt] pigment<br />

b. /di + pwg + t/ > [dipwkt] depict<br />

c. /pwg + t + or + I + æl/ > [pwktoricl] pictorial<br />

(8) Root /mæg/ ‘great, more’:<br />

a. /mæg + swm + æl/ > [mækscmcl] maximal<br />

b. /mæg + ws + ter + I + æl/ > [mæ:9cstericl] magisterial<br />

c. /mæg + or/ > [me:9cr] major<br />

(9) Root /]g/ ‘increase’:<br />

a. /]g + ment/ > []gment] augment<br />

b. /]g + t + wcn/ > []kšcn] auction<br />

c. /wn + ]g + ur + et/ > [wn]gyuret] inaugurate<br />

(10) Root /pæg/ ‘fasten, agree’:<br />

a. /pæg + ent/ > [pæ:9cnt] pageant<br />

b. /wn + pæg + t/ > [wmpækt] impact<br />

c. /pro + pæg + et/ > [prapcget] propagate


CHAPTER THREE: SYNTAX<br />

3.1 LINGUISTIC ARGUMENTATION REVISITED<br />

Linguistics, like all sciences, is concerned with explaining natural phenomena, that is, things which<br />

occur naturally in the world and which people can perceive with their senses. The particular<br />

phenomenon investigated in <strong>linguistic</strong>s is language. Linguists look at all human languages that<br />

naturally occur in the world and attempt to understand and describe their properties. One property<br />

that linguists have discovered is that all natural languages consist of an infinite number of sentences<br />

which are constructed in specific ways following specific rules. For example, all the sentences in this<br />

paragraph are English sentences constructed correctly in terms of the rules of English grammar. The<br />

area of <strong>linguistic</strong>s that is specifically concerned with sentence structure is called SYNTAX.<br />

It is possible to look at the structure of sentences and provide a variety of descriptions to account for<br />

the way those sentences are formed. These various descriptions are actually hypotheses about how<br />

sentences are constructed, and like all scientists, linguists must justify their hypotheses with<br />

independent, objective evidence. Let us consider an example of what such evidence looks like.<br />

3.1.1 LINGUISTIC ARGUMENTATION: SENTENCE TYPES<br />

In most English classes, teachers say that there are three types of complete sentences in English.<br />

There are statements like She is careful, questions like Is she careful, and commands like Be careful,<br />

as well as other examples like the following:<br />

(1) a. Statements: She is careful. That man will try to win. They don’t drive too fast.<br />

b. Questions: Is she careful? Will that man try to win? Don’t they drive too fast?<br />

c. Commands: Be careful. Try to win. Don’t drive too fast.<br />

English teachers also point out that all English sentences must have a subject, which is usually the<br />

person or thing that performs the action in the verb. For example, the subjects for the statements and<br />

questions in (1) are the italicized phrases in (2).<br />

(2) a. Statements: She is careful. That man will try to win. They don’t drive too fast.<br />

b. Questions: Is she careful? Will that man try to win? Don’t they drive too fast?<br />

When we consider the commands in (1c), it appears that they have no subjects. Generally, English<br />

teachers say that the subject of all commands is an understood you. In other words, (1c) is<br />

understood as follows:<br />

(3) Commands: (You) be careful. (You) try to win. (You) don’t drive too fast.<br />

Actually, the statement, “the subject of all commands is an understood you,” is a hypothesis, and like<br />

all hypotheses, it must be justified with evidence. When asked to justify this particular hypothesis<br />

about commands, people often assert that commands are directed at the person (or persons) one is


118<br />

talking to and that such a person is referred to with the pronoun you. The pronoun for the speaker,<br />

called the FIRST PERSON, is I; the pronoun for the person spoken to, the addressee, called the<br />

SECOND PERSON, is you. Since commands are addressed to the second person, the subject must<br />

be the second person pronoun, you.<br />

While this seems logical, it is not proof because it relies on the judgement and opinion of the person<br />

making the assertion about the data. It is subjective. Since different people can view the same<br />

phenomenon in different ways, what is needed as proof of the above description is independent,<br />

objective evidence – evidence that is not based on the way in which a particular person views the<br />

data.<br />

To see how we can support a hypothesis with objective evidence, consider first the following<br />

sentences paying particular attention to the italicized words which are called REFLEXIVE<br />

PRONOUNS:<br />

(4) a. I see myself.<br />

b. The little girls dressed themselves.<br />

c. Mary voted for herself.<br />

Notice that the reflexive pronouns refer back to the subject, that is, in (4a) myself refers back to I, in<br />

(4b) themselves refers back to the little girls, and in (4c) herself refers back to Mary. In fact, if the<br />

reflexive pronoun does not agree with the subject, then the sentence is ungrammatical as follows:<br />

(5) a. *I see yourself. (lack of agreement in person, first person versus second person)<br />

b. *The little girls dressed herself. (lack of agreement in number, singular versus plural)<br />

c. *Mary voted for himself. (lack of agreement in gender, female versus male)<br />

Given the above, we can make the following statements about reflexive pronouns in English.<br />

(6) a. Reflexive pronouns occur after the main verb and refer back to the subject.<br />

b. Reflexive pronouns must agree with the subject in person, number, and gender.<br />

Returning to the issue of commands, notice that the only reflexives that are possible in a command<br />

are the second person reflexive pronouns, yourself and yourselves:<br />

(7) a. Dress yourself/yourselves.<br />

b. *Dress myself/himself/herself/ourselves/themselves.<br />

Since reflexive pronouns must agree with the subject in person (cf. (6b)) and since the only reflexive<br />

pronouns possible in commands are second person, then the subject of a command must be second<br />

person, that is, the addressee(s) or you. This argument constitutes independent, objective evidence<br />

for the assertion, “the subject of all commands is an understood you.” Notice that all native speakers<br />

of English unconsciously know the facts listed in (6) even if they have never heard the term reflexive


pronoun. We know that is correct because native speakers utter sentences like (4) and never utter<br />

ones like (5).<br />

Like other scientists, linguists look for more than one argument to support their hypotheses; therefore,<br />

let us explore the matter further.<br />

Consider next tag questions, in which the subject of the main sentence is repeated in a question<br />

tagged onto a statement, such as the following:<br />

(8) a. He didn’t do it, did he?<br />

b. They will go, won’t they?<br />

c. *She wasn’t there, was he?<br />

d. *I’ll be invited, won’t they?<br />

Notice that tag questions after a command must contain the second person pronoun you; hence, the<br />

subject of a command must be an understood you.<br />

(9) a. Dress yourself, won’t you (please)?<br />

b. Don’t bother me, will you?<br />

c. *Dress yourself, won’t he?<br />

d. *Don’t bother me, will she?<br />

As a third proof, consider idioms like the following and notice that the POSSESSIVE PRONOUNS<br />

(in italics) must agree with the subject of the sentence; if they don’t the sentence is ungrammatical:<br />

(10) a. She gave the children her full attention.<br />

b. The man lost his temper.<br />

c. *She gave the children my full attention.<br />

d. *The man lost your temper.<br />

Notice that idioms like the above can only contain second person possessive pronouns when they<br />

occur in commands; hence, the subject of commands must be second person or you:<br />

(11) a. Give the children your full attention.<br />

b. Don’t lose your temper.<br />

c. *Give the children my full attention.<br />

d. *Don’t lose her temper.<br />

The three arguments above provide justification for the hypothesis, “the subject of all commands is<br />

an understood you.” Such justification is not derived from the opinion of the person making the<br />

119


120<br />

assertion, that is, it is not subjective. Instead, it is derived entirely from the objective observation of<br />

facts about English sentences as they occur naturally in everyday speech. The arguments can be<br />

verified or falsified through additional examination of other data; therefore, they constitute<br />

independent evidence to support the hypothesis.<br />

3.1.2 LINGUISTIC ARGUMENTATION: PARTS OF SPEECH<br />

When trying to describe some aspect of syntactic structure, linguists always rely on independent<br />

criteria to support their analyses. Let us consider here another example with the following sentences:<br />

(12) a. John looks Italian.<br />

b. John speaks Italian.<br />

These two sentences appear to have the same structure, that is, they appear to be made up of the same<br />

types of phrases with the same parts of speech (noun, verb, etc.). In fact, native speakers know that<br />

the word Italian is used differently in the two sentences. We can prove that by examining other data<br />

like the following.<br />

(13) a. John looks very Italian.<br />

b. *John speaks very Italian.<br />

(14) a. *John looks fluent Italian.<br />

b. John speaks fluent Italian.<br />

Native speakers would agree that (13a) is grammatical, but (13b) is not, and that (14a) is<br />

ungrammatical while (14b) is perfectly well-formed. These facts indicate the word Italian is used<br />

differently in the two sentences. Specifically, in (12a) it functions as an adjective, while in (12b) it<br />

functions as a noun. Confirmation of this hypothesis comes from examining other words whose<br />

function is unquestioned (adjective or noun) and conjoining those words with Italian in the two<br />

contexts under investigation (after looks and speaks):<br />

(15) a. John looks tall, handsome, Jewish, and Italian (so he’s right for the part in the movie).<br />

b. John speaks Hebrew, Sanskrit, Italian, and several other languages.<br />

(16) a. *John looks Hebrew, Sanskrit, Italian, and several other languages.<br />

b. *John speaks tall, handsome, Jewish, and Italian.<br />

A linguist must take great care when examining data. It is easy to be mislead, which is why linguists<br />

search for as many arguments as they can. For example, consider the following:<br />

(17) a. John looks more Italian (than Bill).<br />

b. John speaks more Italian (than Bill).


Given these examples, it appears that Italian functions in the same way in the two sentences since<br />

both sentences allow the comparative more. Further examination of other comparative-type<br />

expressions reveals that, in fact, they are different as we have hypothesized:<br />

(18) a. *John looks too much Italian.<br />

b. John speaks too much Italian.<br />

(19) a. John looks too Italian (to play that part in the movie).<br />

b. *John speaks too Italian.<br />

The additional data indicate that the grammaticality of both examples in (17) is only an apparent<br />

falsification of our hypothesis that Italian functions differently in the two sentences in (12). There<br />

must be some other fact which makes both of the examples in (17) good. In those cases, it is because<br />

the comparative more can freely occur before both adjectives and nouns:<br />

(20) a. John is more handsome, educated, courteous, etc. (than Bill).<br />

b. John has more money, grandchildren, hair, etc. (than Bill).<br />

3.1.3 LINGUISTIC ARGUMENTATION: PHRASES<br />

Consider now one final example of <strong>linguistic</strong> argumentation using the following sentences:<br />

(21) a. My niece hit the bus stop.<br />

b. My niece heard the bus stop.<br />

c. My niece saw the bus stop.<br />

These sentences appear to involve the same succession of elements with only the verbs being<br />

different (hit, heard, and saw):<br />

(22) a. My niece - hit - the bus stop<br />

b. My niece - heard - the bus stop<br />

c. My niece - saw - the bus stop<br />

Other data, however, indicate that the structure of these sentences is quite different. The difference<br />

hinges on the way the word stop is analyzed. Notice that the word stop can be used either as a noun<br />

(This bus makes too many stops) or a verb (The bus stopped at the corner). When stop functions as<br />

a noun, other words can combine with it to form a COMPOUND, which is a phrase composed of two<br />

or more elements that act like a single unit (bus stop, mail box, hair dryer, time machine, etc.). When<br />

stop functions as a verb, it can be modified by an adverb (suddenly stop, quickly go, happily sing,<br />

easily succeed, etc.). Thus, in (21a), the word stop is a noun and part of the compound bus stop; in<br />

(21b), the word stop is a verb. Further, in (21c), either analysis is appropriate (noun or verb) so the<br />

example is ambiguous.<br />

121


122<br />

We can support this analysis of the sentences in (21) with data like the following:<br />

(23) a. *My niece hit the bus suddenly stop.<br />

b. My niece heard the bus suddenly stop.<br />

c. My niece saw the bus suddenly stop.<br />

(24) a. My niece hit both the mail box and the bus stop.<br />

b. *My niece heard both the mail box and the bus stop.<br />

c. My niece saw both the mail box and the bus stop.<br />

What the above sentences indicate is that, after the verb hit, the words bus and stop can form a<br />

compound. Sentence (24a) is grammatical because the word and connects two compound nouns<br />

(mail box and bus stop). On the other hand, sentence (23a) is ungrammatical because the word<br />

suddenly separates the two elements of what is supposed to be a compound (cf. *mail probably box,<br />

*hair thoroughly dryer, etc.).<br />

After the verb heard in (23b), the words bus and stop do not form a compound and the word stop is<br />

itself a verb. As a result, it can be modified by the adverb suddenly, and (23b) is grammatical. On<br />

other hand, (24b) is ungrammatical under the ordinary interpretation of the verb hear and the objects<br />

mail box and bus stop. Judgements of grammaticality are based on ordinary language in ordinary<br />

circumstances, i.e., ones in which mail boxes and bus stops do not talk or make noise by themselves<br />

though that is certainly imaginable. Significantly, (24b) only makes sense under such special<br />

circumstances.<br />

The example in (23c) is unambiguous allowing only the reading in which stop is a verb. As expected,<br />

(24c) is also unambiguous having only the opposite reading that involves conjoining two compound<br />

nouns (mail box and bus stop). Other data that support our analysis include the following:<br />

(25) a. The bus stop was hit by my niece.<br />

c. *The bus stop was heard by my niece. (Bus stops do not ordinarily make noise.)<br />

c. The bus stop was seen by my niece. (unambiguous; stop must be a noun)<br />

(26) a. *It was the bus that my niece hit stop. (Elements of a compound cannot be separated.)<br />

b. It was the bus that my niece heard stop.<br />

c. It was the bus that my niece saw stop. (unambiguous; stop must be a verb)


(27) a. *My niece hit the busses stop. (The first element in a compound cannot be plural.)<br />

b. My niece heard the busses stop.<br />

c. My niece saw the busses stop. (unambiguous; stop must be a verb)<br />

All these examples add independent and objective support for our analysis of the phrase structure of<br />

the sentences in (21).<br />

3.1.4 LINGUISTIC ARGUMENTATION: STRATEGIES<br />

The three examples of <strong>linguistic</strong> argumentation given here should be viewed as a model for how to<br />

proceed in syntactic analysis. With these examples, we can formulate four strategies that can be used<br />

not only for <strong>linguistic</strong> analysis, but also for the analysis of any problem. Here is a summary of these<br />

four strategies.<br />

(28) Strategy One: Proceed in a step-wise fashion.<br />

It is often useful to scan data for patterns and regularities. If nothing appears to fall into place,<br />

try to find some commonality in a few examples in the data and proceed from that starting<br />

point to gradually incorporate other examples. Separate examples into mutually exclusive<br />

classes defined by the same types of criteria, so that each of your examples can only fall into<br />

one class. If some examples or some data don’t fit into the criteria, put them aside. It is better<br />

to leave some examples out of your analysis than to fit them in by relaxing your criteria.<br />

(29) Strategy Two: Search for generalizations.<br />

An analysis says very little if it does not lead to generalizations; therefore, your description of<br />

the data should result in a statement of some general principles. As above, it is better to leave<br />

some elements out of an analysis if their inclusion requires giving up a generalization or<br />

violating a well-established principle. Perhaps they are misunderstood cases or exceptions.<br />

An analysis that describes most of the data with interesting, contrastive generalizations is better<br />

than one that includes all the examples but says little of interest. A proposal that covers most<br />

concerns with well-supported data is better than one which tries to include everything by<br />

adding extra conditions and special cases.<br />

(24) Strategy Three: Make your hypotheses and your proposals data-driven.<br />

Your hypotheses and your proposals should arise from an examination of the data. Always<br />

begin with the examples and show how they drive your descriptive apparatus, terminology, and<br />

representations. Do not propose a hypothesis unless there are data to support it. Once you<br />

make a proposal make sure your representations (symbols, discussion, etc.) always follow it.<br />

The more you show how that data drive your proposals, the more robust your proposals will<br />

be, so much so that your proposals become inevitable.<br />

123


124<br />

(25) When presenting your hypothesis or making your proposal, consider your audience.<br />

You should choose your examples carefully, be consistent, and remove extraneous material<br />

from your description. You should only mention what is essential to make your point, and<br />

don’t introduce unnecessary and potentially distracting complexities. Your proposal should<br />

be presented in such a way that it can be easily followed and understood. Presentation matters.<br />

3.2 ORDERING CONSTRAINTS<br />

With the above discussion about the nature of <strong>linguistic</strong> argumentation in mind, let us now turn to<br />

the focus of this chapter, describing the structure of English sentences and developing a theory of<br />

syntax. We begin by noting that sentences are not random strings of words. Rather, the words of<br />

every sentence are arranged into units called PHRASES. Further, there is both a left to right<br />

constraint on the order of phrases, called LINEAR ORDER, and a top to bottom constraint on the<br />

order of phrases, called HIERARCHICAL ORDER. Learning English consists in part of mastering<br />

these ordering constraints. Failure to observe the constraints on linear order can lead to<br />

ungrammaticality at any time during language acquisition. In adult language, (30b) is<br />

ungrammatical; in child language, (31b) in ungrammatical for the meaning given.<br />

(30) a. The boy ran away.<br />

b. *Boy the away ran.<br />

(31) a. Daddy chair. (= That is daddy’s chair.)<br />

b. *Chair daddy. (= That is daddy’s chair.)<br />

In addition, failure to observe linear order can lead to meaning changes in both adult language (32)<br />

and child language (33).<br />

(32) a. John saw Bill.<br />

b. Bill saw John.<br />

(33) a. Mommy find. ( = Mommy come and find me; I’m hiding.)<br />

b. Find mommy. ( = I will find mommy.)<br />

Changes in hierarchical order often result in ambiguity, that is, multiple meanings. For example, the<br />

phrase the Spanish history books can be interpreted like the Spanish math books or like the art history<br />

books, as follows:


(34) a. John has the Spanish history books. (= the history books in Spanish)<br />

John has the Spanish math books.<br />

b. John has the Spanish history books. (= the books on Spanish history)<br />

John has the art history books.<br />

As we noted above, SYNTAX is the area of <strong>linguistic</strong>s that is specifically concerned with sentence<br />

structure, including the linear and hierarchical ordering of phrases. Formally, a PHRASE is a word<br />

or group of words that functions as a unit, which means that the language treats it as a whole. Phrases<br />

are identified by one or more of three syntactic processes mentioned in the Chapter One and reviewed<br />

here.<br />

3.2.1 TESTING HYPOTHESES: REFERENCE, OMISSION, PLACEMENT<br />

REFERENCE is a binding relationship between phrases. Some phrases get their meaning only from<br />

identification with other phrases. For example, in John hurt himself, the reflexive pronoun himself<br />

gets its meaning from its identification with John. We say himself refers to or is bound to John, and<br />

the relationship between the two is an instance of reference. Reference occurs in simple sentences<br />

like (35), in complex sentences like (36), and between sentences like (37) and (38).<br />

(35) a. The painter cut himself.<br />

(The phrase himself refers to the phrase the painter.)<br />

b. The painters painted each other.<br />

(The phrase each other refers to the phrase the painters.)<br />

(36) a. The portrait of himself that Rembrandt liked the most is the one he painted last.<br />

b. After the children finished dinner, they brushed their teeth.<br />

125


126<br />

(37) a. Impressionist painters seem to use more blue than expressionist painters.<br />

b. At least, I think they do.<br />

(The phrase they refers to the phrase impressionist painters; the phrase do refers to<br />

the phrase use more blue)<br />

(38) a. The children should not be playing with the paints.<br />

b. Why did you give them them?<br />

(the first them refers to the children; the second them refers to the paints)<br />

OMISSION is the deletion of a phrase. Repeated occurrences of phrases may be left out. In such<br />

cases, the omitted phrase is understood to be identical to the given phrase. For example, one can say<br />

John likes apples more than he likes bananas or John likes apples more than bananas.<br />

PLACEMENT is the occurrence of a phrase in a particular position. For example, the adverb phrase<br />

readily can be placed either before or after the verb it modifies: John readily accepted or John<br />

accepted readily; however, it cannot be placed at the beginning of a sentence: *Readily, John<br />

accepted.<br />

The three syntactic processes of reference, omission, and placement are possible because sentences<br />

are organized into phrases. The sentences of every human language contain phrases. Furthermore,<br />

phrase structure is a feature of the earliest sentences used by children regardless of the language they<br />

are learning. The exact character of phrases varies from language to language, but there is no known<br />

language which lacks phrase structure. Therefore, phrase structure is not an arbitrary convention;<br />

it must be rooted in human biology.<br />

3.2.2 LANGUAGE AND MEMORY<br />

The biological origins of phrase structure become clear when one examines the nature of human<br />

memory. It is a well–known fact that human beings have very limited SHORT TERM MEMORY<br />

(STM), which is the immediate memory for new information, such as a telephone number just<br />

received from the operator. This contrasts with our virtually limitless LONG TERM MEMORY<br />

(LTM), which is the storage and recall of information that is not new, such as one’s mother’s maiden<br />

name.<br />

Generally, STM is thought to be limited to about seven (±2) bits of information. STM can be<br />

facilitated by organizing information into units called CHUNKS. For example, the string of numbers<br />

in (39a) is much more readily recalled when given as (39b).<br />

(39) a. 1–4–9–2–2–0–0–1–1–7–7–6–1–9–9–7<br />

b. 1492 – 2001 – 1776 – 1997


Given the reality of the chunk in psychological studies and the phrase in <strong>linguistic</strong> studies, it seems<br />

plausible to derive (40).<br />

(40) The sentences of a natural language consist of phrases because human STM requires<br />

organizing a string of words into chunks to facilitate processing.<br />

In short, a phrase is a chunk of a sentence. Syntax is the study of phrases. A linguist specifies phrase<br />

structure by examining the units that participate in reference, omission, and placement. This<br />

methodology is theory–independent; in fact, this is the method by which linguists develop theories<br />

of grammar. We can see this if we examine the development of grammatical theory in this century,<br />

specifically, the development from traditional grammar to structural grammar to generative grammar.<br />

3.3 TRADITIONAL AND STRUCTURAL GRAMMAR<br />

The oldest grammatical model in western civilization is TRADITIONAL GRAMMAR, a<br />

grammatical model that has evolved from the language studies of the Greeks and Romans. Such<br />

grammars contain definitions like (41).<br />

(41) A SENTENCE is a structured expression consisting minimally of a SUBJECT and a<br />

PREDICATE. The subject specifies the topic of the sentence, and the predicate specifies what<br />

is asserted of the topic. Predicates always contain a VERB, which is a word that serves to<br />

express an action, occurrence or state of being; sometimes predicates also contain an OBJECT,<br />

which specifies the person or thing directly affected by the action defined in the verb. Since<br />

they must at least contain a verb, predicates are also referred to as VERB PHRASES. Subjects<br />

and objects are phrases that contain a NOUN, which is the name of a person, place, or thing,<br />

and a DETERMINER (DET), which is a word like the, this, or that.<br />

According to these definitions, a sentence like (42a) might be graphically represented by the TREE<br />

DIAGRAM (42b).<br />

(42) a. The passengers obey the stewardess.<br />

b.<br />

127


128<br />

While (42b) appears to be a fairly adequate representation of the phrases in (42a), there are problems.<br />

The first concerns an auxiliary or helping verb like must when it appears in a similar sentence like<br />

The passengers must obey the stewardess. (41) does not tell us what to do with it, in particular, it<br />

does not tell us whether an auxiliary is part of the SUBJECT node or the SENTENCE node or the<br />

VERB PHRASE node. This is important because we would like to be able to devise an explicit set<br />

of rules that describe the phrase structure of all English sentences. Since the left to right order of the<br />

elements in a sentence must be considered, we have three possibilities for connecting an auxiliary<br />

(AUX) with the rest of the sentences. We can represent the choices as follows, where the dotted lines<br />

indicate the possible attachments of AUX:<br />

(43) a. The passengers must obey the stewardess.<br />

b.<br />

If AUX is part of the SUBJECT, then the tree diagram for an English sentence is (44a), and the<br />

PHRASE–STRUCTURE RULES (PS–RULES) that describe English sentences are (44b), where<br />

the arrow can be interpreted as ‘consists of.’<br />

(44) a.<br />

b. (1) SENTENCE ÷ SUBJECT + VERB PHRASE<br />

(2) SUBJECT ÷ DET + NOUN + AUX<br />

(3) VERB PHRASE ÷ VERB + OBJECT<br />

(4) OBJECT ÷ DET + NOUN


If AUX is part of the VERB PHRASE, then the tree diagram for an English sentence is (45a), and<br />

the PS–RULES that describe English sentences are (45b).<br />

(45) a.<br />

b. (1) SENTENCE ÷ SUBJECT + VERB PHRASE<br />

(2) SUBJECT ÷ DET + NOUN<br />

(3) VERB PHRASE ÷ AUX + VERB + OBJECT<br />

(4) OBJECT ÷ DET + NOUN<br />

Lastly, if AUX is part of the SENTENCE, then the tree diagram for an English sentence is (46a), and<br />

the PS–RULES that describe English sentences are (46b).<br />

(46) a.<br />

b. (1) SENTENCE ÷ SUBJECT + AUX + VERB PHRASE<br />

(2) SUBJECT ÷ DET + NOUN<br />

(3) VERB PHRASE ÷ VERB + OBJECT<br />

(4) OBJECT ÷ DET + NOUN<br />

Traditional grammarians were not concerned much with the objective justification of the statements<br />

they made about grammar. The choice between analyses like the above was often, quite simply, a<br />

matter of opinion. All modern theories of grammar take a very different point of view. All modern<br />

theories of <strong>linguistic</strong>s (those of the twentieth century) attempt to ground their analyses in terms of<br />

129


130<br />

structural principles which can be justified, that is, proven. The further into the twentieth century one<br />

gets in the development of grammatical theory, the more stringent the requirement for proof becomes.<br />

To determine which of the above sets of rules is correct, we can use the processes of reference,<br />

omission, and placement. Consider first (44), the hypothesis that AUX is part of SUBJECT. A<br />

well–known fact about English is that subjects and objects can be replaced with pronouns like they,<br />

them, she, her, etc. The use of pronouns is very common in language: by replacing a phrase with a<br />

pronoun we do not have to keep repeating the whole phrase. Instead of saying The stewardess told<br />

the passengers that the passengers had to obey the stewardess, we say The stewardess told the<br />

passengers that they had to obey her. Rules of reference tell us what they and her refer to.<br />

Furthermore, specific pronouns must be used in specific positions: subjects must be replaced with<br />

pronouns like I, he, she, we, they, etc., and objects must be replaced with pronouns like me, him, her,<br />

us, them, etc. Thus, alongside of The passengers must obey the stewardess, we have sentences like<br />

(47), but none like (48).<br />

(47) a. They must obey her.<br />

b. She must obey them.<br />

(48) a. *Them must obey she.<br />

b. *Her must obey they.<br />

Following (44), we produce a fully grammatical sentence when we attempt to substitute the<br />

SUBJECT node, which contains the AUX, and the OBJECT node with the appropriate pronouns:<br />

(49) a. [The passengers must] obey [the stewardess].<br />

b. [They] obey [her].<br />

However, if the nouns in SUBJECT and OBJECT position of (44) are reversed as in (50a), then<br />

substitution of SUBJECT and OBJECT with pronouns produces the ungrammatical (50b).<br />

(50) a. [The stewardess must] obey [the passengers].<br />

b. *[She] obey [them]. (cf. She obeys them).<br />

The ungrammaticality of (50b) tells us that the analysis in (44) is wrong. If the rules were correct,<br />

then we would not get an ungrammatical sentence when we applied them in various circumstances.<br />

We therefore must reject (44). Intuitively, (44) seems incorrect for another reason. Subjects and<br />

objects appear to be the same kinds of phrase; yet, (44) claims that AUX is part of SUBJECT.<br />

Clearly, AUX can never be part of OBJECT: *They obey the stewardess must. If subjects and objects<br />

are the same kinds of phrase, we ought to be able to get AUX in either. As a result, we must reject<br />

(44) which means that our alternatives are (45) or (46). To help us choose between (45) and (46),<br />

let us consider the following data:


(51) a. Generally the passengers must obey the stewardess.<br />

b. *The generally passengers must obey the stewardess.<br />

c. The passengers generally must obey the stewardess.<br />

d. The passengers must generally obey the stewardess.<br />

e. *The passengers must obey generally the stewardess.<br />

f. *The passengers must obey the generally stewardess.<br />

g. The passengers must obey the stewardess generally.<br />

(52) a. *Strictly the passengers must obey the stewardess.<br />

b. *The strictly passengers must obey the stewardess.<br />

c. *The passengers strictly must obey the stewardess.<br />

d. The passengers must strictly obey the stewardess.<br />

e. *The passengers must obey strictly the stewardess.<br />

f. *The passengers must obey the strictly stewardess.<br />

g. The passengers must obey the stewardess strictly.<br />

These data indicate that there are two broad classes of adverbs in English: SENTENCE ADVERBS<br />

like generally that modify the whole sentence, and MANNER ADVERBS like strictly that modify<br />

the verb phrase. Only the diagram in (46) and the rules in (46b) capture this classification, that is,<br />

we arrive at a very efficient characterization of the two classes of adverbs with the following logic:<br />

(53) a. If the rules in (46b) specify sentence structure, then we can say that sentence adverbs<br />

occur around the three major sentential elements, namely, the four positions indicated<br />

by the pound sign as follows:<br />

SENTENCE ÷ # SUBJECT # AUXILIARY # VERB PHRASE #<br />

131<br />

b. If the rules in (46b) specify verb phrase structure, then we can say that manner<br />

adverbs occur either at the beginning or the end of the verb phrase, namely, the two<br />

positions indicated by the pound sign as follows:<br />

VERB PHRASE ÷ # VERB + OBJECT #<br />

The diagram and rules in (45) do not lead to such an efficient characterization. In short, the<br />

PLACEMENT of adverbs proves what the units in sentences are. Furthermore, these rules predict<br />

that (54a) is grammatical, and that (54b) is not.<br />

(54) a. The passengers must generally strictly obey the stewardess.<br />

b. *The passengers must strictly generally obey the stewardess.<br />

There are sentences that corroborate the choice of (46). Notice that the VERB PHRASE node in<br />

(46a) is substantiated by its possible OMISSION in a sentence like The passengers must obey the<br />

stewardess if the pilot orders them to (obey the stewardess). If the VERB PHRASE included AUX,<br />

as in (45), then repetition of the VERB PHRASE would produce *The passengers must obey the


132<br />

stewardess if the pilot orders them to must obey the stewardess. Again, following the rules logically<br />

we see that they are confirmed or rejected by the sentences that result, specifically whether the rules<br />

lead to other sentences that are grammatical or ungrammatical.<br />

As final confirmation of (46), consider the use of do it in a sentence like The pilot told the passengers<br />

that they must obey the stewardess and actually had no trouble convincing them to do it (do it = obey<br />

the stewardess). Again, if the AUX were part of the VERB PHRASE, then do it would have to mean<br />

must obey the stewardess not obey the stewardess. Indeed, there is no pronominal form like do it in<br />

English that stands for a VERB PHRASE that contains an AUXILIARY. If one existed, we would<br />

have evidence supporting (45).<br />

As a result of these considerations, we prove that English sentences contain three basic units;<br />

therefore, the analysis in (46) is justified. Stated this way, a grammatical description is not a matter<br />

of opinion. It is a matter of fact. Furthermore, we attain a very high level of adequacy by basing our<br />

description on the concept of phrase, since phrase structure is the result of chunking, and chunking<br />

is the result of biological constraints on human memory. We have a direct connection between the<br />

nature of man and the nature of grammar.<br />

As we saw in the Chapter One, there are three levels of adequacy that a linguist can attain in<br />

grammatical analysis. The first level, called OBSERVATIONAL ADEQUACY, is attained when<br />

the facts are noted. The second level, called DESCRIPTIVE ADEQUACY, is attained when the<br />

facts are described with generalized principles or rules, e.g., (46). The third and highest level, called<br />

EXPLANATORY ADEQUACY, is attained when those principles are related to the nature of the<br />

language apparatus of man. As a linguist moves from observational to explanatory adequacy, an ever<br />

higher level of generality is reached. At the highest level, linguists begin to relate individual<br />

languages like English to human language in general and, therefore, to offer a real explanation for<br />

<strong>linguistic</strong> phenomena. In attempting to attain explanatory adequacy, a linguist is also able to separate<br />

out what is arbitrary and language specific, from what is predictable in terms of the nature of the<br />

human language apparatus (the brain and the vocal and auditory organs).<br />

Over a period of many years, traditional grammar gave way to STRUCTURAL GRAMMAR<br />

because the latter could provide more descriptively adequate characterizations of natural language.<br />

Traditional definitions such as those in (41) have been replaced by PS–RULES like those in (46b).<br />

Thus far, we have justified a model of English which contains tree <strong>structures</strong> like (46a). However,<br />

there are improvements that can be made to (46) that will allow us to attain a higher level of<br />

descriptive adequacy. Notice that any word or group of words that can be a subject of an English<br />

sentence can also be an object (with a meaning change, of course):<br />

(55) a. The handsome prince rescued the beautiful princess.<br />

b. The beautiful princess rescued the handsome prince.<br />

(56) a. The new tenor from Italy met the members of the orchestra.<br />

b. The members of the orchestra met the new tenor from Italy.


A categories like VP (Verb Phrase) or NP (Noun Phrase) is a STRUCTURAL CATEGORY. It<br />

abbreviates a class of syntactic <strong>structures</strong> that can occur in certain positions in a syntactic<br />

HIERARCHY. On the other hand, a category like subject or object is a FUNCTIONAL<br />

CATEGORY, which names what function or role a particular structure plays in the sentence. Thus,<br />

in (56a) and (56b), the new tenor from Italy is structurally a noun phrase (NP), consisting of the noun<br />

tenor preceded by the determiner the and the adjective new, and followed by the prepositional phrase<br />

from Italy; functionally, this NP is the subject of (56a) and the object of (56b).<br />

This additional information about English syntax, and more specifically about the sentence in (42a),<br />

can be expressed if the tree diagram in (42b) is replaced with the one in (57), an entirely structural<br />

representation (S = Sentence; NP = Noun Phrase; VP = Verb Phrase; N = Noun; V = Verb):<br />

(57)<br />

3.4 TENSE AND THE INTERNAL STRUCTURE OF SENTENCES<br />

The representation in (57) describes the structure of the sentence The passengers must obey the<br />

stewardess. Naturally, our rules must do more than describe the structure of just one sentence since<br />

there is an infinite number of sentences in every language. Also, some VP do not contain direct<br />

objects and some NP do not contain determiners:<br />

(58) a. The passengers can deplane.<br />

b. Passengers must obey stewardesses.<br />

These two facts can easily be accounted for by stipulating that direct object NPs and determiners are<br />

optional. Borrowing the parenthesis notation we used in phonology to indicate optional elements,<br />

we revise the PS-Rules as follows (cf. (46b)):<br />

133


134<br />

(59) a. S ÷ NP + AUX + VP<br />

b. VP ÷ V + (NP)<br />

c. NP ÷ (DET) + N<br />

Other facts about English cannot be so easily accommodated. Consider the following sentences<br />

which appear to contain no AUX:<br />

(60) a. The passenger obeys the stewardess.<br />

b. The passenger obeyed the stewardess.<br />

We might say that such sentences indicate that the AUX should be optional in (59a); however, this<br />

fails to account for the fact that the sentences in (60) have a tense. Example (60a) is in the present<br />

tense (PRS); (60b) is in the past tense (PST). Furthermore, there can be only one tense in each<br />

sentence:<br />

(61) a. The passenger does obey the stewardess.<br />

b. The passenger did obey the stewardess.<br />

c. *The passenger does obeys the stewardess.<br />

d. *The passenger did obeyed the stewardess.<br />

e. *The passenger does obeyed the stewardess.<br />

f. *The passenger did obeys the stewardess.<br />

Summarizing, it is clear that all native speakers of English know the following facts about tense and<br />

the internal structure of sentences:<br />

(62) a. Every sentence (S) must contain a tense.<br />

b. There is only one tense in each S.<br />

c. If there is no auxiliary verb, then tense is marked on the main verb (cf. (60)).<br />

d. If there is an auxiliary verb, then tense is marked on the auxiliary verb (cf. does in<br />

(61a) and did in (61b)).<br />

Of course, the knowledge that native speakers have of these facts is unconscious. That much is clear<br />

because they observe the facts when they produce new sentences, that is, they never say things like<br />

(61c) - (61f). The facts are part of the grammar of English that native speakers have internalized.<br />

The facts exist whether or not there are people around who want to write the facts down as we are<br />

trying to do. When we write down the grammatical facts, all we are doing is bringing those facts to<br />

consciousness. We are not making them up.


Additional facts about tense that native speakers know are the following:<br />

(63) a. Two tense markers are signaled by a change in the shape of the verb: present tense<br />

(PRS) and past tense (PST).<br />

[1] The passenger obeys the stewardess.<br />

[2] The passenger obeyed the stewardess.<br />

[3] The passenger does obey the stewardess.<br />

[4] The passenger did obey the stewardess.<br />

b. One tense marker is signaled by the bare verb stem alone: the imperative tense (IMP),<br />

which is used to express commands.<br />

[1] Obey the stewardess.<br />

[2] Do (not) obey the stewardess.<br />

c. Two other tense markers are signaled by preceding the main verb with an auxiliary<br />

verb called a MODAL: future tense (FUT) and conditional tense (CND).<br />

[1] The passenger will/shall obey the stewardess.<br />

[2] The passenger could/should obey the stewardess.<br />

Since a tense is obligatory and a modal is optional, we should replace (59) with the following where<br />

TP stands for Tense Phrase:<br />

(64) a. S ÷ NP + TP + VP<br />

b. VP ÷ V + (NP)<br />

c. NP ÷ (DET) + N<br />

d. TP ÷ (MOD) + T<br />

e. T ÷ {PRS, PST, IMP, FUT, CND}<br />

In PS–Rules like the above, the PARENTHESES indicate OPTIONAL ELEMENTS and the<br />

BRACES (CURLY BRACKETS) indicate ALTERNATIVE ELEMENTS. These notations, of<br />

course, are the same ones we saw above in Chapter Two in P-Rules (Phonological Rules).<br />

The symbol T stands for TENSE, which is used here as a special abbreviation for the various TIME<br />

and MODE/MOOD distinctions in English. The five tenses in English include the three TIME<br />

distinctions, PRESENT (PRS), PAST (PST), and FUTURE (FUT), and the two MODE/MOOD<br />

135


136<br />

distinctions, CONDITIONAL (CND), and IMPERATIVE (IMP). We have examples like the<br />

following:<br />

(65) a. She lives in a dorm. (lives is present tense, PRS)<br />

b. She lived in a dorm. (lived is past tense, PST)<br />

c. She will live in a dorm . (will is future tense, FUT)<br />

d. She should live in a dorm. (should is conditional mode, CND)<br />

e. Live in a dorm. (live is imperative mode, IMP)<br />

(66) a. She goes to college. (goes is present tense, PRS)<br />

b. She went to college. (went is past tense, PST)<br />

c. She will go to college. (will is future tense, FUT)<br />

d. She should go to college. (should is conditional mode, CND)<br />

e. Go to college. (go is imperative mode, IMP)<br />

Notice that some of these distinctions are not realized as individual words, but as inflectional endings,<br />

that is, changes in the shape of the verb (lives, lived, etc.). Further, in English, inflections aren’t<br />

always an identifiable element at the end of a word: they can appear as modifications of the root or<br />

as nothing at all. For example, went is the past tense of go; will is the modal will in future time;<br />

should is the modal shall in the conditional mode.<br />

In English, a MODAL (MOD) is a word that colors the meaning of the main verb and expresses<br />

notions like possibility (can, may), necessity (must, should), potentiality (might, could), likelihood<br />

(may), obligation (must, should), and so on. The most common modals are can, could, shall, should,<br />

will, would, may, might, must, do, does, did, etc. These words are actually composite forms, e.g.,<br />

does is PRS of do, did is PST of do, etc.<br />

Here is a summary and some other examples of regular and irregular verbs in various tenses:<br />

(67) PRS Singular PRS Plural PST Singular PST Plural FUT<br />

a. obeys obey obeyed obeyed will obey<br />

b. lives live lived lived will live<br />

c. goes go went went will go<br />

d. becomes become became became will become<br />

e. writes write wrote wrote will write<br />

f. dives dive dove/dived dove/dived will dive<br />

g. is are was were will be<br />

h. does do did did will do<br />

i. has have had had will have


3.5 DETERMINERS AND THE INTERNAL STRUCTURE OF NOUN PHRASES<br />

Continuing our investigation of the phrase structure of English, let us now consider the internal<br />

structure of noun phrases like the following (the NPs are in italics):<br />

(68) a. Passengers obey stewardesses.<br />

b. Those passengers obey these stewardesses.<br />

c. All the passengers obey all the stewardesses.<br />

d. All the nervous passengers obey the stewardesses.<br />

(69) a. *Those all passengers obey the stewardesses.<br />

b. *Nervous the passengers obey the stewardesses.<br />

Again, it is clear that native speakers unconsciously know a variety of facts about the internal<br />

structure of NP because they will utter sentences like (68), but not ones like (69). Among other facts,<br />

native speakers know that the left to right order of the elements in an NP must be as follows:<br />

(70) NP ÷ (QNT) + (DET) + (ADJ) + N<br />

In this rule, QNT stands for quantifier (a word like all, both, or each ), DET stands for determiner<br />

(a word like the, this/these, or a/an), and ADJ stands for adjective (a word like nervous, tall, or<br />

happy). Native speakers know which category (QNT, DET or ADJ) each word belongs to because<br />

they always put them in the proper order which, again, is why they utter sentences like (68) but not<br />

ones like (69). They also know exactly how the categories differ from each other, for example, that<br />

only adjectives can be compared:<br />

(71) a. tall, taller tallest<br />

b. nervous, more nervous, most nervous<br />

c. all, *aller, *allest<br />

d. these, *theser, *thesest<br />

In addition to the above, native speakers also know that there are two broad categories of nouns in<br />

English: PROPER NOUNS, which refer to a specific entity (Heather, Daisy, Mary, Michigan,<br />

<strong>Oakland</strong> University, etc.), and COMMON NOUNS, which are general in their reference (heather,<br />

daisy, girl, state, education, university, etc.).<br />

The major distinction between the two categories of nouns is that proper nouns cannot be specified<br />

by a determiner (*this Michigan, *that <strong>Oakland</strong> University, etc.), whereas common nouns can (this<br />

state, that university, etc.). Further, an overt determiner is obligatory for singular COUNT NOUNS,<br />

which are nouns that can be counted (one daisy, two daisies, many daisies, etc.), but optional for<br />

plural count nouns and for non-count nouns or MASS NOUNS, which can not be counted (*one<br />

heather, *two heathers, *many heathers, etc.). Here is a summary of the relevant facts (notice the<br />

capital letters on the proper nouns):<br />

137


138<br />

(72) Noun Class Overt Determiner No Overt Determiner<br />

a. Proper: *I like the Heather and the Daisy. I like Heather and Daisy.<br />

b. Singular Count: I like the daisy. *I like daisy.<br />

c. Plural Count: I like the daisies. I like daisies.<br />

d. Non-count (Mass): I like the heather. I like heather.<br />

As we can see above, proper nouns are usually capitalized in writing; however, that “clue” is missing<br />

in speech. Still, the entire classification of nouns given here is unconsciously known by all native<br />

speakers, which is why they only use determiners when they should in speech. Remember that young<br />

children do not have access to things like the rules for capitalization; they speak the language long<br />

before they learn to read and write. The unconscious knowledge they acquire is our focus. Our<br />

grammar must account for that knowledge to be descriptively adequate.<br />

3.5.1 ABSTRACT ELEMENTS: Ø<br />

As the above description indicates, the use of determiners in noun phrases is complex and subtle.<br />

People learning English as a second language (ESL) often make mistakes in using determiners,<br />

putting them in where they shouldn’t occur and leaving them out where they should occur. This is<br />

especially true of people whose native language has no obligatory determiners, such as Japanese.<br />

Adult native speakers of English never make such mistakes. They don’t say things like *I saw child<br />

or *I live in the Michigan. Importantly, the reason that native speakers do not say such things is not<br />

because they have never heard anyone say such things. The number of sentence is infinite so a<br />

speaker could not have heard everything. The reason that native speakers use determiners correctly<br />

is because they have unconsciously internalized the facts about determiners described above. They<br />

unconsciously know the rules. They have not memorized all the good sentences.<br />

Students new to <strong>linguistic</strong>s are often overwhelmed by the multitude of facts that linguists discuss<br />

about grammar. But students need to remember that they unconsciously already know those facts.<br />

For example, they know not to say things like *I saw child or *I live in the Michigan. Students do<br />

have to learn the terminology that linguists use, such as “proper noun,” but they do not have to learn<br />

the facts; they only need to learn how to recall the facts. Thus, a major focus of this book is on<br />

learning to ask the right questions to become consciously aware of the facts one already knows<br />

unconsciously. This is not as easy as it sounds. If it were simple, linguists would have uncovered<br />

all the facts of grammar long ago.<br />

As we have observed, the basic distinction in the above classification of nouns is that proper nouns<br />

cannot be specified by a determiner and common nouns can:<br />

(73) a. *I like the Heather and the Daisy.<br />

b. I like the heather and the daisy.


The grammar we are developing must specify the distinction between proper and common nouns in<br />

some explicit way. Most grammars of English account for that distinction by postulating a<br />

phonologically null determiner, represented by the symbol Ø. Grammarians argue that this<br />

determiner is present when it appears that a common noun does not have a determiner. The full<br />

analysis is as follows:<br />

(74) a. I like the heather. [ay layk ðc heðcr]<br />

b. I like Ø heather. [ay layk heðcr] - phonetically equivalent to (74f)<br />

c. *I like heather. (ungrammatical because there is no determiner before heather)<br />

d. *I like the Heather.<br />

e. *I like Ø Heather. (ungrammatical because of the presence of Ø before Heather)<br />

f. I like Heather. [ay layk heðcr] - phonetically equivalent to (74b)<br />

The example in (74c) is ungrammatical because heather, a common noun, requires Ø when there is<br />

no overt determiner (cf. (74b)). The example in (74e) is ungrammatical because Heather, a proper<br />

noun, cannot be specified by a determiner, including the phonologically empty determiner Ø (cf.<br />

(74f)). The bottom line here is that our grammar must account for the fact that native speakers know<br />

the difference between thousands of proper nouns like Heather, Daisy, Bill, John, Grace, Jack,<br />

Dawn, etc., and thousands of common nouns like heather, daisy, bill, john, grace, jack, dawn, etc.<br />

Note that (74b) and (74f) are spoken and heard in exactly the same way. Postulating Ø enables us<br />

to distinguish the two types of nouns formally.<br />

Summarizing, the above analysis says this: proper nouns never have a determiner; common nouns<br />

always have a determiner; if a common noun lacks an overt determiner, then Ø is present.<br />

The above analysis extends to possessives (Heather’s, women’s, her, etc.) and to quantifiers (all,<br />

both, etc.). In English, an NP can contain either a possessive or a determiner, but not both – another<br />

fact that native speakers unconsciously know. Further, an NP can only contain a quantifier if it also<br />

contains a determiner. Consider the following, where POS represents the possessive suffix<br />

(apostrophe) and notice that POS is in the same position as determiners, including Ø:<br />

(75) a. all the children<br />

b. all Ø children<br />

c. *all POS children (*all’s children)<br />

d. *Heather the children<br />

e. *Heather Ø children<br />

f. Heather POS children (Heather’s children)<br />

g. *her the children<br />

h. *her Ø children<br />

i. her POS children (her children)<br />

139


140<br />

A possessive pronoun like her is actually a composite of she and the possessive morpheme (POS),<br />

just as went is a composite of go and the past tense morpheme (PST) and did is a composite of do and<br />

the past tense morpheme (PST) as we saw above.<br />

Again, all the above facts about noun phrases must be known by native speakers, at least<br />

unconsciously, because they know which nouns can be specified by determiners and which can’t.<br />

It is worth repeating here that the facts are facts in the grammar of English. Students often think that<br />

grammatical facts and rules are things that teachers make up. That is incorrect. Languages have<br />

grammar whether or not there are teachers to talk about the grammar. There is no human language<br />

that does not have a grammar because languages require grammar. Grammar is, as we noted in the<br />

beginning of this chapter, a biological necessity.<br />

What we are trying to do here is to account for the grammatical facts native speakers know in the<br />

most generalized way possible, an objective of all science. All of the revisions we have made in our<br />

formal description of English are DATA-DRIVEN: we observe the data, discover the facts in<br />

English grammar, and then adjust our rules in such a way that our written, descriptive grammar<br />

accounts for the data and the facts (see Chapter One, Section 1.2). Linguists postulate revisions in<br />

their grammatical descriptions and rules only when there are data to support those revisions.<br />

Now notice that possessives themselves are noun phrases; in the following examples people is<br />

modified by the adjective wealthy and donations is modified by the adjective generous:<br />

(76) a. the people’s generous donations<br />

b. those wealthy people’s generous donations<br />

c. those very wealthy people’s very generous donations<br />

d. their very generous donations<br />

Furthermore, the possessive marker (the apostrophe) is a separate element affixed to the end of the<br />

entire possessive noun phrase:<br />

(77) a. the people’s donations [the people]’s donations<br />

b. the people in that room’s donations [the people in that room]’s donations<br />

c. *the people’s in that room donations<br />

Lastly, as we have seen, determiners and possessives cannot specify the same noun:<br />

(78) a. those donations<br />

b. the people’s donations<br />

c. their donations<br />

d. *those the people’s donations *the people’s those donations<br />

e. *those their donations *their those donations<br />

In other words, determiners and the possessive occupy the same position in noun phrases. A<br />

quantifier like all can only be followed by a determiner (all the books, *all’s books), and an ordinary


noun like John or child can only be followed by the possessive marker (John’s book, that child’s<br />

books, *John the book, *that child the books (cf. (75)). The facts require us to modify (70), repeated<br />

here as (80), to (81).<br />

(80) NP ÷ (QNT) + (DET) + (ADJ) + N<br />

(81) NP ÷ ( {QNT, NP} ) + (DET) + (ADJ) + N<br />

A cluster like ( {QNT, NP} ) in above rule, means that either a QNT or an NP can optionally occur<br />

in the first position of an NP.<br />

Continuing to explore the internal structure of noun phrases, we note that noun phrases can contain<br />

whole sentences:<br />

(82) a. John heard a rumor.<br />

b. John heard (that) Mary kissed Bill.<br />

(83) a. A rumor upset John.<br />

b. That Mary kissed Bill upset John.<br />

The direct object of (82a) is a rumor, and the direct object of (82b) in the sentence Mary kissed Bill,<br />

which must be a sentence because it contains a tensed verb (kissed).<br />

To accommodate all the varieties of NP that occur in the above examples, we require the following<br />

PS-Rule for NP:<br />

(84) NP ÷<br />

The rule (84) says that an NP has one of two forms: either a noun, which can be preceded by some<br />

optional elements, or a sentence. Thus, (84) is an abbreviation for all the rules in (85).<br />

(85) a. NP ÷ QNT + DET + ADJ + N<br />

b. NP ÷ QNT + DET + N<br />

c. NP ÷ QNT + ADJ + N<br />

d. NP ÷ QNT + N<br />

e. NP ÷ DET + ADJ + N<br />

f. NP ÷ DET + N<br />

g. NP ÷ ADJ + N<br />

h. NP ÷ N<br />

i. NP ÷ S<br />

Again, observe that the left to right order in PS–RULES is crucial: it expresses the fact that the NP<br />

in (86) are grammatical while those in (87) are not:<br />

141


142<br />

(86) a. the new tenor from Italy<br />

b. the tenor<br />

c. tenors from Italy<br />

(87) a. *the from Italy new tenor<br />

b. *tenor the<br />

c. *from Italy tenors<br />

3.5.2 PHRASE STRUCTURE RULES: FIRST PROPOSAL<br />

Expanding our corpus, we can allow for more complex phrases such as those in (88) if we make the<br />

additions to our rules specified in the right-hand column (note that (88d) is ambiguous).<br />

(88) a. He will not go. Add a negative (NEG) to the TP rule.<br />

b. Mary quickly finished the assignment. Add an adverb (ADV) to the VP rule.<br />

c. They elected Bill president. Add a second NP to the VP rule.<br />

d. The thief hit the lady with the hat. Add a PP (Prepositional Phrase) to both<br />

VP rule and NP rule.<br />

These new examples gives us the set of PS–Rules (89).<br />

(89) a. S ÷ NP + TP + VP<br />

b. TP ÷ (MOD) + T + (NEG)<br />

c. VP ÷ (ADV) + V + (NP) + ( {NP, PP} )<br />

d. PP ÷ P + (NP)<br />

e. NP ÷<br />

f. T ÷ {PRS, PST, FUT, CND, IMP}<br />

These rules will generate the appropriate structure for the sentence in (88). In particular, they account<br />

for the ambiguity of (88d): if the PP with the hat is what the thief used to hit the lady, then the PP<br />

is part of the VP (89b); if the PP with the hat describes what the lady is wearing, then the PP is part<br />

of the direct object NP (89d). As before, the arrow in these rules is an instruction to rewrite the<br />

symbol to the left as the symbol or symbols to the right. Parentheses indicate optional constituents;<br />

braces indicate alternative constituents. The only function of the plus symbol in PS–RULES is to<br />

mark a clear separation of constituents; it is, therefore, optional. Note again that the left to right order<br />

of constituents is an entirely empirical matter; once a particular order is determined from an<br />

examination of possible phrase <strong>structures</strong>, it cannot be changed unless there is other evidence


indicating that the change is justified. The rules in (89) are not a complete list of all the PS–Rules<br />

for English; for example, notice that conjunctions like and are not included. These rules will be<br />

added to and modified as we proceed.<br />

The name given to grammars formulated in terms of phrase structure rules and tree diagrams is<br />

PHRASE STRUCTURE GRAMMARS; the theory behind them, as we have indicated, is called<br />

STRUCTURAL GRAMMAR. In developing a set of phrase structure rules like (89), a linguist will<br />

attempt to reach the highest level of generality possible, which means proposing rules that describe<br />

the greatest number of cases (out of the infinite number possible) in the simplest way. For example,<br />

postulating tense as occurring after MOD and before V accounts most simply for did play (do PST<br />

play) and played (PST play). Considering only a sentence like they played, one might conclude that<br />

an analysis which places tense to the left of V is unnecessarily abstract. But remember, a grammar<br />

attempts to account for all possible sentences. In English, the tense marker (PRS, PST, etc.) is<br />

affixed to the closet verb, what ever that is (modal or main verb).<br />

In addition to identifying all of the major constituents of a sentence and indicating how these<br />

constituents are related to each other, phrase structure grammars offer a formal way of formulating<br />

such functional notions as subject and object. Notice that in a tree diagram like (57) some of the<br />

nodes in the tree immediately dominate others, that is, are directly above them. For example, the S<br />

node immediately dominates an NP node, a TP node, and a VP node; the VP node immediately<br />

dominates a V node and an NP node; and so on. Using this relationship of immediate dominance,<br />

one can define the subject of a sentence as the NP node which is immediately dominated by S, and<br />

the object as the NP node which is immediately dominated by VP. Similarly, the predicate can be<br />

defined as the VP immediately dominated by S, and the main verb can be defined as the V<br />

immediately dominated by VP. Linguists also use “family relationships” to describe positions in<br />

phrase structure, for example, NP, TP and VP are sisters as well as daughters of S.<br />

Such formal definitions are preferable to definitions like those in (41) because they are explicit, i.e.,<br />

they refer to specific entities standing in unique relationships. A definition like the direct object<br />

specifies the person or thing directly affected by the action defined in the verb, on the other hand, is<br />

not explicit and, therefore, raises many problems. For example, consider the direct objects in the<br />

following sentences:<br />

(90) a. The man will burn the money.<br />

b. The man will earn the money.<br />

Under phrase structure analysis, the sentences in (90) would be assigned to the constituent structure<br />

given in (91).<br />

143


144<br />

(91)<br />

This tree characterizes the object NP of both (90a) and (90b) in the same way. A comparison of the<br />

following sentences indicates that this characterization is correct.<br />

(92) a. How much money did the man burn?<br />

b. How much money did the man earn?<br />

(93) a. The money was burned quickly.<br />

b. The money was earned quickly.<br />

If there were something different about the occurrence of the NP the money in (90a) and (90b), one<br />

would not expect them to behave in the same way. But, the sentences in (92) and (93), and many<br />

others, show that they are, in fact, the same.<br />

Now, according to the definitions in (41), the NP the money in (90a) is the direct object because it<br />

specifies the thing directly affected by the action defined in the verb. This seems defensible. With<br />

regard to the NP the money in (90b), however, a problem arises, because it is difficult to conceive of<br />

the money as being directly affected by the action of earning. This problem becomes even greater<br />

for sentences like the following:<br />

(94) Sue earned a bad reputation.<br />

(95) John suffered a blow on the head.<br />

Generally speaking, this problem always arises when one attempts to describe language on the basis<br />

of definitions like those in (41). Another example occurs with the definition usually given to nouns,<br />

i.e., a noun is the name of a person, place, or thing. This definition combined with (41) leads to<br />

statements like A noun can be the name of a thing which is the topic of an expression. Such<br />

statements reveal little about English sentence structure. On the other hand, a description of a<br />

category like noun, formulated in terms of phrase structure grammar, will explicitly separate those<br />

items which are nouns from those which are not. For this reason, most linguists have abandoned<br />

definitions like those in (41) in favor of more rigorous and formal ways of characterizing sentence<br />

structure, such as those afforded by phrase structure grammar.


3.6 THE ENDOCENTRICITY CONSTRAINT<br />

PS-Rules like (89) and the structural diagrams they generate like (91) also allow us to begin to make<br />

some important generalizations about phrase structure. For example, notice that, in (91), the major<br />

phrases (NP, TP and VP) each dominate a category of the same type (N, T, and V, respectively). The<br />

technical term for this is ENDOCENTRICITY, which means that every constituent X must be<br />

dominated by a phrase of the same type XP, whatever X is. Further, every phrase XP must dominate<br />

an X. What that means, for example, is that noun phrases must contain nouns and verb phrases must<br />

contain verbs. We can formulate this Endocentricity Constraint as follows:<br />

(96) ENDOCENTRICITY CONSTRAINT.<br />

145<br />

a. Each XP must dominate one and only one X; each X must be dominated by one and<br />

only one XP. The constituent X is called the HEAD of the XP. The phrase XP is<br />

called the MAXIMAL PROJECTION of X.<br />

b. Each head X must dominate one and only one word or abstract category (PRS, PST,<br />

FUT, POS, Ø, etc.).<br />

The Endocentricity Constraint stipulates the following:<br />

(97) a. XP ÷ X<br />

b. *XP ÷ Y<br />

There are three constituents in (91) which do not obey the Endocentricity Constraint, DET, MOD and<br />

S. Implementing the Endocentricity Constraint for DET and MOD, we modify (91) as follows (we<br />

will consider S later in this chapter):<br />

(98)<br />

In the above representation, with the exception of S, every X is dominated by an XP, and every XP<br />

dominates X. Further, each head X dominates only one word or abstract category.


146<br />

It is important to note, at this point, that good scientific inquiry always seeks to uncover<br />

generalizations like the Endocentricity Constraint even when there are apparent exceptions such as<br />

S. Also, given the examples we have considered so far, it appears as though DP and MP are<br />

HEAD–ONLY constructions, that is, phrases that only can contain a head.<br />

Returning to our original example, we now have the following representation for The passengers do<br />

obey the stewardess:<br />

(99)<br />

Implementing the Endocentricity Constraint, we can now generalize the internal structure of phrases<br />

in our PS rules as follows:<br />

(100) a. S ÷ NP + TP + VP<br />

b. TP ÷ (MP) + T + (NEGP)<br />

c. VP ÷ (ADVP) + V + (NP) + ( {NP, PP} )<br />

d. PP ÷ P + (NP)<br />

e. NP ÷<br />

f. T ÷ {PRS, PST, FUT, CND, IMP}<br />

g. XP ÷ X<br />

Notice that the structure and rules above are more generalized than those we have had in the past,<br />

because the internal structure of phrases is now more generalized. In our investigation, there has<br />

been a gradual progression toward greater generality from (42b) to (57) to the representation and<br />

rules above. In fact, as we proceed in this chapter, we will uncover evidence supporting the principle<br />

that all phrases have the same internal structure.


3.7 THE LEXICON<br />

In order to generate a tree structure like (99) from rules like (100), our grammar must also contain<br />

a lexicon or dictionary of all the words in the language. We must have a way to ensure that words<br />

are inserted into the appropriate slots in structure, that is, that verbs are inserted under V, nouns under<br />

N, determiners under D, and so on. Recalling our use of features from phonology, let us propose a<br />

lexicon with SYNTACTIC FEATURE distinctions such as the following:<br />

(101) a. truth [+N] N=Noun<br />

b. explain [+V] V=Verb<br />

c. the [+D] D=Determiner<br />

d. from [+P] P=Preposition<br />

Some words can clearly function as more that one category:<br />

(102) a. love [+N; +V]<br />

b. patient [+N; +ADJ]<br />

c. swell [+N; +V; +ADJ]<br />

d. down [+N; +V; +ADJ; +P]<br />

Given feature specifications like (101) and (102), we ensure that words are inserted into tree<br />

<strong>structures</strong> with the following principle of lexical insertion:<br />

(103) For each X, freely insert a lexical item (word) with the feature specification [+X, ...].<br />

Given (103), only words with the feature [+X, ...] will be inserted into tree <strong>structures</strong> under the<br />

category X.<br />

In addition to ensuring that words are inserted under the appropriate category, we must also ensure<br />

that they are inserted into the appropriate environments (before and/or after the appropriate<br />

<strong>structures</strong>). For example, we must ensure that verbs which require a direct object (Transitive Verbs)<br />

are inserted into <strong>structures</strong> where an NP follows the verb, such as (99). Similarly, verbs which cannot<br />

have direct objects (Intransitive Verbs) should not be inserted into <strong>structures</strong> before an NP. Linguists<br />

call such restrictions CO-OCCURRENCE RESTRICTIONS. They stipulate the structural<br />

environments in which lexical items can occur. Adopting the formalism we used in phonology for<br />

environments, we have examples like the following (see the Rule Formalism on page 89):<br />

(104) a. obey [+V, +/___NP] Transitive Verb<br />

b. smile [+V, –/___NP] Intransitive Verb<br />

c. break [+V, ±/___NP] Transitive or Intransitive Verb<br />

These entries stipulate that a verb like obey can only be inserted into trees having a transitive<br />

structure, that is, a VP that dominates a V followed by an NP such as (99).<br />

147


148<br />

Using syntactic features like the above, we can make improvements in the rules in (100) to attain an<br />

even higher level of generality and descriptive adequacy. Consider the following examples of adverb<br />

phrases (ADVP) and adjective phrases (ADJP):<br />

(105) ADVP<br />

a. very beautifully<br />

b. as helpfully as Mary<br />

c. so much more skillfully than Mary<br />

(106) ADJP<br />

a. very beautiful<br />

b. as helpful as Mary<br />

c. so much more skillful than Mary<br />

Clearly, adverbs and adjectives are essentially the same type of syntactic category such that one can<br />

easily be turned into the other. The major difference, of course, is that ADVP modify verbs and<br />

ADJP modify nouns, facts which are directly expressed in the PS-Rules (100). Notice that ADVP<br />

is to the left of V and dominated by VP, while ADJP is to the left of N and dominated by NP. Given<br />

these relationships, it is clear that adverbs and adjectives are members of some larger category, which<br />

linguists call ADJUNCT or A. Implementing this observation, we can replace both ADVP and<br />

ADJP with AP, for ADJUNCT PHRASE. An adjunct is a modifier. The position of the AP in<br />

structure will determine whether it is functioning adverbially or adjectivally: in a VP, it will be<br />

adverbial; in an NP, it will be adjectival. Using features, let us say that adverbs are adjuncts that are<br />

non-adjectival and adjectives are adjuncts that are adjectival:<br />

(107) a. [+A, –ADJ] beautifully, helpfully, skillfully, happily, quickly, etc.<br />

b. [+A, +ADJ] beautiful, helpful, skillful, happy, quick, etc.<br />

c. [+A, ±ADJ] hard, fast, daily, etc.<br />

In a similar way, we do not need to specify both QP and NP in (100e) because quantifiers are a type<br />

of noun. In fact, sometimes the same word can function as either a quantifier noun or a nonquantifier<br />

noun. Consider the following (in the “a” examples, the italicized words function as<br />

quantifier nouns; in the”b” examples, as non-quantifier nouns):<br />

(108) a. Half the men were eliminated. (cf. All/both the men were eliminated)<br />

b. We cut the team in half. (cf. We cut the team into two groups.)<br />

(109) a. We made three times the profit. (cf. We made all the profit.)<br />

b. Times are hard. (cf. Decisions are hard.)<br />

(110) a. We made double the profit. (cf. We made twice the profit.)<br />

b. She is my double. (cf. She is my stand-in.)<br />

Quantifier nouns (all, both, etc.) and determiners are actually in complementary distribution with<br />

non-quantifier nouns (John, child, etc.) and the possessive suffix. Determiners can only be preceded


y quantifier nouns and POS can only be preceded by non-quantifier nouns. Consider again<br />

examples like the following:<br />

(111) NP DP HEAD<br />

a. all the books<br />

b. all Ø books<br />

c. *all POS books (*all’s books)<br />

d. *John the books<br />

e. *John Ø books<br />

f. John POS books (John’s books)<br />

Since a quantifier is a type of noun, we can replace ({QP, NP}) with just (NP) in the rule (100e); and,<br />

given the above discussion, we can also replace ADJP with AP in that rule. The new rule is as<br />

follows:<br />

(112) NP ÷<br />

Using features, we can distinguish individual common nouns and quantifiers in the following way:<br />

(113) a. [+N, –Q] book, girl, truth, group, decision, profit, etc.<br />

b. [+N, +Q] all, both, each, twice, etc.<br />

c. [+N, ±Q] half, time, double, etc.<br />

All the data taken together show that determiners, quantifiers, and possessives have the same<br />

function, namely, they specify nouns (this child, all those books, Mary’s decision, etc.). That<br />

indicates that they are members of a larger category, which linguists call SPECIFIERS.<br />

We can also use syntactic features to distinguish the major subcategories of nouns and pronouns as<br />

follows:<br />

(114) a. [+N, +COMMON] heather, jack, state, etc.<br />

b. [+N, –COMMON, –PRO] Heather, Jack, Michigan, etc.<br />

c. [+N, –COMMON, +PRO, +REFLEXIVE] herself, himself, itself, etc.<br />

d. [+N, –COMMON, +PRO, –REFLEXIVE] she, he, it, etc.<br />

Proper nouns ([+N, –COMMON, –PRO]) share many features with pronouns ([+N, –COMMON,<br />

+PRO]). Both subcategories of nouns cannot occur after quantifiers, determiners and adjectives or<br />

before PP:<br />

(115) a. *That happy Richard laughed.<br />

b. *A tall she married a short him.<br />

149


150<br />

We can account for these co-occurrence restrictions borrowing the formalism for redundancy rules<br />

in Chapter Two (cf. (46) on page 85):<br />

(116) a. [–COMMON] ÷ [–\NP__ ]<br />

b. [–COMMON] ÷ [–\DP__ ]<br />

c. [–COMMON] ÷ [–\AP__ ]<br />

d. [–COMMON] ÷ [–\__ PP]<br />

These redundancy rules state that all non-common nouns (proper nouns and pronouns) cannot occur<br />

after quantifiers, determiners, and adjectives or before PP.<br />

Given the Endocentricity Constraint, we can collapse the four redundancy rules above into one rule<br />

as follows:<br />

(117) [–COMMON] ÷ [–\ XP __, –\ __XP]<br />

This redundancy rule states that all non-common nouns cannot occur after or before any other type<br />

of phrase within an NP.<br />

3.8 A NOTE ON SCIENTIFIC INQUIRY<br />

In the preceding sections, we have discussed some attempts to develop an adequate theory of<br />

grammar beginning with traditional grammar and culminating in a version of structural grammar that<br />

reaches a high level of generality with the Endocentricity Constraint. Reviewing this, we can see<br />

how <strong>linguistic</strong>s has been able to deepen and broaden its characterizations of human language in an<br />

effort to attain ever higher levels of adequacy. The search for descriptively and explanatorily<br />

adequate models of grammar continues today.<br />

It is often dismaying to come to a discipline for the first time and find that it does not provide a<br />

succinct, unified, and fully justified theory. Linguistics is such a discipline; however, although there<br />

is no grammatical theory which is championed by every living linguist, the issues today are quite<br />

clearly drawn, and so are the objectives of research. The discovery of the grammatical facts<br />

themselves is much more significant than the details of particular representations of those facts.<br />

No matter what grammatical model is proposed, it must be able to provide a characterization of all<br />

sentences in such a way that it accounts for the native speaker’s knowledge of them. This involves,<br />

among other things, accounting for ungrammatical sentences in a principled way, that is, in a way<br />

which predicts that they will be ungrammatical. The facts to be accounted for are the same regardless<br />

of the theory invented to characterize them. The objective of the discipline is to provide a theory<br />

which will be consistent with the ever–expanding corpus of data. In this respect, <strong>linguistic</strong>s is no<br />

different from any other science. Consider, for example, the study of celestial objects.<br />

Astronomy is one of the oldest sciences. Even before 2000 B.C., crops were sowed according to the<br />

movements of the sun and moon. Modern theories of the universe which displace the earth from the


center are due to Copernicus (1473–1543). There have been many modifications over the centuries<br />

even to the point that separate areas of inquiry or methodology have been identified like radio<br />

astronomy, astrophysics, and spectroscopy. The discovery of pulsars, quasars, black holes, and other<br />

stellar phenomena has engendered modifications in existing theories of the universe. As our<br />

knowledge of the universe has expanded, the field of astronomy has expanded, and a number of<br />

distinct theories for a number of distinct issues have emerged, e.g., theories on the origin of the<br />

universe, the big bang theory, string theory, brane theory, and so on. In the process, the explanatory<br />

power of the combined theories has increased. The discovery of some new stellar phenomena never<br />

nullifies everything that precedes, that is, astronomy does not begin again from scratch. Rather,<br />

existing theories are appropriately modified or, if the phenomena are not understood, left entirely<br />

unmodified despite apparent conflicts or inconsistencies. It is always possible that putative<br />

exceptions are not exceptions at all, only misunderstood cases.<br />

People have been studying language almost as long as they have been speculating on the heavens.<br />

Terms like verb which form part of the theories described in this book were coined by ancient<br />

grammarians. However, it is only in the last fifty years or so that linguists have been concerned with<br />

many of the issues discussed in this book, in particular, those issues formulated here as the<br />

grammatical characterization problem and the grammatical realization problem. In short, students<br />

of <strong>linguistic</strong>s must understand that new models of characterization are inevitable as new data are<br />

discovered. During this evolution, the issues have become more clearly defined, and the<br />

characterizations have become more explanatorily adequate. More than anything else, this process<br />

and progress of scientific inquiry must be understood.<br />

In addition, students must understand that grammars are theories about language. In writing<br />

grammars, linguists attempt to describe observed phenomena, such as the different ways in which<br />

they observe native speakers using proper nouns and common nouns. Sometimes, the description will<br />

make use of abstract elements such as Ø postulated above. In this regard, linguists are no different<br />

from other scientists. For example, physicists postulate the existence of dark matter, that is,<br />

“invisible” matter, to account for abnormalities in the observed rotation of galaxies. No one has ever<br />

seen dark matter anywhere in the universe, just as no one has ever heard Ø. Nevertheless, scientists<br />

assume that these theoretical constructs exist so that they can account for the phenomena they do<br />

observe.<br />

In our discussion, various approaches to grammatical characterization are adopted, discussed, and<br />

either discarded or maintained as our inquiry proceeds. To some, this may seem to be a waste of<br />

time. Why not ignore the historical perspective and just discuss the right analysis? The answer is<br />

quite simple: there is no right analysis. There is only the analysis which covers the known facts at<br />

the present time. Furthermore, science sometimes takes one or even a few steps backwards, returning<br />

to an older theory once discarded and resurrecting it with modifications.<br />

Since our understanding of language is increasing all the time and analyses, consequently, can be<br />

expected to be falsified by newly discovered data, the most important thing to be learned is how to<br />

do grammatical analysis to begin with. This prepares students for the changes that are inevitable in<br />

so young an area of inquiry as formal <strong>linguistic</strong>s. Therefore, our focus must be on the methods and<br />

objectives of <strong>linguistic</strong> inquiry. At every stage in this inquiry, we will formulate hypotheses and<br />

151


152<br />

examine their consequences for the theory of language. This process of hypothesis development is<br />

common not just to <strong>linguistic</strong>s, but to scientific method in general.<br />

Everything said here about scientific inquiry applies to the analysis of problems that confront society,<br />

businesses, industry, government, and all other institutions and enterprises. As we noted in the<br />

Introduction, the problems facing today’s workers are complex and subtle, as difficult to solve as the<br />

nature of the human mind, language, and the universe. What we have done throughout this book is<br />

devise steps for breaking down problems into manageable parts, for making proposals that are robust<br />

and workable, for testing hypotheses, and for finding solutions that satisfy the most factors and<br />

constituents in the best way possible. Linguistic analysis has been our means to develop expertise<br />

in problem solving. At an abstract level, formulating a theory of language, which is our specific<br />

problem, is like all problems.<br />

3.9 X–BAR SYNTAX<br />

Returning to our main discussion, let us continue to explore the nature of an adequate theory of<br />

syntax. Thus far, our discussion has pivoted around the concept of SYNTACTIC UNIT. To find<br />

these units, we considered the three syntactic processes of REFERENCE, OMISSION, and<br />

PLACEMENT. We have the following definitions:<br />

(118) a. PHRASE: a word or group of words that functions as syntactic unit in<br />

REFERENCE, OMISSION, and/or PLACEMENT.<br />

b. HEAD: the minimal element of a phrase.<br />

A phrase whose head is a noun is a noun phrase; one whose head is a verb, a verb phrase; one whose<br />

head is a preposition, a prepositional phrase; and so on. The phrases we have examined in the<br />

sections above have been relatively simple. Consider now the following increasingly complex<br />

examples of noun phrases:<br />

(119) a. those paintings<br />

b. all those paintings<br />

c. all those paintings of landscapes<br />

d. all those stolen paintings of landscapes<br />

e. all those stolen paintings of landscapes of the Louvre’s<br />

f. all those recently stolen paintings of landscapes of the Louvre’s<br />

g. all those ten recently stolen paintings of landscapes of the Louvre’s<br />

h. all those ten recently stolen Impressionist paintings of landscapes of the Louvre’s on<br />

sale<br />

If we attempt to diagram the NP’s in (119) in accordance with the mechanisms we have so far<br />

developed for English phrase structure, we encounter a number of immediate problems that require<br />

a solution. The most difficult problem concerns the fact that both traditional and early structural<br />

grammar provide only the most meager structural framework for basic syntactic units. Quite clearly,<br />

we cannot suspend all the <strong>structures</strong> in (119h) , for example, from the same NP node. Such an


analysis ignores the fact that NP’s have internal hierarchical structure as well as internal linear<br />

structure. To see this, consider the simple NP in (120) provided by the rules developed so far.<br />

(120)<br />

A diagram like (120) leaves a number of important facts unaccounted for. First, note that we have<br />

examples like (121).<br />

(121) a. John saw those Spanish paintings, and Bill saw these Italian ones.<br />

b. John saw those Spanish paintings, and Bill saw these ____.<br />

The word ones in (121a) substitutes for the noun paintings indicating that paintings is an internal unit<br />

within its own phrase. That fact is accounted for by (120): paintings is under one node by itself, the<br />

N node. However, the same diagram cannot account for the gap in (121b). In this sentence, the gap<br />

stands for Spanish paintings which is not identified as a unit in (120). For Spanish paintings to be<br />

a unit the two elements, the AP (Spanish) and the N (paintings), must be under one node, separate<br />

from the DP (those) node. This means that a better diagrammatic representation of (120) is (122),<br />

where the "?" identifies the missing, as yet unlabeled, node.<br />

(122)<br />

This deficit in the internal structure of phrases has not gone unnoticed in modern grammatical<br />

analysis, and, in the 1970’s, a phrase structure framework was developed that ultimately came to be<br />

known as X–BAR SYNTAX. This theory replaces diagrams like (122) with ones like (123), in<br />

which progressively larger syntactic units of the same phrasal type are indicated by progressively<br />

higher primes; for example, N´ designates a larger unit than N. In the original version of this theory,<br />

primes were not used; rather a bar was placed over a symbol, e.g., N¯. Since bars are difficult to<br />

produce on most typewriters and many word processors, they are generally replaced with primes as<br />

follows:<br />

153


154<br />

(123)<br />

Notice that, in (123), Spanish paintings is contained in a separate node labeled N´. This node<br />

represents a separate, intermediate noun phrase level between N and NP. The representation claims<br />

that phrases, in particular, noun phrases, must have more internal hierarchical structure than the<br />

amount usually accorded them. One of the many examples that demands this is (121b) which<br />

contains a gap that stands for the unit Spanish paintings, represented by the N´ in (123). The<br />

representation in (123) replaces the "?" of (122) with a new intermediate noun phrase level and,<br />

accordingly, directly accounts for the gap in (121b). Basically, X–Bar syntax recognizes more<br />

syntactic levels than the two traditionally recognized, that is, more than just XP over X.<br />

Before continuing, a somewhat trivial matter should be mentioned – one which seems to help students<br />

read complicated phrase structure diagrams. In X–Prime (or X-Bar) notation, it is useful to line up<br />

all the head elements (XP, X´, X) in a straight vertical sequence making the location of the head of<br />

each separate phrase straightforward. Thus, the representation of (123) is (124).<br />

(124)<br />

Note that the X´ phrase is explicitly mentioned in a tree only if it branches; thus, N´ is mentioned but<br />

neither D´ nor A´ is. Also, for simplicity, we can represent tree diagrams like the above linearly as<br />

LABELED BRACKETS:<br />

(125) [ NP [ DP [ D those ] ] [ N´ [ AP [ A Spanish ] ] [ N paintings ] ] ]


Note that each bracket on the left is paired with one on the right beginning with the smallest units and<br />

proceeding to increasingly larger units. The following diagram illustrates which brackets are paired<br />

(first the X phrase, then the X´ phrase if there is one, and lastly the XP phrase):<br />

(126) ¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯<br />

¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯<br />

¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯ ¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯<br />

¯¯¯¯¯¯ ¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯ ¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯<br />

[ NP [ DP [ D those ] ] [ N´ [ AP [ A Spanish ] ] [ N paintings ] ] ]<br />

Returning to the main discussion, consider now a phrase like (127), which can have either of the two<br />

meanings indicated.<br />

(127) those Spanish teachers<br />

a. those teachers who are Spanish<br />

b. those teachers of Spanish<br />

In addition, we have the following examples:<br />

(128) a. those Spanish Braille teachers<br />

b. *those Braille Spanish teachers<br />

(129) a. John saw those Spanish math teachers, and Bill saw these ________.<br />

b. John saw those Spanish math teachers, and Bill saw these Italian ones.<br />

These phrases require that compound nouns like Braille teachers in (128a) and math teachers in<br />

(129) be contained under a separate N node, giving <strong>structures</strong> like the following:<br />

(130) (131)<br />

155


156<br />

The above representations contain the compound nouns Braille teachers and math teachers. In such<br />

compounds, the first element is actually the COMPLEMENT of the head, it completes it’s meaning:<br />

a Braille teacher is a person who teaches Braille; a math teacher is a person who teaches math. In<br />

these representations, both Braille teachers in (130) and math teachers in (131) are contained under<br />

one N´ node. Such representations account for the use of ones in examples like (129b). Observe also<br />

that these representations can account for the ambiguity of a phrase like (127). If it means (127a),<br />

then Spanish is a descriptive adjective and branches off the higher N´ if it means (127b), then<br />

Spanish is part of a compound and branches off the lower N´. Further, this analysis predicts that both<br />

should be able to occur together, and that is correct: those Spanish Spanish teachers is possible;<br />

where the first Spanish (an adjective phrase or AP) refers to origin, and the second Spanish (a noun<br />

phrase or NP) refers to language.<br />

These data indicate that the order of elements within an NP is fixed: SPECIFIERS must dominate<br />

ADJUNCTS and ADJUNCTS must dominate COMPLEMENTS. We have no examples like (132).<br />

(132) a. *(John met) those math Spanish teachers.<br />

b. *(John met) Spanish those teachers.<br />

c. *(John met) math Spanish those teachers.<br />

In the following two diagrams, only (133) is grammatical because the adjunct (AP) Spanish<br />

(indicating national origin) dominates the complement (NP) Spanish (indicating the language). In<br />

(134), the two constituents are reversed so the phrase is not grammatical (cf. *those math Spanish<br />

teachers).<br />

(133) (134) *


The data that we have observed and the facts that we have discovered indicate that the Endocentricity<br />

Constraint (96) must be expanded as follows:<br />

(135) ENDOCENTRICITY CONSTRAINT.<br />

a. Each XP must dominate one and only one X; each X must be dominated by one and<br />

only one XP. The constituent X is called the HEAD of the XP.<br />

b. Each head X must dominate one and only one word or abstract category (PRS, PST,<br />

FUT, POS, Ø, etc.).<br />

c. Between XP and X, multiple recursions of X´ are possible.<br />

d. Specifiers must dominate adjuncts; adjuncts must dominate complements.<br />

3.10 GENERALIZING PHRASE STRUCTURE: S AND NP<br />

While the revisions that we have implemented reach a much higher level of descriptive adequacy than<br />

the rules of traditional grammar, they still leave many generalizations unexpressed. For example, in<br />

every language, there are abundant instances of cross-categorial principles, that is, principles which<br />

spread over many different categories like sentences (S) and noun phrases (NP). Consider the<br />

following:<br />

(136) S: The people generously donate to that charity.<br />

NP: The people’s generous donations to that charity...<br />

(137) S: The barbarians suddenly destroyed the city.<br />

NP: The barbarians sudden destruction of the city...<br />

(138) S: John steadfastly refuses to do anything illegal.<br />

NP: John’s steadfast refusal to do anything illegal...<br />

(139) S The Mafia illegally shipped drugs into the country during June.<br />

NP: The Mafia’s illegal shipments of drugs into the country during June...<br />

Notice that in examples like (136) and for any given verb/noun pair like donate and donation, it is<br />

possible to substitute the same kinds of subjects (the people, Americans, etc.), the same kinds of<br />

complements (to that charity, to Detroit, etc.) and the same kinds of adjuncts (generous, generously,<br />

etc.). Some of these generalizations can be expressed by the principles we have formulated. For<br />

example, consider the following representations for the sentence and noun phrase in (136):<br />

157


158<br />

(140) S: The people generously donate to that charity.<br />

(141) NP: The people’s generous donations to that charity...


Given these <strong>structures</strong>, we can make the necessary generalizations about complements and adjuncts<br />

because they occupy exactly parallel positions. Both adjuncts generous and generously are<br />

dominated by an X´ over another X´; the complements to that charity follow the head X, which is<br />

dominated by an X´. Generalizations regarding the subjects, however, cannot be expressed, because<br />

the above diagrams do not completely match each other; in particular, there seems to be an extra VP<br />

node in (140). Furthermore, the symbol S does not obey the Endocentricity Constraint. We can solve<br />

these problems if we replace (140) with the following structure:<br />

(142) S: The people generously donate to that charity.<br />

The structure in (142) exactly parallels (141) so all relationships can be generalized between<br />

sentences and noun phrases. Just as DP (POSSESSIVE) specifies the head noun, TP (TENSE)<br />

specifies the head verb; the subjects of both <strong>structures</strong> is the phrase the people. Again, both adjuncts<br />

generous and generously are dominated by an X´ over another X´; the complements to that charity<br />

follow the head X, which is dominated by an X´.<br />

Essentially, (142) represents a sentence as a large verb phrase (VP), which is appropriate since the<br />

main constituent of a sentence is the verb.<br />

3.11 ADJUNCTS (MODIFIERS) AND COMPLEMENTS<br />

There is one remaining problem with the above <strong>structures</strong> and that concerns the distinction between<br />

adjuncts (modifiers) and complements. Notice first that the distinction between adjuncts and<br />

complements is real. Adjuncts are always higher in the tree structure than complements, and the<br />

same phrase often can have either function. We have examples like the following:<br />

159


160<br />

(143) Prehead NP position.<br />

a. the cotton sack<br />

[1] ‘the sack made of cotton’ or ‘the sack for cotton’<br />

[2] the cotton cotton sack<br />

[3] the cotton potato sack<br />

[4] *the potato cotton sack<br />

b. a grand piano<br />

[1] ‘a really nice piano’ or ‘a type of piano’<br />

[2] a grand grand piano<br />

[3] a terrific upright piano<br />

[4] *an upright terrific piano<br />

(144) Posthead NP position.<br />

a. the choice of the men<br />

[1] ‘the choosing of the men’ or ‘the choice by the men’<br />

[2] the choice of the men of the men<br />

[3] the choice of the men by the men<br />

[4] *the choice by the men of the men<br />

b. the rumor that they made up<br />

[1] ‘the rumor about their making up’ or ‘the rumor which they made up’<br />

[2] the rumor that they made up that they made up<br />

[3] the rumor that they made up which they made up<br />

[4] *the rumor which they made up that they made up<br />

(145) Posthead VP position.<br />

a. He decided on the boat.<br />

[1] ‘He chose the boat’ or ‘He was on the boat when he decided.’<br />

[2] He decided on the boat on the boat.<br />

[3] He decided on his vote on the boat.<br />

[4] *He decided on the boat on his vote.<br />

b. He reads the most.<br />

[1] ‘He reads the most things’ or ‘He reads the most often.’<br />

[2] He reads the most the most.<br />

[3] He reads the most books the most often.<br />

[4] *He reads the most often the most books.


The problem with the <strong>structures</strong> (140) and (142) concerns the ambiguities in the above examples;<br />

specifically, there is no way to tell whether a phrase is functioning as an adjunct or as a complement<br />

in representations like the following:<br />

(146) a grand piano<br />

(147) He decided on the boat.<br />

The constituents grand and on the boat in the above trees may either be adjuncts or complements<br />

given our statement of the Endocentricity Constraint (135). In both cases, the ambiguities are<br />

structural, not lexical, that is, the ambiguities pertain to syntactic relationships, not the meaning of<br />

words. In a sentence like I found the bug, the ambiguity derives from the multiple meanings of the<br />

word bug (insect, computer problem, etc.). Other examples of LEXICAL AMBIGUITIES are as<br />

follows:<br />

(148) a. The bandit was shot by the bank. (bank = financial institution, edge of river, etc.)<br />

b. The students are revolting. (revolting = disgusting, uprising, etc.)<br />

161


162<br />

Other examples of STRUCTURAL AMBIGUITIES occur in the following examples, where the<br />

constituents can be grouped in more than one way:<br />

(149) a. The farmer looked over the fence.<br />

[1] The farmer - looked over - the fence.<br />

[2] The farmer - looked - over the fence.<br />

b. The man who left suddenly returned.<br />

[1] The man - who left suddenly - returned.<br />

[2] The man - who left - suddenly returned.<br />

The structural ambiguity in (146) and (147) cannot be resolved by different hierarchical groupings<br />

because the problem does not involve the left-to-right hierarchical order of the constituents. To solve<br />

this problem, we might propose to make a distinction between an X´ over another X´, on the one<br />

hand, and an X´ over an X, on the other, as follows:<br />

(150) a. XP ÷ ...X´... Specifier Rule<br />

b. X´ ÷ ...X´... Adjunct Rule<br />

c. X´ ÷ ...X... Complement Rule<br />

This proposal means that He decided on the boat would have the following two representations,<br />

where on the boat is an adjunct in the first and a complement in the second:<br />

(151) a. He decided on the boat. (on the boat is a adjunct; it is where he decided)


. He decided on the boat. (on the boat is a complement; he chose the boat)<br />

But this proposal will not work because complements can be recursive just as adjuncts can. Note first<br />

that we can have multiple adjuncts, that is, recursive X´ levels:<br />

(152) a. That pretty, little, yellow house is for sale.<br />

b. He drives a sleek, green, speedy Maserati.<br />

Similarly, complements and compound nouns can be stacked recursively:<br />

(153) a. That kitchen appliance factory guarantee is very generous<br />

(cf. The factory guarantees the kitchen appliance.)<br />

b. The terrorist cell police raid stunned everyone.<br />

(cf. The police raided the terrorist cell.)<br />

c. The sexual harassment policy court decision was of national interest.<br />

(cf. The court decided on the policy on sexual harassment.)<br />

d. She filled out the customer satisfaction store survey.<br />

(cf. The store surveys customer satisfaction.)<br />

e. They dedicated a cancer patient radiation treatment facility.<br />

(cf. A facility treats cancer patients with radiation.)<br />

According to (150b) and the proposals we have made, a phrase like kitchen appliance factory<br />

guarantee would have the following representation, which would make kitchen appliance an adjunct,<br />

rather than a complement (direct object) of guarantee:<br />

163


164<br />

(154)<br />

To solve this problem, we will make one final revision to phrase structure levels. Let us assume a<br />

three level version of the Endocentricity Constraint such that each level is distinctly specified with<br />

numbers and specifiers are always daughters of X3, adjuncts are always daughters of X2, compounds<br />

and complements are always daughters of X1, and the head is always X0. Just as the original<br />

Endocentricity Constraint stipulated that each phrase minimally consists of an XP over an X, the new<br />

revision stipulates that each phrases minimally consists of an X3 over an X0. This new phrasal<br />

architecture yields diagrams like the following (note again that intermediate levels are only<br />

mentioned in a diagram if they branch):<br />

(155) a. b.


With this revision, we can diagram the noun phrase the kitchen appliance factory guarantee and its<br />

related sentence (The factory guaranteed the kitchen appliance) as follows:<br />

(156) a.<br />

b.<br />

Note that in both of the above trees, kitchen appliance is a complement (X1 level constituent). Since<br />

each level is uniquely specified with a different number, recursion is possible at all levels without<br />

ambiguity.<br />

165


166<br />

Adding a quantifier and adjuncts (both adjectives and an adverb) to the above phrase, we have<br />

examples like all those unexpected, very generous kitchen appliance factory guarantees:<br />

(157)


With all the above revisions, it is now possible to accurately represent ambiguous phrases in which<br />

constituents can be interpreted either as an adjunct or as a complement:<br />

(158) a. [ N3 [ N2 [radio station] [ N1 night manager]]] = a night manager at a radio station<br />

b. [ N3 [ N1 [radio station] [ N1 night manager]]] = a night manager of a radio station<br />

167<br />

A radio station manager can be either a night manager at a radio station (different<br />

managers at the same station), in which case radio station is an adjunct (N2), or a<br />

night manager of a radio station (someone who manages the whole radio station), in<br />

which case radio station is a complement (N1).<br />

(159) a. peanut oil preservatives = oil preservatives made of peanuts<br />

[ N3 [ N2 peanut [ N1 oil preservatives]]]<br />

b. peanut oil preservatives = oil preservatives for peanuts<br />

[ N3 [ N1 peanut [ N1 oil preservatives]]]<br />

c. peanut oil preservatives = preservatives made of peanut oil<br />

[ N3 [ N2 [peanut oil] [ N0 preservatives]]]<br />

d. peanut oil preservatives = preservatives for peanut oil<br />

[ N3 [ N1 [peanut oil] [ N0 preservatives]]]<br />

(160) a. American embassy sniper attack = attack of/on the American embassy by snipers<br />

[ N3 [ N1 American embassy [ N1 sniper [ attack]]]]<br />

b. American embassy sniper attack = attack at/from the American embassy by snipers<br />

[ N3 [ N2 American embassy [ N1 sniper [attack]]]]<br />

c. American embassy sniper attack = an attack by American embassy snipers<br />

[ N3 [ N1 American embassy sniper [attack]]]<br />

d. American embassy sniper attack = an American attack by embassy snipers<br />

e. etc.<br />

[ N3 [ N2 American [ N1 embassy sniper [attack]]]]


168<br />

Returning to our original examples, we have the following representations in X3 notation (cf. (141)<br />

and (142)):<br />

(161) N3: the people’s generous donations to that charity...<br />

(162) V3: The people generously donate to that charity.


Summarizing, we have the following generalizations:<br />

(163) a. Elements that branch from X3 are SPECIFIERS<br />

in N3 Determiners, possessive marker (POS), quantifiers<br />

in V3 Subjects, tenses<br />

b. Elements that branch from X2 are ADJUNCTS<br />

in N2 Numerals (three, third, etc.), adjectives (silky dress)<br />

Compound elements expressing source or material (silk dress)<br />

in V2 Expressions of time and place, adverbs, predicate nominatives<br />

c. Elements that branch from X1 are COMPLEMENTS and COMPOUNDS<br />

in N1 Complements, direct objects<br />

Compound elements expressing complements (evening dress)<br />

in V1 Complements, direct objects<br />

d. Elements that branch from X0 are parts of words<br />

in N0 Affixes that form nouns (-er in singer, teacher, etc.)<br />

in V0 Prepositions that form two part verbs (put on, throw out, etc.)<br />

Lastly, we reformulate the Endocentricity Constraint as follows:<br />

(164) a. Every phrase has three syntactic levels above the X0 level, which is the head and<br />

contains a word or abstract category (PRS, PST, POS, Ø, and so on).<br />

169<br />

b. Every word or abstract category must be dominated by an X0 which, in turn, must be<br />

dominated by an X3. Intermediate levels (X2 and/or X1) are explicitly mentioned in<br />

diagrams and labeled brackets only if the phrase contains X2 and/or X1 level elements<br />

other than the head. Implicitly, intermediate levels are always there.<br />

c. There may be multiple recursions of every level; however, each higher level of a<br />

phrase must be greater than or equal to the level below, that is, all the specifiers must<br />

be higher than all the adjuncts which, in turn, must be higher than all the<br />

complements.<br />

X3 above X3 above X2 above X2 above X2 above X1 above X1 above X0<br />

[ N3 all [ N3 those [ N2 pretty [ N2 little [ N2 yellow [ N1 ranch [ N1 vacation [ N0 homes ]]]]]]]]<br />

*X3 above X2 above X3 above X2 above X1 above X2 above X1 above X0<br />

*[ N3 those [ N2 pretty [ N3 all [ N2 little [ N1 ranch [ N2 yellow [ N1 vacation [ N0 homes ]]]]]]]]


170<br />

3.12 RESIDENTIAL GRAMMAR (RG)<br />

The major unresolved issue in the previous discussion is that our theory still does not provide a way<br />

to express the relationships between syntactic categories like verbs (V3) and nouns (N3). Let us,<br />

therefore, re–examine the matter. Traditionally, syntactic categories have been viewed as atomic,<br />

that is, not composed of other elements. The data from the last few sections suggest that that view<br />

is incorrect. As we have seen, syntactic categories share characteristics which we have accounted<br />

for with features in much the way that sounds share characteristics in phonology.<br />

Feature theory is a standard part of phonological descriptions. For example, consider again the<br />

following features:<br />

(165) a. [+VOICED] produced with vocal cord vibration<br />

b. [–VOICED] not produced with vocal cord vibration<br />

(166) a. [+NASAL] involving exhalation through the nose<br />

b. [–NASAL] not involving exhalation through the nose<br />

(167) a. [+ANTERIOR] articulated at the front of the mouth<br />

b. [–ANTERIOR] not articulated at the front of the mouth<br />

Given these features, we can say that the sounds for m as is mass, b as in bass, p as in pass, and g as<br />

in gas, are as follows:<br />

(168) a. [m] [+VOICED, +NASAL, +ANTERIOR]<br />

b. [b] [+VOICED, –NASAL, +ANTERIOR]<br />

c. [p] [–VOICED, –NASAL, +ANTERIOR]<br />

d. [g] [+VOICED, –NASAL, –ANTERIOR]<br />

Thus, a sound like [m] is nothing more than an abbreviation for a specific set of phonological<br />

features. Let us propose a similar feature analysis for syntax.<br />

We begin by noting the difference between verbs and all other categories, in particular, that verbs are<br />

the only category that carries tense (broke), the only category that shows mode (may break) and<br />

aspect (has broken) distinctions, and the only category that can occur in present and past participial<br />

forms (breaking and broken). For these and other reasons to be discussed below, we make the<br />

following division:<br />

(169)


The feature [+VBL] specifies those categories which are inherently marked for distinctions in tense,<br />

aspect, voice, and/or mode; [–VBL] specifies categories that are not so marked. [–VBL] categories<br />

also fall neatly into two major classes, those that behave like nouns, and those that do not.<br />

A distinctive attribute of nouns is that they are inherently marked for distinctions in number, person,<br />

gender, and/or case. Let us specify the former as [+NML]; the latter, [–NML]. The same distinction<br />

occurs in some verb forms. Verb forms that are inherently marked for nominal distinctions [+NML]<br />

include verbal nouns like the gerund basing in Basing the argument on so many assumptions is<br />

unwise; verb forms that are not inherently marked for nominal distinctions include tensed verbs like<br />

bases in He bases his argument on many assumptions, in which the singular number on bases is a<br />

result of agreement and is not an inherent feature of the tensed verb (cf. They base their argument<br />

on many assumptions). To capture these distinctions, we modify (169) to (170) and refer to<br />

nonnouns as CHARACTERIZERS since they characterize a head.<br />

(170)<br />

[+NML] categories differ from characterizers in a number of ways. First, [+NML] categories have<br />

a number of morphological specifications that characterizers lack. They occur before specific<br />

suffixes like –ment, –ness, –ing, etc. (basement, baseness, basing). They show number distinctions:<br />

base versus bases. They occur in the possessive: the base’s shape and the shape of the base.<br />

Second, [+NML] categories fulfill a number of specific syntactic functions, which means they occupy<br />

specific positions in syntactic hierarchies. For example, they can be SUBJECT or OBJECT. Third,<br />

[+NML] categories are always distributed before [–NML] categories on every X level in both<br />

prehead and posthead positions. Notice that in every diagram in this monograph, when two<br />

categories are suspended from the same level, [+NML] categories (NOUNS) always precede [–NML]<br />

categories (CHARACTERIZERS and VERBS).<br />

We now have four major syntactic categories in language, which RG specifies as follows:<br />

(171) a. Verbs (V): [+VBL, –NML] go, goes, went, gone, going<br />

b. Nouns (N): [–VBL, +NML] woman, women, she, all<br />

c. Characterizers (C): [–VBL, –NML] happy, happily, probably, on, after<br />

d. Verbal Nouns (VN): [+VBL, +NML] swimming, eating, reading<br />

Given these major categorial distinctions, we note that many parts of speech are distinguished from<br />

each other mainly by what kind of phrase they can occur in and where they can occur within that<br />

phrase, that is, they have a specific residence. Formally, we define a RESIDENCE as a specific<br />

171


172<br />

position in syntactic structure which has a specific semantic or syntactic function. The theory based<br />

on the concept of residence is called RESIDENTIAL GRAMMAR (RG).<br />

The morphosyntactic feature oppositions [±VBL, ±NML] are not sufficient to distinguish the major<br />

syntactic categories that occur in the world’s languages. For example, within the category verb, there<br />

are subclasses which include finite verbs, nonfinite verbs (infinitives, participles, etc.), auxiliaries,<br />

and modals. Within the category characterizer, there are prepositions, subordinators (subordinating<br />

conjunctions), adjectives, adverbs, determiners, and so on. To specify these subclasses, we will use<br />

two features [±OPEN PHRASE] ([±OPH]) and [±OPEN CLASS] ([±OCL]) defined as follows:<br />

(172) a. [+OPH]: occurring as the head of a phrase that freely contains other elements<br />

b. [–OPH]: occurring as the head of a phrase that does not freely contain other<br />

elements<br />

(173) a. [+OCL]: unlimited in number<br />

b. [–OCL]: limited in number<br />

The syntactic feature specification [±OPH] separates categories whose internal phrase structure is<br />

open in the sense that it can freely contain specifiers (words like the, this, and that), quantifiers<br />

(words like all, some, and much), or adjuncts (adjectives and adverbs), from other categories whose<br />

internal phrase structure is highly restricted. The [±OPH] distinction is most clearly seen in the<br />

variety of <strong>structures</strong> possible for common nouns on the one hand, which can be specified, quantified,<br />

and modified, and pronouns and proper nouns on the other hand, which cannot:<br />

(174) a. That very old woman left early./*That very old she left early.<br />

b. All the tall women walked in./*All the tall they walked in.<br />

c. A woman that is tall will get the job./*Mary that is tall will get the job.<br />

The feature [+OCL] specifies those categories which form an open class to which an unlimited<br />

number of items may be added. Since classical antiquity, most grammarians have observed the sharp<br />

distinction between the very large number of nouns, verbs, adjectives, and adverbs that occur in<br />

languages as opposed to the rather small fixed number of prepositions, conjunctions, determiners,<br />

pronouns, etc. The opposition [±OCL] is intended to capture this dichotomy. For the most part, in<br />

English, open class words are marked by distinct inflectional suffixes: nouns show variations in<br />

number (boy, boys); verbs show variations in tense (plays, played); and adjectives and adverbs show<br />

variations in comparison (fast, faster, fastest; long, longer, longest). Examples of [+OCL] and<br />

[–OCL] categories are the following:<br />

(175) a. [+OCL]: nouns, verbs, adjectives, adverbs<br />

b. [–OCL]: auxiliaries, modals, pronouns, determiners, prepositions, etc.<br />

Within a particular kind of phrase, certain categories are restricted to X3 level, others to X2 level,<br />

and still others to X1 level. For example, all categories denoting specification (DETERMINERS)<br />

or quantification (QUANTIFIERS) are X3 Level residents. All descriptive modifiers of the head are<br />

X2 Level residents. All elements of compounds (history in history teacher) and complements


(history in teacher of history and teach history) are X1 Level residents. Therefore, with reference<br />

to the X hierarchy, we recognize the following level features:<br />

(176) a. [+X3L] can freely occur immediately dominated by X3 (N3, V3, or C3)<br />

b. [–X3L] cannot freely occur immediately dominated by X3 (N3, V3, or C3)<br />

(177) a. [+X2L] can freely occur immediately dominated by X2 (N2, V2, or C2)<br />

b. [–X2L] cannot freely occur immediately dominated by X2 (N2, V2, or C2)<br />

(178) a. [+X1L] can freely occur immediately dominated by X1 (N1, V1, or C1)<br />

b. [–X1L] cannot freely occur immediately dominated by X1 (N1, V1, or C1)<br />

We note further, that some categories are restricted to phrases with specific heads, that is, can be<br />

suspended from some X level only when X is a specific phrase type. DETERMINERS can only<br />

occur in noun phrase, suspended from N3; ADJECTIVES can occur in either noun phrases or verb<br />

phrases, suspended from N2 or V2; MANNER ADVERBS can occur only verb phrases suspended<br />

from V2. Therefore, we recognize the following environment features:<br />

(179) a. [+ENH] can freely occur immediately dominated by N3, N2, or N1<br />

b. [–ENH] cannot freely occur immediately dominated by N3, N2, or N1<br />

(180) a. [+EVH] can freely occur immediately dominated by V3, V2, or V1<br />

b. [–EVH] cannot freely occur immediately dominated by V3, V2, or V1<br />

(181) a. [+ECH] can freely occur immediately dominated by C3, C2, or C1<br />

b. [–ECH] cannot freely occur immediately dominated by C3, C2, or C1<br />

Lastly, we recognize that some categories are restricted to prehead position (DETERMINERS) and<br />

others to posthead position (NEGATIVES). We, therefore, add these feature oppositions:<br />

(182) a. [+PRH] can freely occur before the head of a phrase<br />

b. [–PRH] cannot freely occur before the head of a phrase<br />

(183) a. [+PSH] can freely occur after the head of a phrase<br />

b. [–PSH] cannot freely occur after the head of a phrase<br />

Ultimately, the concept of residence is linked to the syntactic features of RG. These are proposed<br />

as substantive syntactic universals, meaning that the languages of the world must construct their<br />

syntactic inventories out of these features, just as they must construct their phonological inventories<br />

out of substantive phonological features. Despite this constraint, it is important to note that the theory<br />

does not demand that all languages choose the same features in the same combinations. Quite the<br />

contrary occurs. Different languages select different sets of features out of the pool of possible<br />

features, and even the same language, at different points in its history, utilizes features in different<br />

ways. For example, at an earlier stage of English, word order constraints were less stringent than<br />

they are today; therefore, the features [±PREHEAD] and [±POSTHEAD] did not have the<br />

173


174<br />

significance they have in modern English. The task of children acquiring a language is to discover<br />

which system they have been exposed to by chance.<br />

Note that, with features, we can directly account for the relationship between examples in which<br />

constituents occupy different positions, such as the available books and the books available as in<br />

(184).<br />

(184) a. b.<br />

Recall that such diagrams omit unbranching intermediate X levels, by convention. Thus, N2 is<br />

present because it branches; but N1, not relevant here, is omitted. If the phrases were the available<br />

history books and the history books available, then both N2 (dominating available) and N1<br />

(dominating history) would be present in the diagrams.<br />

In addition, individual levels must be recursive to distinguish units: [ N3 the [ N2 intelligent [ N2 young<br />

[ N men]]]] contrasts with [ N3 the [ N2 young [ N2 intelligent [ N men]]]]. In both of these examples, there<br />

are two successive, separate N2 levels distinguishing the meanings. In the first case, [ N3 the [ N2<br />

intelligent [ N2 young [ N men]]]], one is talking about the young men who are intelligent. But in the<br />

second, [ N3 the [ N2 young [ N2 intelligent [ N men]]]], one is taking about the intelligent men who are<br />

young.<br />

This method of recursion is also necessary to account for the use of ones in sentences like John met<br />

the young men from Cleveland, and Bill met the old ones, where ones refers to the subunit men from<br />

Cleveland. Such examples contrast with others like John met the young men from Cleveland, and<br />

Bill met the ones from New York, where ones refers to the subunit young men.<br />

Since all categories on the X2 Level are modifiers of the head, it no longer matters whether the<br />

adjective precedes the noun or follows it. We simply state idiosyncratic facts about individual words<br />

in the lexicon next to each lexical entry. This means that the word available has a dictionary<br />

specification like [–VBL, –NML, +X2L, +PRH, +PSH] meaning that it is an X2 Level characterizer<br />

(Adjective) that can occur in either prehead or posthead position.<br />

We can extend this analysis to show the relationship between a courageous man and a man of<br />

courage as in (185) and a Braille teacher and a teacher of Braille as in (186).


(185) a. b.<br />

(186) a. b.<br />

The structure of courage in (185b) is called a genitive of quality; notice that, as an X2 Level element,<br />

it serves as a modifier of the head, exactly like the adjective courageous in (185a). The <strong>structures</strong><br />

in (186) show the relationship between compounds and complements. In English, this is most clearly<br />

seen in nouns, although it exists for other categories like verbs (bartend versus tend bar) and<br />

adjectives (life supporting versus supporting life).<br />

The of in (185b) and (186b) is not a full preposition introducing a prepositional phrase. Actually, it<br />

is little more than a phonological filler necessary in English to separate the head from posthead<br />

constituents. In English, noun phrases can contain very long sequences of compound elements as we<br />

have seen. Further, the last noun in a sequence of nouns is the head of the phrase and only the head<br />

can carry number distinctions. Consider the following examples which show that only the head in<br />

a sequence of nouns can show number distinctions and it is the head of the subject NP that the verb<br />

agrees with:<br />

(187) a. The kitchen appliance factory guarantee is/*are generous.<br />

b. The kitchen appliance factory guarantees *is/are generous.<br />

175


176<br />

c. *The kitchen appliance factories guarantee is/are generous.<br />

d. *The kitchen appliances factory guarantee is/are generous.<br />

e. *The kitchens appliance factory guarantee is/are generous.<br />

f. A ten thousand word paper is/*are required.<br />

g. *A ten thousand words paper is/are required.<br />

Also, as the following data show, the head (in italics) of an NP must be separated from posthead<br />

constituents by a characterizer (double underlined):<br />

(188) a. The votes against gun control *is/are greater than expected.<br />

b. John’s reliance on his parents is/*are pathetic.<br />

c. The birds in that tree *is/are nesting.<br />

d. The language teacher is/*are in the auditorium.<br />

If there is no overt characterizer separating the head noun from posthead elements, then of must be<br />

inserted directly after the head. We have contrasts like the following:<br />

(189) a. His love stories *is/are charming.<br />

b. His love of stories is/*are charming.<br />

c. The language teachers *is/are monitored by the principal.<br />

d. The language of teachers is/*are monitored by the principal.<br />

e. The number systems *is/are complicated.<br />

f. The number of systems is/*are complicated.<br />

g. The student letters *is/are very complimentary.<br />

h. The student of letters is/*are very complimentary.<br />

All of the above intricacies about English noun phrases seem to involve the rule of verb-subject<br />

agreement. Without agreement, many English sentences are uninterpretable. There is a very large<br />

number of words in English that can be either a noun or a verb, e.g., school, show, play, book, table,<br />

chair, man, etc. Consider the following and observe the number on the verb:<br />

(190) a. The school shows play here. (Subject is shows; the verb play is plural.)<br />

b. The school show plays here. (Subject is show; the verb plays is singular).<br />

c. The school shows plays here. (Subject is school; the verb shows is singular.)<br />

d. The schools show plays here. (Subject is schools; the verb show is plural.)<br />

Without agreement, the sentences are uninterpretable:


(191) a. *The school show play here.<br />

b. *The schools shows plays here.<br />

Since verbs agree with the head of the subject phrase, it is important that speakers be able to identify<br />

the head. The three constraints mentioned above facilitate that identification: (i) only the head can<br />

show number distinctions; (ii) the head must be separated from posthead constituents by a<br />

characterizer; and (iii), if there is no characterizer after the head, then of must be inserted effectively<br />

marking the head. It is interesting that the word that is inserted to mark the head is of, which is<br />

perhaps the most generic preposition in English, often pronounced [c].<br />

Given this analysis, we might have an explanation for why the past tense has become regular in<br />

English for all persons and numbers, but the present tense has not. Compare the following.<br />

(192) a. Past Tense:<br />

played for all persons and numbers: She/They played.<br />

b. Present Tense:<br />

plays for third person singular; play elsewhere: She plays versus They play.<br />

The basic problem is that singular and plural noun inflection is identical to verb inflection:<br />

(193) a. play: either a singular noun or a plural present<br />

b. plays: either a plural noun or a singular present<br />

There are many nouns in English that also function as verbs. On the other hand, there are only a few<br />

past tense verbs that are also nouns, and they are all irregular, e.g., cut and hit. Further, locating the<br />

head of an English noun phrase is not a trivial matter. There are many opportunities for ambiguity.<br />

All these potential ambiguities are eliminated by the rule of subject verb agreement. Quite simply,<br />

without the inflectional differences between singular and plural count nouns and between singular<br />

and plural present verbs, speakers would be unable to locate the head of a noun phrase. Thus, the<br />

present tense of verbs cannot become regular<br />

We can generalize the above description of the English N3 to V3 and account for the very large<br />

number of nominals that are related to verbs, e.g., destruction and destroy, evolution and evolve,<br />

advancement and advance, shipment and ship, etc. As we have seen, this is essential if we are to<br />

generalize notions like subject–of and object–of across categories: we want to be able to relate the<br />

N3 his insistence on that to the V3 he insisted on that, the N3 her unexpected refusal to comply to<br />

the V3 she unexpectedly refused to comply, and so on. Consider the following representations which<br />

illustrate the close relationships between V3 and N3:<br />

177


178<br />

(194) The Mafia illegally shipped drugs into the country during June.<br />

(195) the Mafia’s illegal shipments of drugs into the country during June...


The representations in (194) and (195) make significant improvements in the search for descriptive<br />

adequacy. For example, notice that such representations as the above make possible a generalized<br />

statement of subject and object. The subject N3 (the Mafia) has the same relationship to the V3 head<br />

shipped in (194) as it has to the N3 head shipment in (195). Similarly, the object N3 (drugs) has the<br />

same relationship to both V1 in (194) and N1 in (195); the adverb illegally is in the same relationship<br />

to shipped as the adjective illegal is to shipment. In short, the RG framework goes a long way in<br />

solving the problems in previous discussions.<br />

In (194), PST is the morpheme for the past tense discussed earlier (see Page 136). Thus, TENSE<br />

markers in V3 occupy the same residence as DETERMINERS and POSSESSIVES in N3. In (195),<br />

POS stands for the possessive suffix, which is usually either [s] as in book’s (the book’s cover), [z]<br />

as in John’s (John’s son), or [cz] as in Bess’s (Bess’s boss). Notice that, in forming a possessive like<br />

Mafia’s, the noun Mafia is under the N3 and POS is under the C3. This is necessary because English<br />

contains expressions like the boy with the stick’s hand is sore, where the possessive phrase consists<br />

of the N3 the boy with the stick followed in a separate node by the possessive suffix. Notice that we<br />

do not say *The boy’s with the stick hand is sore.<br />

With these improvements, we are able to represent a complex example like (119h) as follows:<br />

(196) all those ten recently stolen Impressionist paintings of landscapes of the Louvre’s on sale<br />

179


180<br />

Another example of the relationship between V3 and N3 is the following:<br />

(197) The friendly flight attendant patiently described the safety precautions to the nervous<br />

passengers in their native language.<br />

(198) the friendly flight attendant’s patient description of the safety precautions to the nervous<br />

passengers in their native language...


Observe again that, by convention, nodes do not appear in trees explicitly unless they branch:<br />

(199) this very young student (200) this Renaissance history student<br />

(201) this very curious very young Renaissance history student<br />

181


182<br />

The complete RG morphosyntactic feature matrix is summarized in Figure Eight. Elsewhere in this<br />

text, syntactic categories are often referred to using the following abbreviations:<br />

V: VERB ADV: MANNER ADVERB<br />

AUX : AUXILIARY PPN: PREPOSITION<br />

MOD : MODAL SCJ: SUBORDINATING CONJUNCTION; SUBORDINATOR<br />

N: NOUN CCJ: COORDINATING CONJUNCTION; COORDINATOR<br />

PRO: PRONOUN CPL: COMPLEMENTIZER<br />

QNT: QUANTIFIER DET: DETERMINER<br />

ADJ: ADJECTIVE DGR: DEGREE WORD<br />

One of the most significant advantages of the above framework is that it enables us to state the formal<br />

universal (202):<br />

(202) [+NML] categories must precede [–NML] categories in both prehead and posthead position<br />

on every X level.<br />

Given the matrix in Figure Eight, the potential difficulty of constructing a revealing set of phrase<br />

structure rules is solved. All possible phrase structure sequences in English are reducible to one<br />

PHRASE STRUCTURE FILTER (PSF), namely, (203a) which is equivalent to the tree in (203b).<br />

(203) a. [X n ([+NML]) ([–NML]) X m ([+NML]) ([–NML]) ]<br />

b.<br />

where m # n<br />

(203) asserts that each X level must dominate a lower X level with an equal or lesser numerical value,<br />

e. g., X2 over X2, X1, or X0 but not X2 over X3. Further, (203) asserts that each X level may have<br />

at most one [+NML] and one [–NML] category, in that order, to the right and/or to the left of the<br />

head X.<br />

Given (203), we have solved the categorial problem and can eliminate from our grammar complex<br />

and unrevealing PS–Rules like those in (89).


FIGURE EIGHT: FEATURES FOR ENGLISH MORPHOSYNTACTIC CATEGORIES<br />

CATEGORIES & EXAMPLES VBL NML OPH OCL PRH PSH ENH EVH ECH X1L X2L X3L<br />

VERB: go, goes, went + – + + – + + + + + + +<br />

AUX: have, has, had + – – – + + – + + – – –<br />

MODAL: can, could, must + – – – + – – – + – – –<br />

NOUN: boy, milk, Mary – + + + + + + + + + + +<br />

PRONOUN: she, he, herself – + – – + + + + + + + +<br />

QUANTIFIER: all, both, half – + – – + – + – – – – +<br />

DETERMINER: a, the, this – – – – + – + – – – – +<br />

COMPLEMENTIZER: that, if – – – – + – – + – – – +<br />

DEGREE WORD: so, too, this – – – – + – + – – – – +<br />

PREPOSITION: in, out, after – – + – – + + + + + + +<br />

SUBORDINATOR: since, after – – + – – + + + + – + +<br />

COORDINATOR: and – – – – – + + + + + + +<br />

ADJECTIVE: happy, big – – + + – + + + – + + –<br />

MANNER ADVERB: happily – – + + + + – + – – + –<br />

SENTENCE ADVERB: probably – – – + + + – + + – – –<br />

VBL: VERBAL inherently marked for distinctions in tense, aspect, voice, and/or mode<br />

NML: NOMINAL inherently marked for distinctions in number, person, gender, and/or case<br />

OPH: OPEN PHRASE occurring as the head of a phrase that freely contains other elements<br />

OCL: OPEN CLASS unlimited in number<br />

PRH: PREHEAD can freely occur before the head of a phrase<br />

PSH: POSTHEAD can freely occur after the head of a phrase<br />

ENH: ENVIRONMENT OF N can freely occur immediately dominated by N3, N2, or N1<br />

EVH: ENVIRONMENT OF V can freely occur immediately dominated by V3, V2, or V1<br />

ECH: ENVIRONMENT OF C can freely occur immediately dominated by C3, C2 or C1<br />

X1L: X1 LEVEL can freely occur immediately dominated by X1 (N1, V1, or C1)<br />

X2L: X2 LEVEL can freely occur immediately dominated by X2 (N2, V2, or C2)<br />

X3L: X3 LEVEL can freely occur immediately dominated by X3 (N3, V3, or C3)<br />

183


184<br />

(203) also makes clear the relationship between a tree diagram such as (203b) and an equivalent,<br />

linear representation such as (203a), referred to as LABELED BRACKETS. For example, the<br />

following representations are equivalent; again, note that labeled brackets always occur in left–right<br />

pairs as the arrows indicate:<br />

(204) ¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯<br />

¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯<br />

¯¯¯¯ ¯¯¯¯¯¯ ¯¯¯¯¯¯¯ ¯¯¯¯¯<br />

a. [ V3 [ N3 he] [ C3 PST] [ V1 [ V0 leave] [ N3 her] ] ]<br />

b.<br />

Note that her is the object of leave and is part of V1. As before, PST + leave = left.<br />

Labeled brackets are difficult to read and, therefore, often simplified. For example,<br />

[ N3 he] above is technically [ N3 [ N0 he]]; however, since the internal structure of the<br />

noun phrase is clear, it is given in simplified form. If only the V1 is important to a<br />

discussion, the above might even be simplified to [ V3 he PST [ V1 leave her]].<br />

(205) ¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯<br />

¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯<br />

¯¯¯¯ ¯¯¯¯¯¯ ¯¯¯¯ ¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯<br />

a. [ V3 [ N3 he] [ C3 PST] [ V2 [ V0 leave] [ C3 happy/happily] ] ]<br />

b.<br />

Note that happy/happily is a modifier of the predicate leave and is part of V2 (the<br />

distinction between X1 and X2 is discussed further on the next page).


As the above diagrams show, the most significant difference between RG and other versions of<br />

X–Bar syntax is the level distinctions, in particular, the status of the X2 level. In all phrases, the X2<br />

level contains descriptive modifiers of the head. These may be either characterizers or nouns;<br />

compare (206a) and (206b).<br />

(206) a. a courageous act b. an act of courage.<br />

In V3, the V2 level dominates manner adverbs and, in copulative constructions, predicate modifiers<br />

of the subject:<br />

(207) a. He acted courageously. b. He was courageous.<br />

The parallelism between V2 and N2 can be seen in the following representations:<br />

(208) a. It smells bad. [ V3 [ N3 it] [ C3 PRS] [ V2 [ V0 smell] [ C3 bad] ]]<br />

b. It has a bad smell. [ V3 [ N3 it] [ C3 PRS] [ V1 [ V0 have] [ N3 [ C3 a] [ N2 [ C3 bad] [ N0 smell] ]] ]]<br />

c. Its smell is bad. [ V3 [ N3 [ N3 it] [ C3 POS] [ N0 smell] ] [ C3 PRS] [ V2 [ C3 bad] ]]<br />

185


186<br />

The need for three X levels above the head X proceeds from the following assumptions we have<br />

made all along:<br />

(209) a. The rules of language are structure dependent, that is, they refer to structural units<br />

or phrases.<br />

b. The rules refer to whole phrases, not pieces of phrases. In terms of a tree diagram,<br />

this means that rules make reference to nodes.<br />

Given (209), consider the RG structure for this young history student:<br />

(210)<br />

Verification of each level proceeds as follows:<br />

(211) a. The entire phrase (the whole N3) is replaced in the sentence This young history<br />

student said that he would pass. (he = this young history student)<br />

b. The anaphor one can occur with N2 elements: John met this young history student,<br />

and Mary met that one. (one = young history student)<br />

c. Conversely, one cannot occur with N1 elements: *John met a history student, and<br />

Bill met a biology one. (one = student)<br />

The need for the distinction between N2 and N1 is confirmed by a phrase like the Spanish Spanish<br />

teacher. Without two levels below the, there would be no way to disambiguate the senses of<br />

Spanish. The first one means from Spain; the second, of Spanish. Thus, the phrase equals the<br />

teacher of Spanish from Spain (compare (212a) and (212b)).


(212) a. the Spanish Spanish teacher b. the teacher of Spanish from Spain<br />

Residency requirements for this phrasal architecture predict the grammaticality of (213a) and (213b),<br />

and the ungrammaticality of (213c) and (213d).<br />

(213) a. the French math teacher<br />

b. the teacher of math from France<br />

c. *the math French teacher<br />

d. *the teacher from France of math<br />

In addition, these <strong>structures</strong> account for the ambiguity of phrases like the practical nurse, an<br />

intellectual historian, and the issue of student grants. All of these facts result from the following<br />

residency requirements of English: Descriptive modifiers of the head must hang from X2; elements<br />

of compounds and complements must hang from X1.<br />

Lastly, observe that this system allows the first member of a compound noun to be any one of the<br />

three major syntactic categories: in math teacher the noun head (teacher) is preceded by another<br />

noun (math); in physical therapist the head noun (therapist) is preceded by a characterizer<br />

(physical); and, in go cart, the head noun (cart) is preceded by a verb (go).<br />

187


188<br />

The three level hypothesis for V3 can be confirmed with reference to the following structure:<br />

(214) Sue will get the mail on Monday.<br />

Given (209), verification of the three V nodes proceeds as follows:<br />

(215) a. The existence of the V3 level is indicated by its pronominalization in the following<br />

sentence: Sue will get the mail on Monday; at least, that’s what Bill says. (that =<br />

Sue will get the mail on Monday)<br />

b. The existence of the V2 level is indicated by its omission in the following sentence:<br />

Sue will get the mail on Monday, and Mary will ___ too. (get the mail on Monday<br />

is left out.)<br />

Further, V2 level elements can occur after the pro–form do so as in the following:<br />

Sue will get the mail on Monday, and Mary will do so on Tuesday. (do so = get the<br />

mail)<br />

c. The existence of the V1 level is indicated by its omission in the following sentence:<br />

Sue will get the mail on Monday, but Mary won’t ____ until Tuesday. (get the mail<br />

is left out.)<br />

Further, V1 elements can NOT occur after the pro–form do so as the following<br />

indicates: *Sue will get the mail on Monday, and Mary will do so the pay checks on<br />

Tuesday.


The existence of V1 (direct object and object complement position) as opposed to V2 (predicate<br />

nominative position, referring back to subject) also resolves the ambiguity in (216).<br />

(216) a. John left the house messy.<br />

(i) messy an object modifier:<br />

[ V3 [ N3 John] [ C3 PST] [ V2 [ V1 [ V0 leave] [ N3 the house] [ C3 messy ] ] ] ]<br />

(ii) messy a predicate adjective, subject to agreement rules:<br />

[ V3 [ N3 John] [ C3 PST] [ V2 [ V1 [ V0 leave] [ N3 the house] ] [ C3 messy] ] ]<br />

b. John defied Bill to get even.<br />

(i) to get even a complementary infinitive with subject Bill:<br />

[ V3 [ N3 John] [ C3 PST] [ V2 [ V1 [ V0 defy] [ N3 Bill] [ C3 to get even] ] ] ]<br />

(ii) to get even a purposive infinitive with subject John:<br />

[ V3 [ N3 John] [ C3 PST] [ V2 [ V1 [ V0 defy] [ N3 Bill] ] [ C3 to get even] ] ]<br />

189


190<br />

c. The boys made good models.<br />

(i) make a transitive verb like build:<br />

[ V3 [ N3 the boys] [ C3 PST] [ V2 [ V1 [ V0 make] [ N3 good models] ] ] ]<br />

(ii) make a copulative verb like become:<br />

[ V3 [ N3 the boys] [ C3 PST] [ V2 [ V1 [ V0 make] ] [ N3 good models] ] ]<br />

In addition, the V1/V2 distinction explains the grammaticality of (217), and predicts the<br />

ungrammaticality of (218).<br />

(217) a. John ate the food raw, nude.<br />

b. John left the house unlocked, drunk as a skunk.<br />

(218) a. *John ate the food nude, raw.<br />

b. *John left the house drunk, unlocked.<br />

The V1/V2 distinction also accounts for the ambiguity of sentences like those in (219):<br />

(219) a. They left good friends.<br />

b. They left the country great men.<br />

c. They considered the candidates very concerned about the future of the country.<br />

The most striking feature of these examples is the parallelism between the N1/N2 distinction and<br />

the V1/V2 distinction, clearly seen in the following:<br />

(220) a. a young math teacher<br />

[ N3 [ C3 a] [ N2 [ C3 young] [ N1 [ N3 math] [ N0 teacher ] ] ] ]<br />

b. a teacher of math that young (is rare)<br />

[ N3 [ C3 a] [ N2 [ N1 [ N0 teacher] of [ N3 math] ] [ C3 that young] ] ]<br />

c. He taught math young.<br />

[ V3 [ N3 he] [ C3 PST] [ V2 [ V1 [ V0 teach] [ N3 math] ] [ C3 young] ] ]<br />

(221) a. a superb math teacher<br />

[ N3 [ C3 a] [ N2 [ C3 superb] [ N1 [ N3 math] [ N0 teacher ] ] ] ]<br />

b. a teacher of math that superb (is rare)<br />

[ N3 [ C3 a] [ N2 [ N1 [ N0 teacher] of [ N3 math] ] [ C3 that superb] ] ]<br />

c. He taught math superbly.<br />

[ V3 [ N3 he] [ C3 PST] [ V2 [ V1 [ V0 teach] [ N3 math] ] [ C3 superbly] ] ] ]


3.13 TRANSFORMATIONAL GENERATIVE GRAMMAR<br />

By themselves, phrase structure rules can describe a great number of the individual sentences that<br />

occur in languages; however, if our corpus is expanded to include more types of constructions, it<br />

appears that some relationships between sentences will not be able to receive adequate<br />

characterizations with phrase structure rules alone. For example, consider sets of English sentences<br />

like the following and note that each pair means basically the same thing:<br />

(222) a. The city must burn this book.<br />

b. This book, the city must burn.<br />

(223) a. The frightened cat ran under the bed.<br />

b. Under the bed, the frightened cat ran.<br />

(224) a. He will never be very strong.<br />

b. Very strong, he will never be.<br />

The construction illustrated in (222b), (223b), and (224b) is TOPICALIZATION, the placement<br />

of a phrase in sentence initial position for emphasis. Such examples rarely occur in isolation, which<br />

is why they sound somewhat strange. However, in context they are not unusual. For example,<br />

during a discussion of the books to be burned, (222b) would sound quite appropriate.<br />

Students often claim that they would never utter topicalized phrases, but careful attention to<br />

language reveals that, in fact, they do. Further, whether one utters topicalized phrases or not is<br />

completely irrelevant. The fact is that such sentences are immediately understood by native speakers<br />

in context. Given this, the sentences become part of the corpus of data that a linguist must analyze.<br />

As our discussion of prescriptive versus descriptive grammar in Chapter One indicated, modern<br />

<strong>linguistic</strong>s is concerned with describing what is possible, not what is considered correct.<br />

These three pairs of sentences begin with phrases that occur before the NP subject phrase. In (222b),<br />

the subject phrase is preceded by another N3; in (223b), by a prepositional phrase; and, in (224b),<br />

an adjective phrase. We could accommodate these data by adding a PS-Rule like the following<br />

where X3 is a phrase with a [–VBL] head (noun, preposition, or adjective):<br />

(225) V3 ÷ (X3) + N3 + T3 + V2<br />

But this will not do for several reasons. First, the optional phrases at the beginning of (225) are<br />

understood as the complements of the verbs, that is, phrases that complete the meaning of the verbs.<br />

For instance, this book in (222b) is the object of burn. Our structural definition of object says that<br />

the object is the N3 dominated by the V1. While this definition holds for (222a), it fails for (222b)<br />

because the initial NP of (225) is not dominated by V1. Furthermore, our structural definition of<br />

subject is now compromised. Given (225), there are now two N3 dominated by V3. Worse yet, if<br />

we adopt (225), the whole classification of English verbs comes to grief. Broadly speaking, there<br />

are two types of verbs in English: TRANSITIVE VERBS like catch, which must take a direct<br />

object; and, INTRANSITIVE VERBS like die, which never do:<br />

191


192<br />

(226) a. John caught Bill.<br />

b. *John caught.<br />

(227) a. John died.<br />

b. *John died Bill.<br />

If, to account for (228), we allow transitive verbs to occur in verb phrases without a following N3,<br />

we lose the distinction between transitives and intransitives.<br />

(228) Foul balls like that, no one can catch.<br />

Somehow, we must indicate that the initial phrases in (222b), (223b), (224b), and (228) are<br />

complements of the main verb. Since a phrase structure solution via (225) failed, another method<br />

must be sought.<br />

PS–RULES generate tree <strong>structures</strong> with phrases in specific positions. Suppose that we now allow<br />

grammars to contain other rules that move elements from such positions to new positions, that is,<br />

transform one structure into another. For example, suppose that, as before, the PS–RULES in (89)<br />

generate a structure like (229).<br />

(229)<br />

Now suppose a TRANSFORMATIONAL RULE moves the object NP to the front of the sentence<br />

leaving behind a TRACE (a kind of footprint) of that object in the form of a co–indexed NP. The<br />

result is (230), where "[e]" indicates the EMPTY NP TRACE designating the original home of the<br />

object.


(230)<br />

This produces the sentence (231a) or, more accurately, (231b).<br />

(231) a. This book, the city must burn.<br />

b. [ NP this book] i the city must burn [ NP e] i<br />

A crucial point in the representation (231b) is that there really is a gap in the sentence at the point<br />

of the [e]. When speakers hear a sentence that begins with a “displaced” object, they must wait for<br />

the gap in the sentence before they can assign an interpretation to that “displaced” phrase. Consider<br />

(52).<br />

(232) a. This book, you absolutely must try to get your students to convince each other to tell<br />

their friends to read.<br />

b. [ NP this book] i you absolutely must try to get your students to convince each other to<br />

tell their friends to read [ NP e] i<br />

Given representations like the above, we can say that [ NP e] i is bound to [ NP this book] i via<br />

REFERENCE, not unlike the way pronouns are bound to their referents in sentences like John i saw<br />

himself i in the mirror.<br />

A grammar that contains transformational rules is called a TRANSFORMATIONAL<br />

(GENERATIVE) GRAMMAR (TG). In such grammars, a sentence like (231a) is associated with<br />

two <strong>structures</strong>: the structure generated by the phrase structure rules, that is, (229); and the structure<br />

generated by the transformational rules, that is, (230). Technically, we say that phrase structure<br />

rules generate the DEEP STRUCTURE of sentences, and transformational rules generate the<br />

SURFACE STRUCTURE. Crucially, functional relations like subject and object are not altered<br />

by transformational rules. However, the rules do switch the order of constituents in a sentence<br />

meaning that the order in the deep structure can be different from the order in the surface structure.<br />

More importantly, our description of the grammars of human languages has now changed.<br />

Originally, we claimed that human languages could be described by PS-Rules alone. Now, we must<br />

say that they require an additional rule, the Transformational Rule or T-Rule.<br />

193


194<br />

3.14 NONTRANSFORMATIONAL GENERATIVE GRAMMAR<br />

With transformational rules, we say that human languages cannot be adequately described without<br />

the following two assumptions:<br />

(233) a. Every sentence has two structural levels, an abstract underlying structure roughly<br />

equivalent to what is understood, and a real superficial structure roughly equivalent<br />

to what is heard.<br />

b. The order of phrases in the abstract underlying structure can be different from the<br />

order of phrases in the real superficial structure.<br />

It seems quite clear that (233a) must be assumed. The syntactic processes of REFERENCE,<br />

OMISSION, and PLACEMENT demand it. For example, there is no way to understand the<br />

superficial structure (234a) without the underlying representation (234b).<br />

(234) a. John will sing if you ask him to.<br />

b. John will [VP sing ] i if you ask him to [VP e ] i<br />

On the other hand, (233b) is not a necessary assumption. That assumption is linked to<br />

transformational grammar. Rather than postulating a new rule type that moves constituents to<br />

different positiions leaving behind a co-indexed empty category, supposed we allow [e] to be<br />

directly generated as follows:<br />

(235) XP ÷ [e]<br />

If we allow empty phrases to be generated directly via PS–Rules, then we can give up (233b). All<br />

that remains is to propose principles for finding the referent for [e] something that we need to do<br />

anyway to account for sentences like the following which contain co-indexed constituents:<br />

(236) a. After John i got up, he i had a big breakfast.<br />

b. After he i got up, John i had a big breakfast.<br />

c. First John i entered the room, and then the SOB i insulted the hostess.<br />

Therefore, we do not need transformational rules at all. What we need is a mechanism for relating<br />

[NP e] to full noun phrases, something that is needed anyway. Again, it is useful to stop at this point<br />

and take stock of what we are trying to accomplish. Native speakers of every language completely<br />

understand every possible sentence in their language. The sentence that you are now reading is a<br />

sentence which you have probably never encountered before in your life, and yet you understand<br />

it immediately as you read it. It must be that, at some unconscious level, you understand precisely<br />

the relationships we are trying to uncover. The number of sentences in every language is infinite;<br />

learning a language does not consist of memorizing a list of the possible sentences. Rather, it must<br />

consist of learning the principles upon which every possible sentence is constructed. These<br />

principles form native speakers’ unconscious knowledge of their language. Throughout this


discussion, we have been trying to ascertain just what this knowledge is, that is, what must native<br />

speakers know to understand all the sentences we have been considering.<br />

3.15 COMMAND RELATIONS IN PHRASE STRUCTURE<br />

We are now in a position to formalize relationships like SUBJECT and OBJECT and to account for<br />

so–called displaced phrases. Consider first (229) recast with the RG innovations as (237).<br />

(237)<br />

In a diagram like (237), it is possible to follow a path from one X category to another. Some paths<br />

prove to be crucial in determining syntactic relationships. One particularly useful relationship in<br />

syntax is the C–COMMAND (for CATEGORY COMMAND) relationship, which we define as<br />

follows:<br />

(238) A node α C–commands a node β if the node immediately above α dominates β.<br />

Applying (238) to the diagram in (237), we see that the N3 the city C–commands the verb burn<br />

because the node immediately above that N3 is the top V3 node and that top V3 node dominates the<br />

verb burn. Similarly, the N3 this book C–commands burn because the node immediately above that<br />

N3 is the V1 in the diagram and that V1 dominates the verb burn.<br />

As we will see, this relationship is at the basis of all the rules for finding the referents of pronouns<br />

in English. For now, we will use it to formally define the functional notions subject–of and<br />

object–of:<br />

(239) a. The subject of some node β is the N3 which most immediately C–commands and<br />

precedes β.<br />

b. The object of some node β is the N3 which most immediately C–commands and<br />

follows β.<br />

The phrase most immediately means ‘is closest to’ or ‘is separated by the fewest number of<br />

intervening nodes in the tree.’<br />

195


196<br />

Given (238) and (239), we determine the subject and object of a verb such as the one diagramed in<br />

(237) as follows:<br />

(240) a. The N3 above city C–commands and precedes the verb burn. The N3 is α; the V0<br />

node burn is β; the node immediately above α, which is the topmost V3 in the<br />

diagram, dominates β. Since α precedes β, α (the city in this example) is the subject<br />

of β (burn).<br />

b. The N3 above book C–commands and follows the verb burn. The N3 is α; the V0<br />

node burn is β; the node immediately above α, which is V1, dominates β. Since α<br />

is to the right of β, α (this book in this example) is the object of β (burn).<br />

The same definitions will work for all the other relevant diagrams in this text. For example, The<br />

Mafia is the subject and drugs the object of ship in (197) and shipment in (198); and Sue is the<br />

subject and mail the object of get in (214).<br />

As we have seen, RG permits the terminal nodes of (203) to dominate two kinds of empty<br />

categories, that is, categories that are phonologically null: [u], which is an understood element in<br />

a sentence like Let’s eat [u]; and [e], which is a bound ANAPHOR, that is, an item that requires a<br />

referent. The availability of [e] together with (238) will account for the interpretation of so–called<br />

displaced constituents. Consider again (231) recast with the RG innovations as (241).<br />

(241)<br />

As in (237), city is the subject of burn. Importantly, book is not the subject. Although the N3 above<br />

book C–commands burn, it does not immediately C–command it. The N3 above city is closer.


In (241), the empty N3 most immediately C–commands and follows burn, so it is the object;<br />

however, it is also an anaphor, so it must have a referent. To find the referent, we use the following<br />

concepts.<br />

(242) IMMEDIATE NEIGHBORHOOD: An immediate neighborhood embraces all phrases<br />

that are dominated by the first X3 above an X3 level prehead characterizer (DET or POS<br />

in N3; CPL or TNS in V3).<br />

(243) EXTENDED NEIGHBORHOOD: An extended neighborhood embraces all X3<br />

recursions above the immediate neighborhood.<br />

(244) THE EMPTY CATEGORY CONDITION (ECC): An empty syntactic category can<br />

only occur in a position that can contain a fully specified phrase.<br />

Given these specifications, consider (241). The tense characterizer PRS is an X3 Level prehead<br />

characterizer; therefore, all items within the first V3 above it are in its immediate neighborhood.<br />

This includes the anaphor [N3 e]. The phrase this book is in a V3 recursion above the immediate<br />

neighborhood; hence, it is in an extended neighborhood. Both this book and the [e] are phrases of<br />

the same type; accordingly, this book is the referent for [e] and the object of burn even though it<br />

precedes the subject.<br />

While the definitions and conditions presented in this section have been simplified for expository<br />

purposes, they nonetheless satisfy all the major difficulties that have been presented in previous<br />

sections. There are, quite naturally, some more difficult examples to be considered, but the essential<br />

direction of the solution presented here is correct and extends, with some elaboration, to other very<br />

complicated examples.<br />

The crucial result of our investigation is that it is possible to formalize even complex relationships<br />

in terms of linear and hierarchical structure. We have succeeded in reducing all phrases to variations<br />

on one frame (203). Furthermore, we have provided formal, explicit definitions of relations like<br />

SUBJECT, OBJECT, REFERENCE, and so on. We have done this without transformational rules.<br />

In short, our entire solution is base on the concept phrase that is rooted in human cognitive capacity.<br />

3.16 EMPTY CATEGORIES<br />

As we have seen, sentences sometimes contain missing elements or gaps which speakers must fill<br />

either from information elsewhere in the sentence or from some general principles. Examples of<br />

sentences with gaps are the following:<br />

(245) a. You can come if you want to ____.<br />

b. He shrugged ____.<br />

197


198<br />

Native speakers know intuitively that the gaps in the above sentences should be filled as follows:<br />

(246 ) a. You can come if you want to come.<br />

b. He shrugged his shoulders.<br />

There are two major types of empty categories in language: [e], a bound element that has a referent<br />

somewhere inside the same sentence, and [u], an understood element. Consider the following<br />

examples, where [1] is the sentence as it is spoken, where [2] indicates the way it must be<br />

understood, and where the subscripts indicate which two elements are bound (refer to each other):<br />

(247) a. [1] You can come if you want to.<br />

[2] You can come i if you want to [e] i. (The [e] is bound to come.)<br />

b. [1] What did he eat today?<br />

[2] What i did he eat [e] i today. (The [e] is bound to what, the logical object of<br />

eat.)<br />

c. [1] He shrugged.<br />

[2] He shrugged [u]. (The [u] indicates some understood phrase.)<br />

Note that [e] is bound to some referent elsewhere in the sentence, but [u] is unbound. In other<br />

words, the meaning of [e] is recovered from information given elsewhere in the sentence, whereas<br />

the meaning of [u] must be supplied by some other general principles. In the case of (247c), shrug<br />

belongs to class of English verbs, body-part verbs, which allow the omission of a specific body-part.<br />

Membership in this class must be learned. For example, the class includes blink, clap, nod, and<br />

wave, but not braid, crane, pluck, or sprain. While it’s possible to say She blinked, it is not possible<br />

to say *She sprained. Speakers must simply learn which verbs allow an understood body-part.<br />

As the above examples indicate, an empty category can only occur in a position that can contain a<br />

fully specified phrase. Each [e] and [u] above can be replaced by a fully specified phrase. [u]<br />

occurs in a position that can contain an NP; [e] occurs in a position that can contain its referent.<br />

Conversely, [e] and [u] cannot occur where fully specified phrases cannot occur:<br />

(248) a. John persuaded Bill that Mary should go.<br />

b. *John persuaded Bill Mary to go.<br />

c. *Who i did John persuade Bill [e] i to go?<br />

(249) a. He donates money to charities.<br />

b. He donates [u] to charities.<br />

c. *He donates charities money.<br />

d. *He donates charities [u].<br />

Given the above, we can add the following condition to our grammar:


(250) THE EMPTY CATEGORY CONDITION (ECC)<br />

An empty syntactic category can only occur in a position that can contain a fully specified<br />

phrase.<br />

The data above indicate clearly that grammars must contain empty categories as well as rules for<br />

where empty categories can or must occur. Understandably, the matter can be complicated.<br />

Consider, for example, the following sentence:<br />

(251) Who did John promise that Bill would visit?<br />

This sentence has two possible meanings, which are disambiguated by the following representations:<br />

(252) a. Who i did John promise [e] i that Bill would visit [u]?<br />

b. Who i did John promise [u] that Bill would visit [e] i?<br />

In (252a), the question being asked is who John promised, whereas in (252b) the question being<br />

asked is who Bill would visit. Note that only [e] is bound to who, and that empty categories can<br />

occur in the middle of sentences.<br />

For a sentence like Who did John promise that bill, the grammar must generate the following:<br />

(253) Who i did John promise [e] i that bill?<br />

Note that (254) should not generated because then there would be no slot for an [e] bound to who:<br />

(254) *Who did John promise [u] that bill?<br />

Declarative variants of (254) do tolerate a [u] in object position for some speakers:<br />

(255) a. John promised me that bill.<br />

b. John promised [u] that bill. (cf. I never promised you/[u] a rose garden.)<br />

Crucially, [e] and [u] must occur in every WH–question where a verb allows a [u] object; otherwise,<br />

grammars would not produce the correct reading for classic examples like the following:<br />

(256) a. What i did the teacher read [u] to the children from [e] i?<br />

b. *What i did the teacher read [e] i to the children from [u]?<br />

An important feature of empty categories is that they block contraction so that grammars of natural<br />

languages must contain the following condition:<br />

199


200<br />

(257) THE CONTRACTION BLOCK CONDITION (CBC)<br />

Contraction is not possible over an empty category.<br />

Examples of this condition involving [e] include the following:<br />

(258) a. Who i did you want [e] i to win the race?<br />

b. *Who did you wanna win the race?<br />

(259) a. Could i we [e] i have gone there?<br />

b. *Could we’ve gone there? (cf. We’ve gone there.)<br />

The empty [e] found in passive constructions also blocks contraction:<br />

(260) a. He i was dared [e] i to challenge her.<br />

b. *He was [dærDc] challenge her. (cf. Did he [dærDc] challenge her?)<br />

(261) a. John i is said [e] i to be a good teacher.<br />

b. *John is [seDc] be a good teacher.<br />

The empty category [u] also blocks contraction:<br />

(262) a. Sue will now dress [u] to get ready for the prom. (reflexive object understood)<br />

b. *Sue will now [dresc] get ready for the prom.<br />

(263) a. They met [u] to discuss the wedding. (reciprocal object understood)<br />

b. *They [meDc] discuss the wedding.<br />

(264) a. Sue will nod [u] to indicate her approval. (understood body part)<br />

b. *Sue will [naDc] indicate her approval.<br />

(265) a. They eat [u] to live. ([u] = some type of food)<br />

b. *They [iDc] live.<br />

The CBC also extends to idioms such as the following where a very specific N3 is understood:<br />

(266) a. Did they get a chance to see that play when they were in town?<br />

b. Did they get [u] to see that play when they were in town.<br />

c. *Did they [geDc] see that play when they were in town.<br />

Examples like (266) contrast with the following where no empty category occurs:<br />

(267) a. They have got to see that play.<br />

b. They’ve [gaDc] see that play.


Consider now a sentence like (268), which must be related to the sentences in (269).<br />

(268) When was Sally interviewed?<br />

(269) a. Someone interviewed Sally at a particular time.<br />

b. Sally was interviewed.<br />

c. Someone interviewed Sally.<br />

The question (268) is clearly related to the statements in (269). Notice that (268) presupposes, in<br />

fact, that there was someone who actually interviewed Sally at a particular time. As a result, the<br />

grammar should give (268) the representation in (270).<br />

(270) When i was j Sally k [e] j interviewed [e] k [e] i?<br />

201<br />

a. The empty category with subscript “i” marks the ordinary position of a phrase<br />

expressing time (compare (269a)).<br />

b. The empty category with subscript “j” marks the ordinary position of the auxiliary<br />

in a sentence (compare (269b)).<br />

c. The empty category with subscript “k” marks the ordinary position of a direct object<br />

(compare (269c)).<br />

It is clear from examples such as the ones above that empty categories are necessary to give<br />

sentences the full interpretation of their meaning. All native speakers know that there is a gap in a<br />

sentence like He can come if he wants to, and that the gap can only be filled by come. As a result,<br />

the complexity that empty categories introduce into a grammar is unavoidable if one wishes to<br />

impart meaning to sentences.<br />

Note that the matter is not simply one of providing a meaningful interpretation to a sentence. Empty<br />

categories are justified in representations on purely <strong>linguistic</strong> grounds. Observe that the following<br />

sentences are ungrammatical:<br />

(271) a. *He wants to.<br />

b. *He admires.<br />

(271a) is ungrammatical because the infinitive construction (the one introduced by to) requires a<br />

verb phrase after the to; similarly, (271b) is ungrammatical because admire is a transitive verb,<br />

meaning it requires a direct object. The following representations satisfy these constraints:<br />

(272) a. He can come i if he wants to [e] i. ([e] i = come)<br />

b. Who i does he admire [e] i?<br />

As these examples indicate, inserting empty categories into syntactic representations is a necessity.<br />

Actually, it is a biological necessity since human beings are not clairvoyant. Elements cannot be<br />

left out of sentences unless there are principles that can recover them, because human beings can’t


202<br />

read minds. In fact, we can propose the following universal condition operative in all human<br />

languages:<br />

(273) THE RECOVERABILITY OF DELETION CONDITION (RDC)<br />

All gaps in sentences must be recoverable.<br />

The ECC, the CBC and the RDC are natural conditions for a grammar to contain. Human beings<br />

are not clairvoyant (generally). Since the ECC stipulates that an empty category can only occur in<br />

a position where a fully specified category can occur, empty categories are associated with positions<br />

where speakers expect something to occur. The RDC stipulates that an empty category in those<br />

positions must be recoverable. The position occupied by [u] is one that is usually filled by a fully<br />

specified phrase; the one occupied by [e] is the position occupied by its referent in a given sentence.<br />

Contraction over empty categories would have the effect of eliminating those positions; in essence,<br />

speakers would be unable to fill the empty positions with appropriate phrases because the empty<br />

positions would have disappeared in contraction.


3.16 THE ENGLISH AUXILIARY<br />

3.16.1 THE FACTS AND GENERALIZATIONS<br />

Chomsky’s original analysis of the English auxiliary, along with subsequent work in the framework<br />

of transformational grammar (TG), revealed a number of important facts about the English auxiliary,<br />

which are summarized in (274).<br />

(274) a. Every English independent clause (S/V3) must contain a tense (TNS) marker:<br />

1. PRS (PRESENT): hunts, has hunted, is hunting<br />

2. PST (PAST): hunted, had hunted, was hunting<br />

3. FUT (FUTURE): will hunt, will have hunted, will be hunting<br />

4. CND (CONDITIONAL): could/would/should hunt<br />

5. IMP (IMPERATIVE): hunt/do hunt<br />

203<br />

b. The verb that carries the TNS marker is always the first verb in the verbal sequence.<br />

This verb also carries agreement: She is hunting/*They is being hunted/*She have<br />

been hunting.<br />

c. Every English clause must also contain a main verb, which is the last verb in the<br />

verbal sequence. This main verb may be empty: The women have hunted, and the<br />

men have [e] too.<br />

d. Every English clause may also optionally contain a MODAL, PERFECTIVE,<br />

PROGRESSIVE, and/or PASSIVE element in that order. Thus:<br />

TNS (MOD) (PERF) (PROG) (PASS)<br />

e. The PERF, PROG, and PASS each consist of an auxiliary verb and a participial affix<br />

which always appears on the next verb in the sequence, whatever that verb is (the<br />

PROG affix is always –ing; the PERF and PASS affixes are –ed in regular verbs):<br />

PERF = have + PFP (PERF PARTICIPLE AFFIX): has hunt–ed<br />

PROG = be + PGP (PROGRESSIVE PARTICIPLE AFFIX): is hunt–ing<br />

PASS = be + PSP (PASSIVE PARTICIPLE AFFIX): is hunt–ed


204<br />

f. Further examples of participles are:<br />

PROGRESSIVE PARTICIPLES PASSIVE/PERFECTIVE PARTICIPLES<br />

hunting hunted<br />

going gone<br />

weeping wept<br />

being been<br />

having had<br />

doing done<br />

These facts are realized in English in sixteen possible auxiliary sequences:<br />

(275) a. Women hunted. TNS<br />

b. Women could hunt. TNS + MOD<br />

c. Women had hunted. TNS + PERF<br />

d. Women were hunting. TNS + PROG<br />

e. Men were hunted. TNS + PASS<br />

f. Women could have hunted. TNS + MOD + PERF<br />

g. Women could be hunting. TNS + MOD + PROG<br />

h. Men could be hunted. TNS + MOD + PASS<br />

i. Women have been hunting. TNS + PERF + PROG<br />

j. Men had been hunted. TNS + PERF + PASS<br />

k. Men were being hunted. TNS + PROG + PASS<br />

l. Women could have been hunting. TNS + MOD + PERF + PROG<br />

m. Men could have been hunted. TNS + MOD + PERF + PASS<br />

n. Men could be being hunted. TNS + MOD + PROG + PASS<br />

o. Men have been being hunted. TNS + PERF + PROG + PASS<br />

p. Men could have been being hunted. TNS + MOD + PERF + PROG + PASS<br />

Listing the possible combinations is hardly an adequate description of English: it attains only<br />

observational adequacy. The TG analysis has gone much further. It notes that all the above<br />

combinations are variations of the sequence in (3).<br />

(276) TNS (MOD) (have + PFP) (be + PGP) (be + PSP) V<br />

The major coup was realizing that the affixes (TNS, PFP, PGP, and PSP) are always associated with<br />

the following verb, whichever happen to come next in the sequence. Given this, a transformational<br />

analysis is necessary; it must take a phrase structure sequence like (3) and distribute the affixes to<br />

the following verb, whatever that might be. Consider the following examples:


(277) TNS + V<br />

PST + hunt<br />

.)))0)))hunted<br />

(278) TNS + MODAL + V<br />

CND + can + hunt<br />

.)))0))))could<br />

hunt<br />

(279) TNS + MODAL + PERF + PROG + V<br />

CND + can + have + PFP + be + PGP + hunt<br />

.)))0)))- .))0))- .)))0)))-<br />

could have been hunting<br />

(280) TNS + PERF + PROG + PASS V<br />

PRS + have + PFP + be + PGP + be + PSP + hunt<br />

.)))0))))- .))0))- .))0)))- .))0))has<br />

been being hunted<br />

205


206<br />

3.16.2 PROBLEMS WITH THE CLASSIC TG ANALYSIS<br />

Despite the elegance of this treatment of the English auxiliary, it was soon realized that it could not<br />

be maintained in its original form as described above. Three major problems were encountered.<br />

First, it was realized that the auxiliary elements (TNS, MOD, PERF, PROG, PASS) do not have the<br />

same range of occurrence possibilities. In particular, the following split exists:<br />

(281) TNS and MOD cannot occur in infinitives (to go) and participles (going):<br />

a. I wanted to be seen.<br />

*I wanted to was seen.<br />

I wanted to be able to drive.<br />

*I wanted to can drive.<br />

b. Being seen with her is a sign of success.<br />

*Wasing seen with her is a sign of success.<br />

Being able to drive is a sign of success.<br />

*Canning (to) drive is a sign of success.<br />

(282) PERF, PROG, and PASS can occur in infinitives and participles:<br />

a. PERF:<br />

It was fun [to have done that].<br />

[Having done that] he left.<br />

b. PROG:<br />

I want [to be working] when he arrives.<br />

?[Being hunting] when you should be working is bad.<br />

c. PASS:<br />

(283) BASIC SPLIT:<br />

He tried [to be seen].<br />

[Being invited to such parties] is not important.<br />

(MOD) TNS – (PERF) (PROG) (PASS) V<br />

This split is confirmed in two ways:


(284) An negative (not) can modify either constituent:<br />

a. He can not attend. (ambiguous)<br />

b. He can’t just not attend.<br />

(285) When the modal occurs, it inverts in questions:<br />

a. Can he go? (cf. He can go.)<br />

b. Won’t they go? (cf. They won’t go.)<br />

Adopting either a TG or RG framework, we can account for the above split with the following<br />

diagrams:<br />

(286) You can not attend.<br />

[ S [ NP you] [ AUX [ TNS [ MOD can]] PRS [ NEG not] ] [ VP [ V attend] ]]<br />

[ V3 [ N3 you] [ C3 [ C0 [ V3 can]] PRS [ C3 not] ] [ V0 attend] ]<br />

[ S [ NP you] [ AUX [ TNS [ MOD can]] PRS ] [ VP [ NEG not] [ V attend] ]]<br />

[ V3 [ N3 you] [ C3 [ C0 [ V3 can]] PRS ] [ V2 [ C3 not] [ V0 attend] ]]<br />

The second problem with the classic TG analysis of the auxiliary concerns the use of do. If a clause<br />

contains only TNS, then the verb do must occur in questions:<br />

(287) a. He will go. Will he go?<br />

b. He has gone. Has he gone?<br />

c. He is going. Is he going?<br />

(288) a. He went. *Went he?<br />

b. He went. Did he go?<br />

This do acts like a modal for two reasons:<br />

(289) a. It carries TNS, agreement, and NEG:<br />

Doesn’t – he – want that?<br />

Don’t – they – want that?<br />

Did – they – want that?<br />

b. It does not occur in infinitives and participles:<br />

*I want to do go there.<br />

*Doing go there is fun.<br />

207


208<br />

This do must be distinguished from the main verb do as follows:<br />

(290) MODAL MAIN VERB<br />

a. He does that.<br />

b. He does see that.<br />

c. He does do that.<br />

d. He doesn’t do that.<br />

e. He does so do that.<br />

But, do (unlike the other modals, e.g., can) cannot occur with PERF, PROG, and/or PASS:<br />

(291) a. He can be working.<br />

b. *He does be working.<br />

c. He could have gone.<br />

d. *He did have gone.<br />

If we treat do as a modal, we can add a constraint to rule out occurrences of do with PERF, PROG,<br />

and/or PASS. Recalling that PERF, PROG, and PASS all consist of a verb, we can add filter (292)<br />

to our grammar (where W, X, Y and Z are variables):<br />

(292) a. TG: *[ S W do X TNS Y V Z]<br />

b. RG: *[ V3 W do X TNS Y V Z]<br />

This filter, like most syntactic filters in English, is under a clause constraint, meaning that the listed<br />

morphological elements do and TNS must be in the same clause (S or V3). This proviso is<br />

necessary to disallow *he does be going while allowing does he think he is going.<br />

Given this analysis, do occupies the same residence as the modals generally do in addition to main<br />

verb position:<br />

(293) He does not do that.<br />

[ S [ NP he] [ AUX [ TNS [ MOD does] PRS] [ NEG not] ] [ VP do that] ]<br />

[ V3 [ N3 he] [ C3 [ C0 [ V3 does] PRS] [ C3 not] ] [ V0 do that] ]<br />

The third problem with the classic TG analysis of the auxiliary is the most serious. It concerns the<br />

constituency of the various elements. It is here that RG provides an analysis that is superior to the<br />

classic TG analysis. In particular, the classic TG analysis leaves the following facts unexpressed:


(294) The PROG and PASS can occur, as participles, without their associated verbs:<br />

a. The man lurking in the shadows is the culprit.<br />

The man who is lurking in the shadows is the culprit.<br />

b. The man discovered in the bushes is a flasher.<br />

The man who was discovered in the bushes is a flasher.<br />

c. We saw the man hunting.<br />

d. We saw the man hunted.<br />

(295) PGP and PSP forms are ambiguous:<br />

a. an imposing Avon lady<br />

an Avon lady imposing on her neighbors (PARTICIPLE)<br />

an Avon lady imposing in size (ADJECTIVE)<br />

b. a broken vase<br />

a vase accidentally broken by a child (PARTICIPLE)<br />

a vase so broken that it can't be fixed (ADJECTIVE)<br />

These facts can be accommodated within the RG framework by observing that participial markers<br />

behave like characterizers, in particular, like prepositions. Thus, (296a), (296b), (296c), and (296d)<br />

are analogous <strong>structures</strong>; significantly, the post-verbal characterizers (the C3 off V2 to the right of<br />

V0) are independent <strong>structures</strong>, thus allowing for participial examples like those in (294):<br />

(296) a. The jars started to break.<br />

[ V3 [ N3 the jars] [ C3 PST] [ V2 [ V0 started] [ C3 [ C1 [ C0 to ] [ V3 [ V0 break] ]]]]<br />

b. The jars started breaking.<br />

[ V3 [ N3 the jars] [ C3 PST] [ V2 [ V0 started] [ C3 [ C0 [ C0 PGP ] [ V3 [ V0 breaking] ]]]]<br />

c. The jars were breaking.<br />

[ V3 [ N3 the jars] [ C3 PST] [ V2 [ V0 were] [ C3 [ C0 [ C0 PGP ] [ V3 [ V0 breaking] ]]]]<br />

d. The jars were broken.<br />

[ V3 [ N3 the jars] [ C3 PST] [ V2 [ V0 were] [ C3 [ C0 [ C0 PSP ] [ V3 [ V0 broken] ]]]]<br />

209


210<br />

If we treat be as a main verb and treat PGP and PSP as characterizers, we solve the above problems<br />

in (294) and (295). Specifically, we take advantage of the fact that RG makes transparent the many<br />

left-of head/right-of-head alternations that occur in English.<br />

English is a head–center language, that is, one that tolerates elements both before and after the head;<br />

many phrases can occur alternatively in prehead or posthead position. For example, we have noun<br />

phrase pairs like the following:<br />

(297) a. [ N3 the [ N2 Spanish [ N1 math [ N0 teacher]]]]<br />

b. [ N3 the [ N2 [ N1 [ N0 teacher] of math] from Spain]<br />

We have other examples of prehead/posthead alternations like the following:<br />

(298) a. V3: Ultimately, peace will prevail/Peace will prevail, ultimately.<br />

That guy there, he’s my friend./He’s my friend, that guy there.<br />

b. N3: enough money/money enough<br />

as many too many marbles/as many marbles too many<br />

c. C3: quite far down the road/down the road quite far<br />

two miles down the road/down the road two miles<br />

(299) a. V2: enthusiastically sang the aria/sang the aria enthusiastically<br />

often sang the aria/sang the aria often<br />

b. N2: a sleeping baby/a baby sleeping<br />

a 5000 foot high mountain/a mountain 5000 feet high<br />

a courageous man/a man of courage<br />

c. C2: directly down the road for a mile/down the road directly for a mile<br />

especially for Sue/for Sue especially<br />

In English, complements are generally posthead, although there are productive alternatives in noun<br />

phrases (history student versus student of history; *history studied versus studied history) and<br />

participial phrases (French speaking students versus students speaking French). Depending on the<br />

language (head center, head initial, head final), complements generally either precede or follow the<br />

head.<br />

When a verb is embedded in prehead position of PGP or PSP it forms a kind of compound adjective<br />

with the affix; in posthead position, the embedded verb is the complement of the affix:


(300) a. The lady was imposing (PROGRESSIVE).<br />

[ V3 [ N3 the lady] [ C3 PST] [ V2 [ V0 was] [ C3 [ C0 [ C0 PGP ] [ V3 [ V0 imposing] ]]]]<br />

b. The lady was imposing ( DERIVED ADJECTIVE 1).<br />

[ V3 [ N3 the lady] [ C3 PST] [ V2 [ V0 was] [ C3 [ C0 [ V3 [ V0 imposing] ] [ C0 DA1 ] ]]]<br />

(301) a. The jars were broken (PASSIVE).<br />

[ V3 [ N3 the jars] [ C3 PST] [ V2 [ V0 were] [ C3 [ C0 [ C0 PSP ] [ V3 [ V0 broken] ]]]]<br />

b. The jars were broken (DERIVED ADJECTIVE 2).<br />

[ V3 [ N3 the jars] [ C3 PST] [ V2 [ V0 were] [ C3 [ C0 [ V3 [ V0 broken] ] [ C0 DA2 ] ]]]<br />

If we allow that a main verb can be empty [e] and bound to be in the TNS characterizer, we account<br />

for the occurrence of be in questions:<br />

(302) The jars all were broken.<br />

[ V3 [ N3 the jars] [ C3 [ C0 PST] ] [ V2 [ N3 all] [ V0 were] [ C3 broken]] ]<br />

(303) The jars were all broken (PASSIVE). [= All the jars were broken (PASSIVE).]<br />

[ V3 [ N3 the jars] [ C3 [ C0 were i [ C0 PST]] ] [ V2 [ N3 all] [ V0 [e] i] [ C3 broken]] ]<br />

In the process, we also account for the ambiguity of all.<br />

(304) The jars were all broken (ADJ). [= All the jars were broken (ADJ).]<br />

[ V3 [ N3 the jars] [ C3 [ C0 were i [ C0 PST]]] [ V2 [ N3 all] [ V0 [e] i] [ C3 broken]] ]<br />

(305) The jars were all broken (ADJ). [= The jars were totally broken.]<br />

[ V3 [ N3 the jars] [ C3 [ C0 were i [ C0 PST]]] [ V2 [ V0 [e] i] [ C3 [ N3 all] broken]] ]<br />

(306) The jars were all all broken (ADJ). [= All of the jars were totally broken (ADJ).]<br />

[ V3 [ N3 the jars] [ C3 [ C0 were i [ C0 PST]]] [ V2 [ N3 all] [ V0 [e] i] [ C3 [ N3 all] broken]] ]<br />

The above analysis solves a multitude of problems for English syntax. Notice that the participial<br />

characterizer phrases are all suspended from the V2 level. This is the residence in RG of predicate<br />

nominatives: items suspended from this position refer back to the subject. Consider the following<br />

sentences and their associated RG diagrams:<br />

211


212<br />

(307) The boys made good cooks. (make is copulative)<br />

[ V3 [ N3 the boys] [ C3 [ C0 PST]] [ V2 [ V0 made] [ N3 good cooks] ] ]<br />

(308) The boys made good cakes. (make is transitive)<br />

[ V3 [ N3 the boys] [ C3 [ C0 PST]] [ V1 [ V0 made] [ N3 good cakes] ] ]<br />

Observe that the only structural difference between (307) and (308, 309) is that the postverbal N3<br />

in (307) comes off V2, while the one in (308, 309) comes off the V1. This is in accordance with the<br />

RG residential requirements: predicate nominatives are V2 level elements; direct objects are V1<br />

level elements. Since predicate nominatives refer back to the subject, they must agree with the<br />

subject. In short, the syntactic hierarchy of RG accounts automatically for all of the following:<br />

(309) Faulty agreement between subject and V2 level predicate nominative phrase:<br />

a. *The boys became a good cook.<br />

b. *The boy made good cooks.<br />

c. *The boy is pregnant.<br />

d. *The boys made (became) coffee.<br />

e. *The coffee is broken.<br />

(310) No need for agreement between subject and V1 level direct object phrase:<br />

a. The boys made a good cake.<br />

b. The boy made good cakes.<br />

c. The boy made the girl pregnant.<br />

d. The boys made coffee.<br />

(311) There is often ambiguity between V1 and V2 level elements.<br />

a. John left the house messy. (= John was messy when he left the house.)<br />

[ V3 John PST [ V2 [ V1 [ V0 left] [ N3 the house]] [ C3 messy]]]<br />

b. John left the house messy. (= The house was left messy by John.)<br />

[ V3 John PST [ V1 [ V0 left] [ N3 the house] [ C3 messy]]


(312) The order must be V1 level elements before V2 level elements in post verbal position.<br />

a. John [ V2 [ V1 left the house unlocked] ]<br />

b. John [ V2 [ V1 left the house] dazed ]<br />

c. John [ V2 [ V1 left the house unlocked] dazed ]<br />

d. *John [ V2 [ V1 left the house dazed] unlocked ]<br />

Since the structure of (312) parallels (307) as regards predicate nominative position, agreement<br />

between participles and subjects is automatically accounted for:<br />

(313) a. The terrorist was undaunted by threats.<br />

1. *Threats undaunted the terrorist.<br />

2. *The lamp was undaunted by threats.<br />

b. The men were undivided.<br />

1. *That man was undivided.<br />

2. *We undivided those men.<br />

c. The men were divided (ambiguously adjective or participle).<br />

1. I am divided. (adjective only)<br />

2. *These conflicts are dividing me.<br />

Of course, an added plus for this analysis is that case/number/gender agreement between subjects<br />

and predicate nominatives (including participles) in languages like Latin, French, etc., is directly<br />

accounted for.<br />

Given the above, it follows that we can analyze PERFECTIVE have in either of two ways (recall<br />

that the emphatic so is part of the TNS characterizer):<br />

(314) a. They [could have so] [gone].<br />

b. They [could so] [have gone].<br />

There is, in fact, support for assuming that have can occur in each one of the two above positions.<br />

It must be in V3 when it occurs in infinitives and participles:<br />

(315) a. For him [to have done that] is awful.<br />

b. [Having done that] he left.<br />

In cases like (315), we know that have cannot be in the tense characterizer, because TNS cannot<br />

occur in infinitives and participles. However, have must be in the TNS characterizer in questions<br />

and in certain elliptical clauses:<br />

213


214<br />

(316) a. Have they done that?<br />

b. He has done that, and so has she _______.<br />

The two positions for have in (314) are, in fact, fairly fixed positions in English syntax: the tense<br />

characterizer and the main verb. Perhaps, for this reason, have seems to float back and forth<br />

between the two possible <strong>structures</strong>, required in the one to account for (315), and in the other to<br />

account for (316). We document this fluctuation with the following two representations for<br />

PERFECTIVE have:<br />

(317) Perfective have is part of the TNS characterizer:<br />

[ V3 [ N3 he] [ C3 [ C0 [ V3 [ V0 has]] PRS ]] [ V0 gone] ]<br />

(318) Perfective have is part of the verb phrase:<br />

[ V3 [ N3 he] [ C3 PRS ] [ V2 [ V3 [ V0 has]] [ V0 gone]] ]<br />

3.16.3 RESOLUTION<br />

The complete English auxiliary is, therefore, the following:<br />

(319) The jars could so have been being broken.<br />

[ V3 [ N3 the jars] [ C3 [ C0 could [ C0 CND]] so ]<br />

[ V3 have [ V2 [ V0 been]<br />

[ C3 [ C0 [ C0 PGP] [ V3 [ V2 [ V0 being]<br />

[ C3 [ C0 [ C0 PSP] [ V3 [ V0 broken]]]] ]]]]]]]<br />

Additional support for the above analysis comes from the behavior of so-called "floating" quantifiers<br />

like all:<br />

(320) a. All of the men could have gone fishing.<br />

b. The men all could have gone fishing.<br />

c. The men could all have gone fishing.<br />

d. The men could have all gone fishing.<br />

e. *The men could have gone all fishing.<br />

Observe that floating quantifiers can "float" up to the main verb (gone in (320)).We see the same<br />

paradigm in (320) in all of the following:


(321) a. All of the men could have been six-feet tall.<br />

b. The men all could have been six-feet tall.<br />

c. The men could all have been six-feet tall.<br />

d. The men could have all been six-feet tall.<br />

e. *The men could have been all six-feet tall.<br />

(322) a. All of the men could have been fishing.<br />

b. The men all could have been fishing.<br />

c. The men could all have been fishing.<br />

d. The men could have all been fishing.<br />

e. *The men could have been all fishing.<br />

(323) a. All of the men could have been seen.<br />

b. The men all could have been seen.<br />

c. The men could all have been seen.<br />

d. The men could have all been seen.<br />

e. *The men could have been all seen.<br />

(324) a. All of a men could have been aware of a problem.<br />

b. The men all could have been aware of a problem.<br />

c. The men could all have been aware of a problem.<br />

d. The men could have all been aware of a problem.<br />

e. *The men could have been all aware of a problem.<br />

(325) a. All of the jars could have been all broken.<br />

b. The jars all could have been all broken.<br />

c. The jars could all have been all broken.<br />

d. The jars could have all been all broken.<br />

e. *The jars could have been all all broken.<br />

Of course, be is the main verb of all of these sentences in the RG analysis. Accordingly, all of the<br />

data are accounted for. There is no version of TG that can make the same claim.<br />

Notice, in addition, that the above analysis treats all uses of be (copular, progressive, and passive)<br />

in the same way, which is necessary given the form of tag questions like the following:<br />

(326) a. They were aware of the problem, weren’t they?<br />

They weren’t aware of the problem, were they?<br />

b. They were fishing, weren’t they?<br />

They weren’t fishing, were they?<br />

c. They were seen, weren’t they?<br />

They weren’t seen, were they?<br />

Given (326), we see that all uses of be repeat be in the tag with opposite polarity. In this regard, all<br />

uses of be work the same way as modals and perfective have:<br />

215


216<br />

(327) a. They could have been aware of the problem, couldn’t they?<br />

They couldn’t have been aware of the problem, could they?<br />

b. They have been aware of the problem, haven’t they?<br />

They haven’t been aware of the problem, have they?<br />

Thus, all auxiliary verbs and all uses of be repeat those verbs in the tag, as opposed to non-auxiliary<br />

verbs, which require a form of do:<br />

(328) a. They went fishing, didn’t they?<br />

They went fishing, did they not?<br />

*They went fishing, weren’t they?<br />

*They went fishing, went they not?<br />

b. They have new cars, don’t they?<br />

They have new cars, do they not?<br />

*They have new cars, haven’t they?<br />

In short, verbs that do not require do-support form their tags without do:<br />

(329) a. *They do be aware of the problem.<br />

b. *They do be fishing.<br />

c. *They do be seen.<br />

d. *They do have gone.<br />

e. *They do can go.<br />

(330) a. They do go fishing.<br />

b. They do have new cars.<br />

c. They do do a good job.<br />

d. They do can tomatoes.<br />

The data above suggest that modals, perfective have, and all uses of be form one class of verbs, say<br />

[+AUX], while all other verbs form another class, say [–AUX].


3.16.4 SUMMARY OF NOMINALS AND VERBALS IN RG<br />

(331) Progressive Participles (PGP) and Derived Adjectives (DA1).<br />

a. Participle (the lady charming the man): [ C3 [ C0 [ C0 PGP] [ V3 [ V0 charming]]]]<br />

b. Adjective (a very charming lady): [ C3 [ C0 [ V3 [ V0 charming]] [ C0 DA1]]]<br />

(332) Passive Participles (PSP) and Derived Adjectives (DA2).<br />

a. Participle (charmed by her flattery): [ C3 [ C0 [ C0 PSP] [ V3 [ V0 charmed]]]]<br />

b. Derived Adjective (a very charmed life): [ C3 [ C0 [ V3 [ V0 charmed]] [ C0 DA2]]]<br />

(333) Gerundial Nominals (GN) and Derived Nominals (DN).<br />

a. GN (charming candy from a baby): [ N3 [ N0 [ N0 GN] [ V3 [ V0 charming]]]]<br />

b. DN: (such charming of snakes): [ N3 [ N0 [ V3 [ V0 charming]] [ N0 DN]]]<br />

(334) Summary of Verbal Structures.<br />

a. Verb resides in posthead position.<br />

[ C3 [ C0 [ C0 PGP] [ V3 [ V0 charming]] ]]<br />

[ C3 [ C0 [ C0 PSP] [ V3 [ V0 charmed]] ]]<br />

[ N3 [ N0 [ N0 GN] [ V3 [ V0 charming]] ]]<br />

b. Verb resides in prehead position.<br />

[ C3 [ C0 [ V3 [ V0 charming]] [ C0 DA1] ]]<br />

[ C3 [ C0 [ V3 [ V0 charmed]] [ C0 DA2] ]]<br />

[ N3 [ N0 [ V3 [ V0 charming]] [ N0 DN] ]]<br />

217


218<br />

3.16.5 PARSES ILLUSTRATING THE ENGLISH AUXILIARY<br />

(335) Imperative Tense: interview them<br />

(336) Present Tense: he interviews them<br />

(337) Past Tense: he interviewed them


(338) Future Tense: he will interview them<br />

(339) Conditional Tense: he would interview them<br />

219


220<br />

(340) Present Tense + Perfective Aspect: he has interviewed them<br />

(341) Present Tense + Progressive Aspect: he is interviewing them


(342) Past Tense + Passive Voice: they were interviewed by him<br />

221


222<br />

(343) Conditional Tense + Perfective Progressive Aspect:<br />

he should have been interviewing them<br />

Structure below need for sentences like He should’ve been interviewing them.<br />

Structure below needed for sentences like Should he have been interviewing them?


(344) Conditional Tense + Perfective Aspect + Passive Voice:<br />

they might have been interviewed by him<br />

223


224<br />

(345) Conditional Tense + Perfective Progressive Aspect + Passive Voice:<br />

they really couldn't all have been being interviewed by him


(346) Conditional Tense + Perfective Progressive Aspect + Passive Voice:<br />

they each could not actually have been being interviewed by him<br />

Another parse has the word not specifying (and, therefore, negating) the modal, which would underlie<br />

the sentence They each couldn’t actually have been being interviewed by him.<br />

225


226


EXERCISES FOR CHAPTER THREE<br />

1. Draw TG diagrams for the DEEP STRUCTURE of the following sentences:<br />

a. The book may be in the library.<br />

b. John will not read those magazines.<br />

c. Mary will send a letter to the company.<br />

d. John reads those magazines.<br />

e. The roses border the fence.<br />

f. The accident occurred at the corner.<br />

g. The plant fell out the window.<br />

h. The boy could take the garbage out.<br />

I. The boy could take out the garbage.<br />

j. The book was not in the library.<br />

2. Collapse each of the following sets of rules into one rule using formal abbreviatory devices<br />

(parentheses and curly brackets):<br />

a. The symbol QNT = QUANTIFIER (more, all, half, etc.)<br />

NP ÷ DET + N<br />

NP ÷ QNT + DET + N<br />

NP ÷ QNT + N<br />

NP ÷ N<br />

b. The symbol AP = ADJECTIVE PHRASE<br />

VP ÷ V<br />

VP ÷ V + PP<br />

VP ÷ V + AP<br />

VP ÷ V + NP<br />

3. As we have noted in the text, the PS–Rules given in (35) are incomplete. They will have to be<br />

revised to accommodate each new structure we consider. Such revisions must be justified by<br />

argument, and the details of proposals must be carefully worked out. Which of the following<br />

sentences can be generated by (89)? Which cannot and, therefore, will require that (89) be<br />

revised? What sort of revisions are necessary?<br />

a. The gardener should water those shrubs with a fine spray.<br />

b. The nearsighted soprano fell into the orchestra pit.<br />

c. They will probably read the assignment reluctantly.<br />

d. A new cook from India prepared all the meals.<br />

e. John thinks Bill will come.<br />

227


228<br />

4. All of the following sentences have the same basic phrase structure, that is, they contain the<br />

same basic units. Keep this in mind as you provide TG diagrams for them.<br />

a. The soprano sang the aria with skill.<br />

b. The young soprano from a small town in the south of France sang the aria with skill.<br />

c. The soprano sang the aria from the third act of an opera by Verdi with skill.<br />

d. The soprano sang the aria with the skill of a seasoned veteran.<br />

e. The young soprano from a small town in the south of France sang the aria from the third<br />

act of an opera by Verdi with the skill of a seasoned veteran.<br />

5. Structurally ambiguous sentences must be given a different diagram for each structural<br />

ambiguity. For example, the sentence Bill may slip on the boots has the following two<br />

diagrams in TG format:<br />

a. For the meaning on the boots, Bill may slip:<br />

b. For the meaning Bill may slip the boots on:


Provide disambiguating diagrams for each of the following ambiguous sentences:<br />

a. The thief hit the lady with the hat.<br />

b. The repair man will look up the street.<br />

c. John left the house messy.<br />

d. The prisoner of war spoke foolishly.<br />

6. What problems, if any, do the following ambiguous sentences pose for the TG model of<br />

grammar?<br />

a. They hired Spanish teachers.<br />

b. They are all finished.<br />

c. They do so love a good meal.<br />

d. We made them idols.<br />

e. They made idols.<br />

7. Draw RG diagrams for the following sentences:<br />

a. The book may be in the library.<br />

b. John will not read those magazines.<br />

c. Mary will send a letter to the company.<br />

d. John reads those magazines.<br />

e. The roses border the fence.<br />

f. The accident occurred at the corner.<br />

g. The plant fell out the window.<br />

h. The boy could take the garbage out.<br />

I. The boy could take out the garbage.<br />

j. The book was not in the library.<br />

8. Draw diagrams for the following sentences in RG framework. What are the advantages of the<br />

X–Bar notation?<br />

a. The gardener should water those shrubs with a fine spray.<br />

b. The nearsighted soprano fell into the orchestra pit.<br />

c. They will probably read the assignment reluctantly.<br />

d. A new cook from India prepared all the meals.<br />

e. John thinks Bill will come.<br />

229


230<br />

9. Draw diagrams for each of the meanings of the following sentences in the RG framework.<br />

Does the X–Bar notation allow you to reach a higher level of descriptive adequacy?<br />

a. The thief hit the lady with the hat.<br />

b. John left the house messy.<br />

c. The repair man will look up the street.<br />

d. The prisoner of war spoke foolishly.<br />

e. They hired Spanish teachers.<br />

f. They made idols.<br />

10. Show that the following sentences must be assigned different structural descriptions no matter<br />

which theory of grammar is adopted.<br />

a. (1) The boys made good cooks.<br />

(2) The boys made good cakes.<br />

Do the same with the following pair:<br />

b. (1) The cars passed in the tunnel.<br />

(2) The boys passed in the tests.


APPENDIX A: ANSWERS TO EXERCISES<br />

1. Draw TG diagrams for the following sentences:<br />

a. The book may be in the library.<br />

b. John will not read those magazines.<br />

c. Mary will send a letter to the company.<br />

231


232<br />

d. John reads those magazines.<br />

e. The roses border the fence.<br />

f. The accident occurred at the corner.<br />

g. The plant fell out the window.


h. The boy could take the garbage out.<br />

I. The boy could take out the garbage.<br />

j. The book was not in the library.<br />

2. Collapse each of the following sets of rules into one rule using formal abbreviatory devices<br />

(parentheses and curly brackets):<br />

a. NP ÷ (QNT) + (DET) + N<br />

b. VP ÷ V + ({ PP, AP, NP})<br />

233


234<br />

3. a. (89) can generate the structure for The gardener should water those shrubs with a fine<br />

spray:<br />

b. (89) cannot generate the structure for The nearsighted soprano fell into the orchestra pit.<br />

The phrase orchestra pit is a compound noun made up of two nouns (orchestra and pit).<br />

The rule (89d) for rewriting NP does not allow an NP to contain two nouns. Note that<br />

orchestra is a noun, not an adjective: it can be made plural (orchestras) and it cannot be<br />

made comparative (*more orchestra).<br />

c. (89) cannot generate the structure for They will probably read the assignment reluctantly.<br />

(89) contains no rule for adverbs. Probably is a sentence adverb (a constituent of S), so<br />

(89a) must be revised to allow an adverb. Reluctantly is a manner adverb (a constituent<br />

of VP), so (89b) must also be revised to allow an adverb.<br />

d. (89) cannot generate the structure for A new cook from India prepared all the meals. All<br />

is a quantifier, and (89d) does not allow for the generation of a quantifier in an NP. The<br />

top line of (89d) would have to be revised as follows:<br />

(QNT) + (DET) + (ADJ) + N + (PP)<br />

e. (89) can generate the structure for John thinks Bill will come.


4. All of the following sentences have the same basic phrase structure, that is, they contain the<br />

same basic units. Keep this in mind as you provide TG diagrams for them.<br />

a. The soprano sang the aria with skill.<br />

b. The young soprano from a small town in the south of France sang the aria with skill.<br />

c. The soprano sang the aria from the third act of an opera by Verdi with skill.<br />

d. The soprano sang the aria with the skill of a seasoned veteran.<br />

e. The young soprano from a small town in the south of France sang the aria from the third<br />

act of an opera by Verdi with the skill of a seasoned veteran.<br />

235


236<br />

5. Provide disambiguating diagrams for each of the following ambiguous sentences:<br />

a. The thief hit the lady with the hat.<br />

(1) =It was with the hat that the thief hit the lady.<br />

(2) =It was the lady with the hat that the thief hit.<br />

b. The (repair) man will look up the street.<br />

Note: Repair man cannot be generated by the rules in (89); it is a compound noun like<br />

orchestra pit in exercise (3b) above. Still, the sentence remains ambiguous without the<br />

word repair in it.<br />

(1) = It is up the street that the man will look.


(2) = The man will look the street up.<br />

c. Ron left the house messy.<br />

(1) = The house was messy when Ron left it.<br />

(2) = Ron was messy when he left the house.<br />

237<br />

Note: While this diagram would appear to be satisfactory to account for the meaning in<br />

which messy modifies Ron, it will prove to be descriptively inadequate when other<br />

sentences are considered. For example, we know that a manner adverb like reluctantly<br />

must be part of the VP (see exercise (5d) below and the explanation for (3c) above).<br />

There are sentences like Ron left the house messy reluctantly, which are still ambiguous<br />

as to whether it is Ron or the house that was left messy. Thus, the above diagram is<br />

descriptively inadequate: since reluctantly must part of the VP in both readings of the<br />

sentence Ron left the house messy reluctantly (it is a manner adverb in both readings),<br />

then messy cannot be outside of the VP as in the above diagram. The standard theory<br />

fails in this case.


238<br />

d. The prisoner of war spoke foolishly.<br />

(1) = The manner in which the prisoner of war spoke was foolish.<br />

(2) = It was foolish of the prisoner of war to speak. (foolishly is a sentence adverb)<br />

6. What problems, if any, do the following ambiguous sentences pose for TG?<br />

Within the TG framework, there is no way to disambiguate any of the following sentences, that<br />

is, PS-Rules, like those in (89), cannot handle the subtle distinctions made.<br />

a. They hired Spanish teachers means either They hired teachers who are Spanish or They<br />

hired teachers of Spanish. Notice that we have They hired Spanish Spanish teachers.<br />

b. They are all finished means either All of them are finished or They are completely<br />

finished. Notice that we have They are all all finished.<br />

c. In They do so love a good meal, so emphasizes do as in They do too love a good meal or<br />

it emphasizes love as in He really loves a good meal.<br />

d. We made them idols means We made them into idols (like We elected them officers) or<br />

We made idols for them (like We bought them presents).<br />

e. They made idols means either They became idols or They created idols. The verb make,<br />

therefore, can be used either as a transitive verb (one that takes a direct object) or as a<br />

copulative verb (one that has a complement which refers back to the subject.


7. Draw RG diagrams for the following sentences:<br />

a. The book may be in the library. (be is a copulative verb; note the V2)<br />

b. John will not read those magazines. (read is a transitive verb; note the V1)<br />

c. Mary will send a letter to the company. (send is a transitive verb; note the V1)<br />

239


240<br />

d. John reads those magazines. (read is a transitive verb; note the V1)<br />

e. The roses border the fence. (border is a transitive verb; note the V1)<br />

f. The accident occurred at the corner. (occur is an intransitive verb; note the V2)<br />

g. The plant fell out the window. (fall is an intransitive verb; note the V2)


h. The boy could take the garbage out. (take is a transitive verb; note the V1)<br />

i. The boy could take out the garbage. (take is a transitive verb; note the V1)<br />

j. The book was not in the library. (be is a copulative verb; note the V2)<br />

241


242<br />

8. Draw diagrams for the following sentences in RG framework. What are the advantages of the<br />

X–Bar notation?<br />

a. The gardener should water those shrubs with a fine spray.<br />

b. The nearsighted soprano fell into the orchestra pit.


c. They will probably read the assignment reluctantly.<br />

d. A new cook from India prepared all the meals.<br />

e. John thinks Bill will come.<br />

243


244<br />

9. a. The thief hit the lady with the hat.<br />

(1) = It was with the hat that the thief hit the lady.<br />

(2) = It was the lady with the hat that the thief hit.


. Ron left the house messy.<br />

(1) = The house was messy when he left it.<br />

(2) = Ron was messy when he left the house.<br />

245


246<br />

c. The repair man will look up the street.<br />

(1) = The repair man will look the street up.<br />

(2) = It is up the street that the repair man will look.


d. The prisoner of war spoke foolishly.<br />

(1) = It was foolish of the prisoner of war to speak.<br />

(2) = The way the prisoner of war spoke was foolish.<br />

247


248<br />

e. They hired Spanish teachers.<br />

(1) = teachers who were Spanish (2) = teachers of Spanish<br />

f. They made idols<br />

(1) = They became idols. (2) = They built idols.<br />

10. a. The following data indicate that The boys made good cooks and The boys made good<br />

cakes must have different structural descriptions:<br />

(1) a. *The boy made good cooks.<br />

b. The boy made good cakes.<br />

(2) a. *Good cooks were made by the boy.<br />

b. Good cakes were made by the boy.<br />

b. The following data indicate that The cars passed in the tunnel and The boys passed in the<br />

tests must have different structural descriptions:<br />

(1) a. *The cars passed the tunnel in.<br />

b. The boys passed the tests in.<br />

(2) a. It was in the tunnel that the cars passed.<br />

b. *It was in the tests that the boys passed.


APPENDIX B: LATIN SYNTAX<br />

Latin verbs must agree with their subjects in number:<br />

1. a. Agricola lupam necat. The farmer kills the wolf.<br />

b. Agricola lupas necat. The farmer kills the wolves.<br />

2. a. Agricolae lupam necant. The farmers kill the wolf.<br />

b. Agricolae lupas necant. The farmers kill the wolves.<br />

Agreement patterns between subjects and verbs:<br />

3. a. Singular: Subject–a–Ø verb–a–t<br />

regin–a–Ø voc–a–t<br />

b. Plural: Subject–a–e verb–a–nt<br />

regin–a–e voc–a–nt<br />

4. a. *Agricola lupas necant.<br />

b. *Agrocilae lupam necat.<br />

Latin adjectives and numerals must agree with the nouns they modify in both number and case:<br />

5. a. Laeta agricola malas lupas duas necat.<br />

‘The happy farmer kills the two bad wolves.’<br />

b. Amicae feminae duae aegras aegricolas duas curant.<br />

‘The two friendly women take care of the two sick farmers.’<br />

Phrase Structure Rules for Latin:<br />

6. a. S ÷ NP + VP<br />

b. VP ÷ NP + V<br />

c. NP ÷ ADJ n<br />

0 + N + (NUM)<br />

249


250<br />

7.<br />

Rules for Case Marking and Rules for Agreement:<br />

8. NP dominated by S is subject; all elements of that NP are in the nominative case (–Ø if<br />

singular, –e if plural).<br />

9. NP dominated by VP is object; all elements of that NP are in the accusative case (–m if<br />

singular, –s if plural).<br />

10. If the subject is singular, verb ends in –t; if the subject is plural, verb ends in –nt.<br />

After these rules apply to the above tree, the grammar generates the sentence Aminae feminae duae<br />

aegras agricolas duas curant.<br />

Vocabulary:<br />

11. Nouns (quoted in the nominative singular feminine form):<br />

lupa ‘wolf’ luna ‘moon’ regina ‘queen’ agricola ‘farmer’<br />

stella ‘star’ casa ‘cottage’ fabula ‘story’ domina ‘mistress’<br />

12. Adjectives (quoted in the nominative singular feminine form):<br />

mala ‘bad’ pulchra ‘pretty’ multa ‘many’ clara ‘famous’<br />

bona ‘good’ amica ‘friendly’ inimica ‘unfriendly’ laeta ‘happy’<br />

13. Verbs (quoted in the infinitive form):<br />

liberare ‘free’ vocare ‘call’ laudare ‘praise’ aedificare ‘build’<br />

necare ‘kill’ curare ‘care for’ adorare ‘worship’ superare ‘conquer’<br />

14. Others:<br />

non ‘not’ et ‘and’


APPENDIX C: SUMMARY OF TREE STRUCTURES<br />

1. Traditional grammar (confuses functional and structural categories):<br />

2. Structural grammar and TG (not enough internal levels for phrases):<br />

3. X–bar grammar and RG:<br />

4. Sentence with a transitive verb (John studies Latin):<br />

251


252<br />

5. Noun phrase structure (John’s study of Latin...):<br />

6. Noun phrase structure (all the/Ø study of Latin...):


7. Sentence with an intransitive (John died happy/happily) or copulative verb (John was happy):<br />

253


254


4.1 PRELIMINARY REMARKS<br />

CHAPTER FOUR: SEMANTICS<br />

Of all of the areas of grammar which linguists have studied, by far the most puzzling and problematic<br />

is semantics, the area which concerns the meanings of words and sentences. Despite the efforts of<br />

numerous linguists, philosophers, psychologists, and anthropologists, a number of very fundamental<br />

questions remain unanswered both in regard to the meaning of words and to the meaning of<br />

sentences. Consider, for example the question of what a particular word, say, table, means. It is clear<br />

that when native speakers of English use the word table, they are referring to a specific object and<br />

recognize in that object certain identifiable characteristics which make the use of table appropriate.<br />

Still, it is exceedingly difficult to determine what these identifiable characteristics are, considering<br />

all of the various types of objects which are called a table. Even words such as dog and cat present<br />

problems. Although a biologist could give a highly specific definition of both of these animals by<br />

referring to particular anatomical and physiological features, it is obvious that the average speaker<br />

does not distinguish a dog from a cat by referring to such features, e.g., that a dog has two upper<br />

molar teeth while a cat has only one. When words such as beauty, love, and joy are brought into the<br />

picture, the problem of providing definitions reaches nearly unmanageable proportions, for words<br />

such as these, in addition to referring to intangible objects, also vary considerably in meaning from<br />

speaker to speaker and language to language. Semantic analysis typically raises wicked problems<br />

in the sense mentioned in the Introduction (Page 5).<br />

In translating from one language to another, these problems are compounded because the sphere of<br />

objects named by a particular word is rarely the same from language to language. For example, the<br />

English word uncle can refer either to one’s mother’s brother or one’s father’s brother (among<br />

others). In Latin, these two relatives are distinguished by separate words: avunculus is one’s<br />

maternal uncle, and patruus is one’s paternal uncle. This distinction was important in ancient Rome<br />

to designate who a minor’s guardian would be upon the death of parents. In general, kinship terms<br />

vary greatly from language to language, reflecting social custom and law. The same can be said<br />

about words to designate color, shape, time, place, and many other categories. One successful<br />

approach to describing such cultural differences has been to break the categories down to features<br />

and describe the different classes as different arrangements of features. We will take this approach<br />

in analyzing English prepositions. The important point to keep in mind now is that any child can<br />

learn any of these systems as part of his native language. Such cultural differences, therefore, must<br />

reflect innate abilities of human perception and categorization.<br />

4.2 DENOTATION AND CONNOTATION<br />

In an effort to cope with the problem of definition, semanticists have recognized a number of useful<br />

distinctions in the meaning of a word. One of these is the distinction between DENOTATION and<br />

CONNOTATION. The denotative meaning of a word is its specific, exact meaning, excluding all<br />

of its extended uses and emotional colorations. On the other hand, a connotative meaning is any<br />

meaning which carries some special implication or association. Thus, in (1) the word fox is used in


256<br />

its denotative meaning to refer to a specific animal, while in (2) it is used in a connotative meaning<br />

to imply a crafty person.<br />

(1) A hungry fox was seen prowling around the chicken coop.<br />

(2) Mary doesn’t trust John, because he’s such a fox.<br />

4.3 SYNONYMY, HOMONYMY, AND ANTONYMY<br />

Other terms often used by semanticists in defining words and indicating relationships among them<br />

include SYNONYM, HOMONYM, and ANTONYM. Two words are synonyms if they are<br />

pronounced differently, but mean the same thing, e.g., huge and enormous (adjectives), oculist and<br />

eye doctor (nouns), imprison and incarcerate (verbs) ; they are homonyms if they are pronounced<br />

the same, but have different meanings, e.g., bank (river’s edge) and bank (financial institution); they<br />

are antonyms if they mean opposite things, e.g., hot and cold (adjectives), love and hate (nouns or<br />

verbs).<br />

Antonyms fall into two groups: complementary and gradable. Complementary anonyms are absolute<br />

opposites like male and female, dead and alive, present and absent, etc., in which the negative of one<br />

is synonymous with the other. Thus, if one is not male, one is female; or, if one is not female, one<br />

is male. Gradable anonyms are not absolute opposites; the negative of one is not synonymous with<br />

the other, e.g., fast and slow, big and little, etc.<br />

4.4 HYPONYMY/HYPERNYMY AND MERONYMY/HOLONYMY<br />

Semanticists also make distinctions between HYPONYMY/HYPERNYMY which is the<br />

member/class distinction; for example, robin is a hyponym of bird, and bird is a hyponym of animal.<br />

Such relationships are TRANSITIVE, which means that the reverse relationship also holds: animal<br />

is a hypernym of bird, and bird is a hypernym of robin.<br />

Closely related is the distinction between MERONYMY and HOLONYMY, that is, the part/whole<br />

relationship; for example, ceiling is a meronym or room, and room is a meronym of house. This<br />

distinction is also transitive: house is a holonym of room, and room is a holonym of ceiling.<br />

4.5 IDIOMS<br />

Semanticists also make a distinction between idiomatic and non–idiomatic meaning. An IDIOM is<br />

a highly specialized expression whose meaning typically cannot be deduced from the meaning of the<br />

words out of which it is composed. Expressions like shoot the breeze, be up tight, and so long are<br />

examples of idioms. In most instances, idioms are fixed in usage and cannot be expanded or<br />

modified. For example, one cannot say *We shot a southwesterly breeze yesterday.


(3) a. We were shooting the breeze.<br />

1. *We were shooting a southwesterly breeze.<br />

2. We were cheerfully shooting the breeze.<br />

3. We shot the tigers./The tigers were shot by us.<br />

4. We shot the breeze./*The breeze was shot by us.<br />

b. He was pulling your leg.<br />

257<br />

1. Were you pulling my (her, John’s) leg?<br />

2. Were you pulling (*yanking, tugging) my leg (*arm, hair).<br />

3. Sue’s leg’s been pulled so many times that she doesn’t trust anyone anymore.<br />

On the other hand, idioms must be assigned a syntactic structure because they are subject to rules.<br />

For example, consider the rule of Particle Movement (the movement of an intransitive preposition)<br />

as it applies in the following:<br />

(4) Particle Movement.<br />

a. The teacher handed out the assignment.<br />

The teacher handed the assignment out.<br />

b. The teacher spoke about the assignment.<br />

*The teacher spoke the assignment about.<br />

c. John gave away the show.<br />

John gave the show away.<br />

d. John beats around the bush.<br />

*John beats the bush around.<br />

e. Further examples: bark up the wrong tree, bring down the house, go off the deep end,<br />

jump down one’s throat, lay down the law, let down one’s hair, make up one’s mind,<br />

pay through the nose, sit on the fence<br />

4.6 AMBIGUITY AND PARAPHRASE<br />

In the study of meaning, linguists have also been concerned with AMBIGUITY and<br />

PARAPHRASE. There are a great many pairs of words, phrases or sentences in all languages which<br />

are ambiguous, that is, which are phonologically identical but semantically distinct; others are<br />

paraphrases, that is, phonologically distinct but semantically similar.


258<br />

(5) AMBIGUITY (one sound, more than one meaning).<br />

a. Lexical level, the level of the word.<br />

1. After making the right turn at the corner,...<br />

2. After making the left turn at the corner,...<br />

b. Phrasal level.<br />

1. He looked over the fence.<br />

2. He looked under the fence.<br />

c. Sentential level.<br />

1. Visiting relatives can be boring.<br />

2. The chickens are ready to eat.<br />

3. What worried John was being ignored by everybody.<br />

(6) PARAPHRASE (one basic meaning, more then one sound).<br />

a. Lexical level.<br />

1. They murdered/killed the president.<br />

2. Mary picked up the pail/bucket.<br />

b. Phrasal level.<br />

1. John resembles Bill./John is similar to Bill.<br />

2. John is a father./John has children.<br />

c. Sentence level.<br />

1. The bees are swarming in the garden./The garden is swarming with bees.<br />

2. John is easy to please./It is easy to please John.<br />

(7) Disambiguating sentences with paraphrase.<br />

a. Moving vehicles can be hazardous.<br />

1. Vehicles which are moving can be hazardous.<br />

2. It can be hazardous to move vehicles.


. The baby is too young to stand up.<br />

1. The baby is too young for someone to stand up.<br />

2. The baby is too young to stand up by itself/himself/herself.<br />

Most native speakers are unaware of ambiguity when it occurs because context favors one meaning<br />

over others. The task of the linguist is to ascertain what differences, if any, there are between each<br />

member of the ambiguous pair. Very often, the members can be shown to be syntactically distinct.<br />

For example, when sentence (7a) receives the first interpretation, the word vehicles is the subject of<br />

the word move, and when the sentence receives the second interpretation, vehicles is the object of<br />

move.<br />

4.7 PRAGMATICS<br />

Beyond these considerations, most of the problems in sentence meaning which linguists have been<br />

especially interested in concern either the relationship between semantics and the other components<br />

of grammar, particularly syntax and phonology, or the relationship between semantics and such<br />

extra–<strong>linguistic</strong> or PRAGMATIC facts as the beliefs and knowledge a person has about the world.<br />

The interaction of phonology and semantics is clearly illustrated in the following set of examples<br />

(upper–case type indicates heavy stress):<br />

(8) a. After John complimented Mary, SHE complimented HIM.<br />

b. *After John complimented Mary, she COMPLIMENTED him.<br />

c. *After John complimented Mary, SHE insulted HIM.<br />

d. After John complimented Mary, she INSULTED him.<br />

Notice that the pronouns in the second half of these sentences receives stress only when the meaning<br />

of the verbs in both halves is identical. When the meaning of the verbs in both halves is not identical,<br />

then the verbs themselves receive the heavy stress. This is an example of how the phonological rules<br />

of a language can depend on semantic structure.<br />

Lastly, notice that the interpretation of the following sentences depends on specific beliefs that people<br />

have.<br />

(9) a. After John called Mary a republican, SHE complimented HIM.<br />

b. After John called Mary a republican, she COMPLIMENTED him.<br />

c. After John called Mary a republican, SHE insulted HIM.<br />

d. After John called Mary a republican, she INSULTED him.<br />

(10) a. Both of John’s parents are schizophrenics, and it looks as though John is crazy too.<br />

b. Both of John’s parents are skydivers, and it looks as though John is crazy too.<br />

c. Both of John’s parents are engineers, and it looks as though John is crazy too.<br />

259


260<br />

For most speakers of English, the sentiment expressed in (10a) would be considered reasonable, since<br />

they know that schizophrenia is a form of mental illness, and the one in (10c) would be considered<br />

unreasonable, since most people do not equate engineering with insanity. The status of (10b), on the<br />

other hand, would probably vary. If people are skydivers, they are likely to find it unreasonable;<br />

however, other people, who believe that anyone willing to jump out of a plane without immediately<br />

opening a parachute is insane, would find (10b) reasonable.<br />

4.8 THEMATIC RELATIONS: CASE GRAMMAR<br />

One of the best understood areas of semantics concerns the roles that various noun phrases fulfill in<br />

a sentence, roles such as AGENT and INSTRUMENT. The research was originally carried out by<br />

Charles Fillmore in the 1960s and became known as CASE GRAMMAR because of its similarity<br />

with the study of grammatical case in traditional grammar. Over the past thirty years, case relations<br />

have been investigated by many other linguists in a variety of theoretical frameworks. Many scholars<br />

have pointed out that the SEMANTIC FUNCTION (AGENT or INSTRUMENT) that a noun phrase<br />

has in a sentence often appears to be of greater significance than its SYNTACTIC FUNCTION<br />

(SUBJECT or OBJECT). For example, although the syntactic function of the noun phrase the door<br />

in (11) changes, its semantic function does not.<br />

(11) a. The door will open. door is subject<br />

b. The janitor will open the door. door is object<br />

c. The door will open with this key. door is subject<br />

d. This key will open the door. door is object<br />

There are many similar cases in English and other languages such as those in (12).<br />

(12) a. John broke the dish. dish is object<br />

b. The dish broke. dish is subject<br />

c. John started the car. car is object<br />

d. The car started. car is subject<br />

e. John woke up the baby. baby is object<br />

f. The baby woke up. baby is subject<br />

Consider also the various roles that the subject children plays in the following:<br />

(13) a. Children walk easily.<br />

b. Children fall easily.<br />

c. Children frighten easily.<br />

d. Children cry easily.


The role of a noun phrase in relation to a particular verb determines not only how it will be<br />

understood in a sentence, but also how it will behave. For example, in (14) Mary can be understood<br />

as either an ACCOMPANIER or as an INSTRUMENT.<br />

(14) John broke the window with Mary.<br />

As (15) shows, different roles cannot usually be combined.<br />

(15) a. John broke the window. (John is agent)<br />

b. A hammer broke the window. (hammer is instrument)<br />

c. *John and a hammer broke the window.<br />

Relations like AGENT, ACCOMPANIER and INSTRUMENT, which specify the role that a noun<br />

phrase plays in a sentence, are called CASE RELATIONS or THEMATIC RELATIONS. In his<br />

earliest formulations, Fillmore proposed the following case relations:<br />

(16) AGENTIVE: the case of the typically animate perceived instigator of the action identified<br />

in the verb (often simply called AGENT).<br />

a. JOHN opened the door.<br />

b. The door was opened BY JOHN.<br />

(17) INSTRUMENTAL: the case of the inanimate force or object causally involved in the<br />

action or state identified in the verb.<br />

a. THE HAMMER broke the window.<br />

b. The window was broken WITH THE HAMMER.<br />

c. THE HURRICANE destroyed the village.<br />

(18) OBJECTIVE: the semantically most neutral case; typically the case of the thing directly<br />

affected by the action or state identified in the verb. (Not to be confused with the notion<br />

direct object; often called PATIENT or THEME)<br />

a. Someone opened THE DOOR. (door is both direct object and objective case.)<br />

b. THE DOOR opened. (door is subject, but still objective case.)<br />

(19) DATIVE: the case of the usually animate entity affected by the state or action identified<br />

in the verb (often called EXPERIENCER or RECIPIENT).<br />

a. John gave the book TO BILL.<br />

b. BILL received the book.<br />

c. The movie appeals to HIM.<br />

d. THE SNOW melted.<br />

261


262<br />

(20) POSSESSIVE: the case of the possessor.<br />

a. JOHN’S book is on the table.<br />

b. JOHN owns that book.<br />

(21) LOCATIVE: the case which identifies the location or spatial orientation of the state or<br />

action identified in the verb.<br />

a. It happened IN ITALY.<br />

b. The book is ON THE TABLE.<br />

(22) GOAL: the case which identifies the direction of the state or action identified in the verb.<br />

a. John flew TO ITALY.<br />

b. John ran INTO THE HOUSE.<br />

(23) SOURCE: the case which identifies the origin of the state or action identified in the verb.<br />

a. John flew FROM ITALY.<br />

b. John ran OUT OF THE HOUSE.<br />

Given an inventory of thematic relations like the above, a linguist can specify the roles that noun<br />

phrases play with particular verbs. For example, we can characterize the verb open as follows:<br />

(24) a. It requires an OBJECTIVE and tolerates an INSTRUMENTAL and/or AGENTIVE.<br />

b. If only the OBJECTIVE NP occurs, it must be the subject:<br />

[1] The door can open. ACTIVE<br />

[2] The door will be opened. PASSIVE<br />

c. If the INSTRUMENTAL also occurs, either the OBJECTIVE or the<br />

INSTRUMENTAL can be subject.<br />

[1] The door can open with a key. ACTIVE<br />

[2] The door can be opened with a key. PASSIVE<br />

[3] A key can open the door. ACTIVE<br />

d. If the OBJECTIVE and the AGENTIVE occur, either can be subject.<br />

[1] A janitor can open the door. ACTIVE<br />

[2] The door can be opened by a janitor. PASSIVE


e. If all three cases occur, either the AGENTIVE or the OBJECTIVE can be subject, but<br />

the INSTRUMENTAL cannot.<br />

[1] A janitor can open the door with a key. ACTIVE<br />

[2] The door can be opened with a key. PASSIVE<br />

[3] *A key can open the door by a janitor.<br />

As these examples indicate, the thematic relation of an NP in English is signaled overtly by a<br />

preposition unless that NP is a subject or object. For example, the instrumental relation is signaled<br />

by the preposition with except when the instrument is in subject position (cf. (24c3)). Fillmore<br />

argued that this indicates that the case relations should be directly represented in DEEP<br />

STRUCTURE, and that subject and object should be derived from full prepositional phrases in<br />

English. For example, he proposed that the deep structure of (25a) would be something like (25b).<br />

(25) a. The janitor will open the door with the key.<br />

b. [ S [ AUX will] [ VP [ V open] [ PP of the door] [ PP by the janitor] [ PP with the key] ]]<br />

Rules of SUBJECT FORMATION and OBJECT FORMATION then turn these <strong>structures</strong> into<br />

<strong>structures</strong> of the more familiar type like (26).<br />

(26) [ S [ NP the janitor] [ AUX will] [ VP [ V open] [ NP the door] [ PP with the key] ]]<br />

4.9 THE MEANING AND USE OF THE WORD CASE<br />

In a description such as the above, an important distinction must be made between THEMATIC or<br />

CASE RELATIONS and the traditional use of case as a label for a particular morphological category.<br />

For example, in Latin, we find inflectional endings like the following:<br />

(27) a. Nominative (–s suffix): the case of the subject.<br />

b. Accusative (–m suffix): the case of the direct object.<br />

[1] Marcus (subject) Publium (direct object) adjuvat. = Marcus helps Publius.<br />

[2] Marcum (direct object) Publius (subject) adjuvat. = Publius helps Marcus.<br />

A term like subject or direct object is a label for a SYNTACTIC RELATION (SYNTACTIC<br />

FUNCTION); these indicate specific positions that a noun phrase occupies in a SYNTACTIC<br />

HIERARCHY like (?). Notice that the subject is the NP immediately dominated by the S node, and<br />

the object is the NP immediately dominated by the VP node. A term like agent or agentive is a label<br />

for a THEMATIC RELATION (SEMANTIC FUNCTION); these specify the various roles that a<br />

noun phrase can play in a sentence. In English, these are usually indicated by prepositions; in<br />

languages like Japanese, they are indicated by postpositions; and in languages like Latin, they are<br />

frequently indicated by inflectional endings called case endings.<br />

263


264<br />

Quite frequently in languages, these functions overlap, so there is some terminological confusion.<br />

Thus, the word case is used for both a morphological category (a case or inflectional ending) or a<br />

semantic category (a case or thematic relation). Compare the following examples.<br />

(28) a. English:<br />

John gave the book to Mary.<br />

b. Japanese:<br />

Taroo wa Hanako ni hon o ageta<br />

Taro SUBJECT Hanako TO book OBJECT gave<br />

‘Taro gave a book to Hanako.’<br />

wa: postposition indicating subject/topic, in this example, the agentive relation<br />

ni: postposition indicating indirect object, in this example, the dative relation<br />

o: postposition indicating direct object, in this example the objective relation<br />

c. Latin:<br />

Marcu–s Publi–o libru–m dabat<br />

Mark–SUBJECT Publius–TO book–OBJECT gave<br />

‘Mark gave a book to Publius.’<br />

–s: nominative case ending indicating subject; here, the agentive relation<br />

–o: dative case ending indicating indirect object; here, the dative relation<br />

–m: accusative case ending indicating direct object; here, the objective relation<br />

As (28c) shows, a term like nominative or accusative is a label for a GRAMMATICAL or<br />

MORPHOLOGICAL FORM. But these terms are also used for both syntactic and semantic<br />

functions. For example, in (28c), Marcus carries the morphological marker for the nominative case<br />

indicating the subject, a syntactic function. But, at another level of analysis, Marcus (still marked<br />

nominative) is also Fillmore’s agentive case, which is a semantic function. Consider the following<br />

example from English:<br />

(29) I saw him.<br />

a. him is direct object:<br />

SYNTACTIC RELATION or SYNTACTIC FUNCTION.<br />

b. him is accusative case:<br />

GRAMMATICAL or MORPHOLOGICAL FORM.<br />

c. him is objective case:<br />

THEMATIC RELATION or SEMANTIC FUNCTION.


Unfortunately, there is even further terminological confusion. Some grammarians use the term<br />

objective case to refer to the grammatical form of the direct object. The term possessive has been<br />

used for all three of the above.<br />

4.10 PROBLEMS WITH CASE GRAMMAR<br />

Regardless of terminology, CASE GRAMMAR has much to recommend it, though it does leave<br />

some facts unaccounted for. For example, this approach leaves unexplained the fact that languages<br />

use the same prepositions (grammatical case/postpositions) to express apparently different thematic<br />

relations.<br />

(30) a. to as Fillmore’s Dative and Goal:<br />

[1] The movie appeals to him. (Dative)<br />

[2] John flew to Italy. (Goal)<br />

b. of as Fillmore’s Agentive, Objective and Possessive:<br />

[1] the crying of babies<br />

[2] the taking of pictures<br />

[3] the shooting of hunters<br />

[4] the pictures of those painters<br />

[a] the pictures painted by those painters<br />

[b] the pictures with those painters in them<br />

[c] the pictures those painters own<br />

Furthermore, CASE GRAMMAR cannot explain why languages use the same markers (prepositions,<br />

postpositions, inflectional endings) for both positional and nonpositional thematic relations as in (31).<br />

(31) [+POSITIONAL] [–POSITIONAL]<br />

He put it into the vase. He turned it into a vase.<br />

He took it out of a vase. He made it out of a vase.<br />

He headed for freedom. He died for freedom.<br />

He withdrew from the heat. He died from the heat.<br />

Although the same marker is used, there is a clear difference between the phrases contrasted in (31).<br />

For example, only a [+POSITIONAL] phrase can be substituted with here, there, where, etc.:<br />

(32) a. Over there is where he put the vase.<br />

b. *Over there is where he turned the vase.<br />

265


266<br />

4.11 RG SEMANTICS<br />

The central hypothesis articulated in the preceding chapters is that the categories of language are<br />

natural classes of features reflective of the nature of the human language apparatus. Further, we have<br />

postulated that languages differ because they select and organize these universal and biologically<br />

determined features differently. If semantic analysis is to parallel the analysis of syntax and<br />

phonology, which one would expect, then one should look first at the categories linguists have<br />

postulated to account for meaning. The largest group of such categories comprises case or thematic<br />

relations.<br />

Over the past twenty–five years, a number of linguists have attempted to incorporate the case<br />

relationships of traditional grammar into formal grammatical theory. All of these efforts have one<br />

thing in common: they attempt to explicate the nature, distribution, and manifestation of thematic<br />

relations like AGENT, INSTRUMENT, SOURCE, GOAL, etc.<br />

Within the entire group of thematic relations that have been proposed in the literature, a basic<br />

division occurs between positional [+PST] and nonpositional [–PST] relations. In the former group,<br />

we have such relations as PLACE and DIRECTION; in the latter, AGENT and PATIENT. For some<br />

reason that is not clear, the former group has been given short shrift by modern theorists, and most<br />

of the attention has been focused on the nonpositional relations. This is a fundamental error, because<br />

the positional relations are more concrete and, therefore, undeniably easier to specify, and because<br />

the nonpositional relations are clearly related to and derived from the positional relations.<br />

Languages, in general, do not have two separate sets of thematic markers (prepositions, postpositions,<br />

grammatical cases, etc.), one for relations that are [+PST], and another for those that are [–PST].<br />

Thus, for example, in the ancient Indo–European languages, all separative relations are expressed by<br />

the ablative case, if there is one. This includes actual perceived movements in the direction away,<br />

e.g., SOURCE, as well as expressions of freedom, deprivation, agency, abandonment, etc. We have<br />

such examples as the following in Latin (33) and Sanskrit (34):<br />

(33) a. Eius milites ab opere (ABLATIVE) vacabant.<br />

‘His soldiers are free from work.’<br />

(Caesar, De Bello Civili, 3, 21)<br />

b. Oculis (ABLATIVE) se privavit.<br />

‘He deprived himself of his eyes.’<br />

(Cicero, De Finibus Bonorum et Malorum, v. 42)<br />

(34) a. nāsmād ganāç (ABLATIVE) chidyate.<br />

‘The people are not cut off from him.’<br />

(Catapatha–Brahmana, 14, 5, 1, 10)<br />

b. sa evainam varunapāçān (ABLATIVE) muñcati.<br />

‘He releases him from Varuna’s snare.’<br />

(Taittiriya–Samhita, 2, 1, 2, 2)


In ancient Greek, which has no ablative case, the separative functions of the ablative are expressed<br />

by the genitive:<br />

(35) a. apostereî me tōn chrēmátōn (GENITIVE).<br />

‘He deprives me of my property.’<br />

(Isocrates, 12, 35)<br />

b. tōn epitēdeíōn (GENITIVE) ouk aporēsomen.<br />

‘We shall not be without provisions.’<br />

(Xenophon, Anabasis, 2, 2, 11)<br />

Whatever the defects of traditional terminology, in the Indo–European languages which have an<br />

ablative, it remains that the ablative is the "from–case"; therefore, all governors (verbs, adjectives,<br />

etc.) having to do with separative notions are construed with the ablative, independent of their<br />

(syntactic) categorial membership. When the ablative is lost as a morphologically distinct case as<br />

in Greek, there is order in the way the functions of the ablative are distributed among the remaining<br />

cases. That order is specified by semantic classes like separative notions. The same situation obtains<br />

in other languages with grammatical case, including those as diverse as Innuit and Finnish: semantic<br />

relationships are grouped into classes, and these classes are realized by the same grammatical case.<br />

When languages do not have elaborate case systems, but express thematic relations with prepositions<br />

(English, Welsh, etc.) or postpositions (Japanese, Hindi, etc.), we find the same basic criterion of<br />

semantic commonality underlying the use of these particles. Consider, for example, the following<br />

data from Italian, which use the same preposition for AGENT, SOURCE, and GOAL:<br />

(36) a. Il meccanico ha riparato la macchina.<br />

the mechanic has repaired the car<br />

‘The mechanic has repaired the car.’<br />

b. La macchina è stata riparata dal meccanico (AGENT).<br />

the car has been repaired by the mechanic<br />

‘The car has been repaired by the mechanic.’<br />

(37) a. Giovanni èsce dal negozio (SOURCE).<br />

Giovanni comes from the store<br />

‘Giovanni is coming from the store’<br />

b. Giovanni trema dal freddo (CAUSE).<br />

Giovanni trembles from the cold<br />

‘Giovanni is trembling from the cold’<br />

Therefore, it is not an accident, for example, that from occurs in separative phrases like the following,<br />

whether or not real movement occurs:<br />

267


268<br />

(38) a. He ran from his office (his father, is responsibilities, etc.)<br />

b. He is back from Europe (the market, unconsciousness, etc.).<br />

c. Keep this away from the children.<br />

d. She can’t tell puce from fuchsia.<br />

e. He can’t find any relief from pain.<br />

f. They’ll be here an hour from now.<br />

g. We got a note from the dean.<br />

h. He died from overexposure.<br />

I. We made it from these instructions.<br />

j. We made it from the materials we had.<br />

In examples like the above, there is a direct connection between positional phrases (from his office)<br />

and nonpositional phrases (from fuchsia), however one wishes to term this connection (denotative<br />

) connotative; literal ) figurative; literal ) metaphorical; central ) extended; etc.). Furthermore,<br />

these examples are typical: as we will see, similar sets exists for the other prepositions in English<br />

(to, in, out, over, etc.); and, one can easily construct other sets for non–Indo–European languages,<br />

e.g., the postpositions ni, e, kara, de, etc. in Japanese.<br />

Theories of case grammar cannot account for data such as those above in a way that relates the<br />

positional and nonpositional uses of prepositions. In Fillmore’s system, for example, it is a complete<br />

accident that a preposition like English to shows up as both GOAL (He went to New York.) and<br />

DATIVE/EXPERIENCER (New York appeals to him.). This is a serious loss of descriptive<br />

adequacy, because the same two relations (GOAL and DATIVE/EXPERIENCER) are realized by<br />

the same postposition in Japanese (ni), the same inflectional case affix in ancient Indo–European<br />

languages like Latin (dative case), the same case in non–Indo–European languages (Finnish allative<br />

case), and so on. When such a wide range of languages realizes ostensibly different relations in the<br />

same way, it is clear that the relations have something in common, and that a descriptively adequate<br />

theory of language must discover and formalize what that commonality is if it is to make revealing<br />

generalizations about natural language. That such generalizations must be made is indicated by sets<br />

of data like the following (an example of literal motion toward a place occurs in the a sentences; of<br />

non–literal motion in the b sentences; of no perceptible motion at all, but rather of the person affected<br />

in the c sentences):<br />

(39) English (same preposition, to).<br />

a. She drove the car to New York. (A question like Where did she drive the car (to)?<br />

is completely acceptable and asks about literal motion toward some unknown place.)<br />

b. She gave the book to him./She gave him the book. (To him cannot be the answer to<br />

a question like Where did she give the book?; in fact, such questions are marginal, at<br />

best.)<br />

c. The book appeals to him. (*Where does the book appeal?)


(40) Latin (same grammatical case, dative).<br />

a. Hostes finibus (dative) appropinquant.<br />

enemy border approach<br />

‘The enemy approaches the border.’<br />

b. Litteras mihi (dative) nuntius reddidit.<br />

letter to me messenger delivered<br />

‘The messenger delivered a letter to me.’<br />

c. Mihi (dative) placet.<br />

to me it pleases<br />

‘It pleases me.’<br />

(41) Italian (same preposition, a).<br />

a. Mio fratello va a scuola ogni giorno.<br />

my brother goes to school every day<br />

‘My bother goes to school every day.’<br />

b. Paulo scrive una lettera a Maria.<br />

Paul wrties a letter to Mary<br />

‘Paul is writing a letter to Mary.<br />

c. A mio fratello piace il romanzo.<br />

to my brother pleases the novel<br />

‘The novel pleases (is pleasing to) my brother.’<br />

(42) Sanskrit (same grammatical case, dative).<br />

a. rājā vanāya (dative) pratis;t;hati.<br />

king forest sets out<br />

‘The king sets out for the forest.’<br />

b. mahyam; (dative) pustakam; dehi.<br />

to me book give<br />

‘Give me the book.’<br />

c. rocate viprebhyah (dative).<br />

it is pleasing to the Brahmans<br />

‘It is pleasing to the Brahmans.’<br />

269


270<br />

(43) Hindi (same postposition ko).<br />

a. vah apne deś ko laut; gayā. (McGregor 1995: 54)<br />

he own country to return went<br />

‘He went back to his own country.’<br />

b. us ādmī ko tīn pustkem< dījie. (McGregor 1995: 54)<br />

that man to three books give<br />

‘Give three books to that man.’<br />

c. landan Ram ko pasand hai.<br />

London Ram to pleasing is<br />

‘Ram likes London.’<br />

(44) Welsh (same preposition, i).<br />

a. Ddaru nhw fynd i Iwerddon. (King, G. 1993: 187)<br />

did they go to Ireland<br />

‘Did they go to Ireland?’<br />

b. Rhoddias fwyd i gath. (Thorne 1993: 405)<br />

I gave food to cat<br />

‘I gave food to a cat.’<br />

c. Dylem ni maddau i’n gelynion. (Thorne 1993: 405)<br />

necessary we forgiving to–our enemies<br />

‘We ought to forgive our enemies.’<br />

(45) Japanese (same postposition, ni).<br />

a. Mary–wa Tokyo–ni itta.<br />

Mary Tokyo–to went<br />

‘Mary went to/toward Tokyo.’<br />

b. Mary–wa sensei–ni tegami–o kaku.<br />

Mary teacher–to letter writes<br />

‘Mary writes a letter to the teacher.’<br />

c. John–ni eiga–ga omoshiroi<br />

John to movie is interesting<br />

‘The movie is interesting to John.’


(46) Finnish (same grammatical case, allative).<br />

a. Menimme asemalle (allative). (Olli 1958: 147)<br />

we went to the station<br />

‘We went to the station.’<br />

b. Annoin miehelle (allative) rahaa. (Olli 1958: 147)<br />

I gave man money<br />

‘I gave the man some money.’<br />

c. Jumala on laupias syntisille (allative). (Eliot 1890: 155)<br />

God is merciful to sinners<br />

‘God is merciful to sinners.’<br />

(47) Turkish (same grammatical case, dative).<br />

a. Türkiye’ye (dative) döndüler. (Lewis 1967: 36)<br />

Turkey they returned<br />

‘They returned to Turkey.’<br />

b. Mektubu Ali’ye (dative) gösterdim. (Lewis 1967: 36)<br />

letter Ali I showed<br />

‘I showed the letter to Ali.’<br />

c. Tütün size (dative) dokunur–mu. (Deny 1971: 187)<br />

tobacco you annoy–question<br />

‘Does tobacco annoy you?’<br />

In RG, case relations like GOAL, EXPERIENCER, SOURCE, AGENT etc. are actually categorial<br />

labels for constellations of semantic features. In the examples (39) to (47), the commonality in<br />

GOAL and EXPERIENCER is the feature [+CONJUNCTURAL] which, roughly speaking, denotes<br />

association or union. In examples (36) and (37) and all the examples in (39), the commonality in<br />

SOURCE, AGENT, and CAUSE is [+DISJUNCTURAL], which, again roughly speaking, denotes<br />

dissociation or separation. Therefore, the use of one thematic marker (preposition, postposition,<br />

grammatical case, etc.) for a variety of thematic relations can be attributed to the presence of identical<br />

features in those relations. This approach overcomes the loss of descriptive adequacy that all the<br />

theories of case relations mentioned above have shared. In those systems, the common features<br />

associated with thematic relations are not expressible, and it becomes a complete accident that the<br />

same marker is used across relations.<br />

The loss of descriptive adequacy in past theories of case grammar leads to a loss of explanatory<br />

adequacy as well. It is very important that work in semantics, like all work in grammatical<br />

description, be generalized across analyses. The study of thematic relations involves one area of<br />

271


272<br />

semantics. The descriptions used in this area must be relatable to descriptions used in other areas of<br />

semantics and to the whole grammar in general. But a theory such as Fillmore’s case grammar is not<br />

easily relatable to other work. For example, in an attempt to represent semantic relations among<br />

different expressions, researchers have constructed semantics networks, which are systems of<br />

connections that link together expressions from the same semantic field, such as color terms (red,<br />

puce, dye, etc.), or animal categories (domestic animals, mammals, animals that live in water, etc.)<br />

or expressions of separation (from, expel, source, etc.). Such semantic networks have been widely<br />

studied in the computer representation of language. But thematic relations like SOURCE and GOAL<br />

cannot be related in any direct way to the concepts which form such semantic networks, as we will<br />

see when we consider semantic networks below.<br />

Further, concepts like SOURCE and GOAL cannot be related to concepts used in other semantic<br />

descriptions. For example, Roger Schank has proposed a set of semantic primitives out of which<br />

meanings can be described. One of his primitives is EXPEL, which refers to the expulsion of an<br />

object from the body of an animal; EXPEL is part of the meaning of verbs like sweat, spit, and cry.<br />

Another of Schank’s primitives is INGEST, which refers to the taking in of an object; INGEST is part<br />

of the meaning of verbs like eat, smoke, and breathe. Clearly, EXPEL is related to SOURCE and<br />

INGEST is related to GOAL. But Fillmore’s theory and Schank’s theory are stated in such as way<br />

that this relationship cannot be precisely specified.<br />

In short, there is little transportability between these systems, so that the valuable insights of each<br />

cannot be gathered into one framework. Yet, the grammatical facts of natural language, in particular,<br />

the distribution of thematic markers, clearly indicate that there must be a connection between<br />

thematic relations and semantic fields in general. That is, the same feature which shows up in<br />

relations like SOURCE and AGENT ([+DISJUNCTURAL], e.g., from) should form part of the<br />

definition of words like aversion, deprive, empty, and so on; and, that feature should also show up<br />

in the definition of a primitive like EXPEL if a theory contains such a primitive. Similarly, the same<br />

feature that shows up in relations like GOAL and EXPERIENCER ([+CONJUNCTURAL], e.g., to)<br />

should form part of the definition of words like inclination, supply, fill, and the like and show up in<br />

a putative primitive like INGEST.<br />

This feature based approach to thematic relations provides an explanation for why the same<br />

groupings of markers occur repeatedly in natural languages. Additionally, since features like<br />

[+DISJUNCTURAL] and [+CONJUNCTURAL] can be directly defined in terms of human and<br />

machine perceptual systems, this approach also specifies the connection between perception and<br />

language. Any system which does not make this connection fails to attain explanatory adequacy.<br />

The central thesis of RG semantics, therefore, is that thematic relations that are [–PST] are metaphors<br />

for those that are [+PST], so that the same features that distinguish and relate the latter group are<br />

employed in distinguishing and relating the former. Furthermore, we will see that thematic relations<br />

like SOURCE and AGENT are categorial abbreviations for constellations of semantic features, just<br />

as syntactic categories like NOUN and VERB are abbreviations for constellations of syntactic<br />

features. Lastly, we will see that the semantic features from which complex semantic categories are<br />

built are features that can be grounded in perception (human or machine).


4.12 POSITIONAL THEMATIC RELATIONS IN RG<br />

We began the discussion of thematic relations by making a distinction between expressions which<br />

indicate positional relations like He ran from his office and those which do not like He died from<br />

overexposure. To this, we must add a fundamental breakdown between those positional relations<br />

which refer to position in time [+TEMPORAL] and those which refer to position in space<br />

[–TEMPORAL]. We can loosely define these features as follows:<br />

(48) a. [+POSITIONAL] ([+PST, ±TMP]): having the primary focus on location,<br />

orientation, or movement in space or time, e.g., He went FROM CALIFORNIA TO<br />

NEW YORK, He remained FROM SUNRISE TO SUNSET.<br />

273<br />

b. [–POSITIONAL] ([–PST]): not having the primary focus on location, orientation, or<br />

movement in space or time, e.g., FROM MY DESCRIPTION, he believes the movie<br />

will appeal TO HIM.<br />

(49) a. [+TEMPORAL] ([+PST, +TMP]): focusing on time, e.g, He remained FROM<br />

SUNRISE TO SUNSET.<br />

b. [–TEMPORAL] ([+PST, –TMP]): focusing on place, e.g., He went FROM<br />

CALIFORNIA TO NEW YORK<br />

Given a perceptual apparatus (human or machine), these definitions can be made very precise. For<br />

example, a computer equipped with a vision system and an internal clock can assign specific values<br />

to each of these features: the definition of [+PST] relations involving movement can be equated with<br />

changes in positional vectors over time; the definition of [+PST] relations not involving movement<br />

can be equated with a lack of change in positional vectors over time; the definition of [–PST]<br />

relations can be equated with the lack of a positional vector altogether; and so on. Thus, the features<br />

can be used to bridge the gap between the concrete (measurable, literal) and the abstract<br />

(metaphorical), a very important objective in semantic analysis.<br />

The vector components for space include values of length, width and depth although spatial relations<br />

do not always refer to all three components. For example, a region may be viewed as a surface in<br />

examples like They are on the lawn, where the depth of the lawn is not relevant. On the other hand,<br />

a region can also be viewed as an area in examples like They are in the lawn, where the depth is<br />

relevant. Compare also They are on the bed and They are in the bed; Look at the smudge on the<br />

mirror and Look at your reflection in the mirror; The ants are on the floor and The termites are in<br />

the floor.


274<br />

4.13 SOME BASIC FEATURE DISTINCTIONS<br />

Within the compass of positional relations, languages make a fundamental distinction between<br />

relations that involve three dimensions and those that do not, e.g., in English, the difference between<br />

in and on. We will specify this distinction as first and second order positional arguments as follows:<br />

(50) [±FIRST ORDER] ([±FST]).<br />

a. [+FST]: Thematic relations which are [+PST, +FST] express relationships relative<br />

to a point, line or surface. Depth is not involved so that “surface” refers to a region<br />

with only length and width.<br />

Examples: on the table, off the table, at the door; on Tuesday, at six o’clock.<br />

b. [–FST] (SECOND ORDER): Thematic relations which are [+PST, –FST] express<br />

relationships relative to area or volume. Depth is involved so that “area” refers to a<br />

region with length, width, and height; compare He is on the field (surface) versus He<br />

is in the field (area).<br />

Examples: in the room, out of the office; in March, out of office hours.<br />

Within each of these categories, natural languages have positional markers to indicate whether there<br />

is contact or lack of contact between the object and the location. If the location is a container, e.g.,<br />

a building, then part of the container includes its interior space; hence, anything within that interior<br />

space is viewed as being in contact with a part of the container. This detail is crucial to<br />

understanding the possible meaning of sentences like The balloon floated around in the smoke–filled<br />

room and She put the (porcelain) elephant into her purse. We will express the feature of contact<br />

with the following opposition:<br />

(51) [±PROXIMAL] ([±PRX]).<br />

a. [+PRX]: involving contact between the object and the location.<br />

Examples: on the floor, in the drawer; on Tuesday, in March.<br />

b. [–PRX]: not involving contact between the object and the location.<br />

Examples: at the door, near his office; around noon, near July 4.<br />

Thematic relations that are [+PST, ±FST, ±PRX] do not necessitate motion, although motion is<br />

possible, e.g., He walked out of his office versus He is out of his office. Such an option is not<br />

available with all positional markers. For example, positional uses of to typically involve movement<br />

of some kind (cf. He has never been to Europe, where the use of to necessitates interpreting been as<br />

gone). Positional uses of to without movement as in They stood back to back are less common.


To account for the differences between motion and rest, as well as the direction of motion (to versus<br />

from) and the location of rest (on/in versus off of/out of), we posit the feature oppositions<br />

CONJUNCTURAL ([±CNJ]) and DISJUNCTURAL ([±DSJ]). Informally, we say that disjunctural<br />

relations ([+DSJ]) are defined as those that involve parting, dissociation, withdrawal, detachment,<br />

or separation. Conjunctural relations ([+CNJ]) are defined as those that involve joining, association,<br />

advance, attachment, or union. Significantly, in any movement, there is simultaneously both a<br />

withdrawal from one location (the SOURCE) and an advance to some other location (the GOAL).<br />

In actual usage, one or the other is generally emphasized: depart from, advance to, go from, go to,<br />

etc. In cases of rest like the cup is on the table, neither parting nor joining is involved.<br />

These two interacting feature oppositions, [±CNJ] and [±DSJ], can be used to account for the<br />

differences between movement and rest in space or time as follows:<br />

(52) INVOLVING TWO LOCATIONS AND INVOLVING MOVEMENT:<br />

a. [–DSJ, +CNJ]: involving movement toward one location in space or time, the<br />

SOURCE location being understood or not mentioned:<br />

Examples: He went as far as/up to the river; He’ll be here until/up to Friday.<br />

b. [+DSJ, –CNJ]: involving movement away from one location in space or time, the<br />

GOAL being understood or not mentioned:<br />

Examples: He left from Detroit; He’s been here since Easter.<br />

(53) INVOLVING ONE LOCATION AND NOT INVOLVING MOVEMENT:<br />

a. [–DSJ, –CNJ]: not involving movement and relating to one location only, specifically<br />

the place where some object is located:<br />

Examples: He is in Europe; The meeting is in June.<br />

275<br />

b. [+DSJ, +CNJ]: not involving movement and relating to one location only,<br />

specifically the place where some object is not located. Temporal examples like out<br />

of season are uncommon.<br />

Examples: He is away from his desk, out of the office.<br />

Notice that, for movement to occur, at least two locations are required. In [αDSJ, –αCNJ] relations,<br />

only one location need be mentioned; the other is implied and could be mentioned (He departed from<br />

the city (for the country)). However, in [+DSJ, +CNJ] cases, any second implied location cannot be<br />

mentioned unless a coordinating conjunction or comma intonation is used between the two,<br />

otherwise, the object appears to be in two places at once:


276<br />

(54) a. *It is now off the wall on the table.<br />

b. It is now off the wall and on the table.<br />

The last feature opposition to be presented is one needed to capture the distinction between<br />

pinpointed and widespread positional expressions, e.g., on versus over, and in versus throughout.<br />

We therefore add (55).<br />

(55) [±EXTENSIONAL] ([±EXT])<br />

a. [+EXT]: emphasizing the extent of space or time.<br />

Examples: over the floor, all around the house; over the weekend, all during<br />

February.<br />

b. [–EXT]: emphasizing a small and highly circumscribed space or time.<br />

Examples: on the horse, in the box; on Monday, in July.<br />

A summary of examples of the positional thematic relations is given in Figure Nine.


–DSJ<br />

–CNJ<br />

+DSJ<br />

+CNJ<br />

–DSJ<br />

+CNJ<br />

+DSJ<br />

–CNJ<br />

FIGURE NINE I: PROXIMAL POSITIONAL THEMATIC RELATIONS ([+PST, –TMP, +PRX])<br />

–EXT +EXT<br />

+FST –FST +FST –FST<br />

LOCATIVE1<br />

on, on top of<br />

He was on the horse.<br />

ABSENTIVE1<br />

off, off of<br />

He was off the horse.<br />

ILLATIVE1<br />

on, onto<br />

He got on the horse.<br />

ELATIVE1<br />

off, off of, from<br />

He got off the horse.<br />

LOCATIVE2<br />

in, within<br />

He was in the pool.<br />

ABSENTIVE2<br />

out of<br />

He was out of the pool.<br />

ILLATIVE2<br />

into, in<br />

He jumped into the<br />

pool.<br />

ELATIVE2<br />

out of, from<br />

He jumped out of the<br />

pool.<br />

LOCATIVE3<br />

over, on<br />

He had the patch over<br />

his eye.<br />

ABSENTIVE3<br />

off, off of<br />

He had the patch off<br />

his eye.<br />

ILLATIVE3<br />

over, on<br />

He put the patch over<br />

his eye.<br />

ELATIVE3<br />

off, off of, from<br />

He took the patch off<br />

his eye.<br />

LOCATIVE4<br />

in, through(out)<br />

There was smoke all<br />

through the house.<br />

ABSENTIVE4<br />

out of<br />

All the smoke was out<br />

of the house.<br />

ILLATIVE4<br />

into, through(out)<br />

He got smoke all<br />

through the house.<br />

ELATIVE4<br />

out of, from<br />

He got all the smoke<br />

out of the house.<br />

FIGURE NINE II: NONPROXIMAL POSITIONAL THEMATIC RELATIONS ([+PST, –TMP, –PRX])<br />

–DSJ<br />

–CNJ<br />

+DSJ<br />

+CNJ<br />

–DSJ<br />

+CNJ<br />

+DSJ<br />

–CNJ<br />

–EXT +EXT<br />

+FST –FST +FST –FST<br />

ADESSIVE1<br />

near, at<br />

He was near the tree.<br />

ABESSIVE1<br />

away from, from<br />

He was away from the<br />

tree.<br />

ALLATIVE1<br />

to, toward<br />

He walked toward the<br />

tree.<br />

ABLATIVE1<br />

away from, from<br />

He walked away from<br />

the tree.<br />

ADESSIVE2<br />

near, at<br />

The balloon was near<br />

the ceiling.<br />

ABESSIVE2<br />

away from, from<br />

The balloon was away<br />

from the ceiling.<br />

ALLATIVE2<br />

to, toward<br />

The balloon floated<br />

toward the ceiling.<br />

ABLATIVE2<br />

away from, from<br />

The balloon floated<br />

away from the ceiling.<br />

ADESSIVE3<br />

along, near, at<br />

The signs were along<br />

the road.<br />

ABESSIVE3<br />

away from, from<br />

The signs were away<br />

from the road.<br />

ALLATIVE3<br />

along, near<br />

He put the signs along<br />

the road.<br />

ABLATIVE3<br />

away from, from<br />

He put the signs away<br />

from the road.<br />

ADESSIVE4<br />

among, amid<br />

The planes were amid<br />

the clouds.<br />

ABESSIVE4<br />

away from, from<br />

The planes were away<br />

from the clouds.<br />

ALLATIVE4<br />

among, amid<br />

The planes flew amid<br />

the clouds.<br />

ABLATIVE4<br />

away from, from<br />

The planes flew away<br />

from the clouds.<br />

277


278<br />

Figure Nine reveals an important advantage to having two interacting features (DSJ and CNJ) with<br />

two values (plus and minus) to account for positional relations, namely, it affords us a simple way<br />

of accounting for the many markers that spread over both STATIVE (rest) and NONSTATIVE<br />

(motion) relations. For example, from is either [+DSJ, +CNJ], that is, stative, as in he is from Detroit,<br />

or [+DSJ, –CNJ], that is, nonstative, as in he moved from Detroit. Using the same α–notation from<br />

phonology (Page 82), we can generalize this as [+DSJ, αCNJ].<br />

A system that begins with [±STATIVE] (or [± MOTION]) as primitives and then attempts to<br />

categorize markers in terms of these primitives misrepresents the facts. A marker like from is<br />

essentially separative, i.e., [+DISJUNCTURAL], however one wishes to label this; it is not<br />

essentially either a marker of motion or a marker of rest. Interestingly, English to is not essentially<br />

[+CONJUNCTURAL]; rather, its basic feature is [–DISJUNCTURAL]. There are LOCATIVE uses<br />

(it is stuck to the wall, they are cheek to cheek) and ADESSIVE uses (his back is to the wall, they<br />

stood to one side, it lies to the north). We find similar data in other languages. In French, for<br />

example, en is used for [–DISJUNCTURAL] expressions: aller en France (‘go to France’), entrer<br />

en ville (‘go into town’), vivre en Angleterre (‘live in England’).<br />

In general, thematic markers in the world’s languages have both stative and nonstative uses, and are<br />

not primarily associated with either motion or rest though this certainly does occur. Crucially, even<br />

when this does occur, the relations are still best expressed along the lines of Figure Nine. For<br />

example, many German prepositions (an, auf, hinter, etc.) are used with the dative case for rest and<br />

the accusative case for motion. This simply means that the dative is associated with [αDSJ, αCNJ]<br />

and the accusative with [αDSJ, –αCNJ]. What we do not find in natural language are common<br />

examples where markers are confined to motion or rest and within each category have both<br />

disjunctural and conjunctural meanings, i.e., a marker that means either motion to or motion from,<br />

or one that means either rest in or rest out of. For these reasons, concepts like stative are derivative,<br />

not primitive, in the system described here.<br />

In Figure Nine notice that English frequently neutralizes features so that the same preposition is used<br />

throughout a row. This is, in fact, one of the motivations behind the RG system. One needs to be<br />

able to both pinpoint and generalize prepositional usage. In some instances, there are fine<br />

distinctions available: in, on, over, throughout. In others, the same preposition covers a wide range<br />

of cases, e.g., from and to. In this regard, English is typical of the world’s languages, though, again,<br />

as the examples from French and German above indicate, different languages will distribute<br />

prepositions over different feature spaces.<br />

The most obvious positional features that have nonpositional correlates are the four DSJ/CNJ pairs<br />

of Figure Nine in both their PROXIMAL and NONPROXIMAL variations. Certain nonpositional<br />

thematic relations are viewed by speakers as involving a conjunction (to and into), others a<br />

disjunction (from and out of), and still others a combination of disjunction and conjunction (off and<br />

away) or lack of both (on and in). Accordingly, the same prepositions that occur in the positional<br />

relations show up in the nonpositional ones. We have very clear cut examples like (56) though (59).


(56) a. He turned into a street. [+PST]<br />

b. He turned into a frog. [–PST]<br />

(57) a. He leaned against them. [+PST]<br />

b. He fought against them. [–PST]<br />

(58) a. They roamed about the city. [+PST]<br />

b. They talked about the city. [–PST]<br />

(59) a. They live by water. [+PST] or [–PST]<br />

b. They travel by water. [+PST] of [–PST]<br />

4.14 NONPOSITIONAL THEMATIC RELATIONS<br />

We have argued above that the nonpositional thematic relations are metaphors for their positional<br />

counterparts. To repeat, a [+PST, +DSJ] theme expresses literal (measurable) separation, whereas<br />

a [–PST, +DSJ] theme expresses figurative separation. A theme like SOURCE is [+PST, +DSJ]; one<br />

like CAUSE is [–PST, +DSJ]. Similarly, a [+PST, –DSJ] theme expresses literal (measurable) union,<br />

whereas a [–PST, –DSJ] theme expresses figurative union. Thus, GOAL is [+PST, –DSJ];<br />

EXPERIENCER is [–PST, –DSJ].<br />

A summary of the nonpositional thematic relations is given in Figure Ten. As Figures Nine and Ten<br />

indicate, case relations like ILLATIVE, AFFECTIVE (EXPERIENCER), EFFECTIVE (AGENT),<br />

etc. are actually categorial labels for constellations of semantic features in RG. Thus, semantics<br />

exactly parallels syntax and phonology. Each one of the semantic features can be precisely defined<br />

in terms of human (or machine) vision.<br />

The commonality in ILLATIVE, ALLATIVE and AFFECTIVE is the feature [+CNJ] which denotes<br />

association or union; the commonality in ELATIVE, ABLATIVE, and EFFECTIVE (and all the<br />

examples in (39)) is [+DSJ], which denotes dissociation or separation. Therefore, the use of one<br />

thematic marker (preposition, postposition, grammatical case, etc.) for a variety of thematic relations<br />

can be attributed to the presence of identical features in those relations. This approach overcomes<br />

the loss of descriptive adequacy that all the theories of case relations mentioned above have shared.<br />

In those systems, the common features associated with thematic relations are not expressible, and it<br />

becomes a complete accident that the same marker is used across relations.<br />

279


280<br />

–DSJ<br />

–CNJ<br />

+DSJ<br />

+CNJ<br />

–DSJ<br />

+CNJ<br />

+DSJ<br />

–CNJ<br />

–DSJ<br />

–CNJ<br />

+DSJ<br />

+CNJ<br />

–DSJ<br />

+CNJ<br />

+DSJ<br />

–CNJ<br />

FIGURE TEN I: PROXIMAL NONPOSITIONAL THEMATIC RELATIONS ([–PST, +PRX])<br />

POSSESSOR<br />

Ø<br />

He knows French.<br />

NONPOSSESSOR<br />

Ø<br />

He doesn’t know<br />

French.<br />

–EXT +EXT<br />

+FST –FST +FST –FST<br />

AFFECTIVE<br />

to<br />

Al taught French to Ed.<br />

EFFECTIVE<br />

from, by<br />

Ed learned French from<br />

Al.<br />

ATTRIBUTIVE<br />

in, with, of<br />

He is a man with/of many<br />

hopes.<br />

NONATTRIBUTIVE<br />

out of, without, from<br />

He is a man without any<br />

hopes.<br />

RESULTATIVE<br />

into<br />

Al turned Ed into an<br />

optimist.<br />

COMPOSITIONAL<br />

out of, from<br />

Ed made a optimist out of<br />

Al.<br />

COMPARATIVE<br />

like, with, to<br />

He is similar to his father.<br />

He is like his father.<br />

NONCOMPARATIVE<br />

unlike, from<br />

He differs from his father.<br />

He is unlike his father.<br />

REFERENTIAL<br />

for<br />

For her, the price is right.<br />

EXPEDIENTIAL<br />

by<br />

He got there by plane.<br />

CIRCUMSTANTIAL<br />

with<br />

He does everything with<br />

haste.<br />

NONCIRCUMSTANTIAL<br />

without<br />

He does everything without<br />

haste.<br />

CONSECUTIVE<br />

for<br />

He’s too ill for work.<br />

CAUSAL<br />

from, of<br />

He died from the extreme<br />

cold.<br />

FIGURE TEN II: NONPROXIMAL NONPOSITIONAL THEMATIC RELATIONS ([–PST, –PRX])<br />

POSSESSOR<br />

Ø<br />

He has a Volvo.<br />

NONPOSSESSOR<br />

Ø<br />

He doesn’t have a<br />

Volvo.<br />

–EXT +EXT<br />

+FST –FST +FST –FST<br />

AFFERENTIAL<br />

to<br />

Al sold his Volvo to Ed.<br />

EFFERENTIAL<br />

from<br />

Ed bought his Volvo<br />

from Al.<br />

ASSOCIATIVE<br />

in, with, of<br />

He is in debt. He’s a man<br />

with/of many debts.<br />

NONASSOCIATIVE<br />

out of, without, from<br />

He is out of debt. He’s a<br />

man without debts.<br />

TERMINATIVE<br />

into<br />

Al got Ed into debt.<br />

ORIGINATIVE<br />

out of, from<br />

Ed got Al out of debt.<br />

COMITATIVE<br />

with<br />

He made the dinner with<br />

her.<br />

NONCOMITATIVE<br />

without<br />

He made the dinner<br />

without her.<br />

BENEFACTIVE<br />

for<br />

He did it for her.<br />

DIFFERENTIAL<br />

by<br />

He won by a mile.<br />

INSTRUMENTAL<br />

with<br />

He built the fort with tools.<br />

NONINSTRUMENTAL<br />

without<br />

He built the fort without<br />

tools.<br />

PURPOSIVE<br />

for<br />

He learned Italian for fun.<br />

He did it for many reasons.<br />

DELIMITIVE<br />

in the event of, if<br />

In the event of an accident,<br />

call the police.


The definitions for the major nonpositional thematic relations are as follows:<br />

(60) EFFECTIVE (EFC): The animate being, missile, or force typically perceived as bringing<br />

about the action identified in the predicate (variously called AGENTIVE, AGENT, and<br />

FORCE).<br />

BILL killed the bug./The bug was killed BY BILL.<br />

THE BOULDER totaled the car./The car was totaled BY THE BOULDER.<br />

THE TORNADO destroyed the crops./The crops were destroyed BY THE TORNADO.<br />

(61) COMPOSITIONAL (CPS): The material or things out of which something is composed;<br />

the product retains the original ingredients (related to INALIENABLE POSSESSION).<br />

They crafted the vase OUT OF SILVER.<br />

The cabinets are made OF WOOD.<br />

The oak grew OUT OF AN ACORN.<br />

(62) EXPEDIENTIAL (EXP): The means by which something is done.<br />

We went BY CAR.<br />

BY COUNTING TO TEN, she manages not to abuse the kids.<br />

(63) CAUSAL (CAU): The entity which expresses the cause of the action or state identified in<br />

the predicate.<br />

He died FROM SMOKING. He died OF CANCER.<br />

He collapsed FROM THE HEAT.<br />

He acted OUT OF GUILT.<br />

(64) EFFERENTIAL (EFR): The quasi–positional entity from which an action emanates. Often<br />

called SOURCE by others.<br />

John received/bought the car FROM BILL.<br />

BILL gave/sold the car to John.<br />

(65) ORIGINATIVE (ORG): The entity or condition from which something is transformed<br />

(related to ALIENABLE POSSESSION).<br />

He got himself OUT OF DEBT.<br />

He detoxed FROM HEROIN.<br />

281


282<br />

(66) DIFFERENTIAL (DIF): The degree of difference expressed in a contrast.<br />

He won BY A MILE.<br />

They are distinguished BY MANY CHARACTERISTICS.<br />

(67) DELIMITIVE (DEL): Delimitive themes specify the condition(s) from which something<br />

results; hence, they are classified as [+DISJUNCTURAL]. Most delimitive expressions in<br />

English are clauses introduced by if.<br />

His sister will care for his children, IF HE DIES.<br />

IN THE EVENT OF HIS DEATH, his sister will care for his children.<br />

(68) AFFECTIVE (AFC): The animate or inanimate entity directly affected by the state or<br />

action identified in the predicate. Variously called EXPERIENCER or DATIVE by others.<br />

JOHN feels that Bill will win.<br />

John killed BILL./BILL died.<br />

John melted THE ICE./ THE ICE melted.<br />

He put the money IN HIS POCKET.<br />

(69) RESULTATIVE (RES): The product created from some materials and retaining the original<br />

ingredients (related to INALIENABLE POSSESSION).<br />

The wove the straw INTO BASKETS.<br />

THE BASKETS were made out of straw.<br />

She baked (the ingredients into) A CAKE.<br />

The acorn grew INTO AN OAK.<br />

He invented THE TELEPHONE.<br />

(70) REFERENTIAL (REF): The person or thing in reference or relation to which something<br />

occurs.<br />

John will always be a hero TO BILL (AS FAR AS BILL IS CONCERNED).<br />

A term paper is optional FOR UNDERGRADUATES.<br />

He is smart FOR HIS AGE.<br />

Bill is a stickler FOR DETAILS.<br />

(71) CONSECUTIVE (CNS): The result or consequences of an action or state.<br />

He became too sick TO/FOR WORK.<br />

He became so sick THAT HE COULDN’T WORK.<br />

It’s too early FOR DINNER.<br />

He has enough qualifications/qualifies FOR THE JOB.


(72) AFFERENTIAL (AFR): The quasi–positional entity to which an action is directed. Often<br />

called GOAL by others.<br />

283<br />

Bill sold the car TO JOHN./Bill sold JOHN the car.<br />

JOHN received/bought the car from Bill.<br />

He gave a new coat of paint TO THE HOUSE./He gave THE HOUSE a new coat of paint.<br />

(73) TERMINATIVE (TRM): The entity or condition into which something is transformed<br />

(related to ALIENABLE POSSESSION).<br />

He came INTO A FORTUNE./He became WEALTHY.<br />

He got himself INTO DEBT.<br />

He withdrew INTO DRUGS AND ALCOHOL.<br />

(74) BENEFACTIVE (BEN): The entity, usually animate, for whose benefit or on whose behalf<br />

the action or state identified in the predicate occurs (see below, Endnote ?).<br />

Bill bought a gift FOR JOAN/bought JOAN a gift.<br />

JOAN was bought a gift by Bill.<br />

(75) PURPOSIVE (PUR): The entity which specifies the purpose of or reason for the action or<br />

state identified in the predicate.<br />

They trained him FOR THE JOB/TO DO THE JOB.<br />

He entered the competition FOR THE MONEY/TO GET MONEY.<br />

They dug a hole FOR WATER/TO GET WATER.<br />

She jumped FOR JOY.<br />

She did it FOR MANY REASONS.<br />

They rewarded him FOR HIS RESEARCH.<br />

4.15 DIMENSIONAL THEMATIC RELATIONS<br />

In addition to the feature specifications given in the above figures, the RG system recognizes another<br />

set of thematic relations of a DIMENSIONAL nature. These are defined as follows and illustrated<br />

comparatively in Figure Eleven:<br />

(76) COMPONENTIAL1: the whole (holonym) in a part–whole relationship.<br />

a. A ROOM has a ceiling.<br />

b. A HOUSE has a roof.


284<br />

(77) COMPONENTIAL2: the part (meronym) in a part–whole relationship.<br />

a. A CEILING is part of a room.<br />

b. A ROOF is part of a house.<br />

(78) TYPOLOGICAL1: the class (hypernym) in a member–class relationship.<br />

a. The class MAMMAL contains primates.<br />

b. The class BIRD contains robins.<br />

(79) TYPOLOGICAL2: the member (hyponym) in a member–class relationship.<br />

a. PRIMATES are mammals.<br />

b. ROBINS are a type of bird.<br />

Since the relationships may involve either inalienable or alienable characteristics and nonpossession<br />

as well as possession, we have the sixteen relationships specified in Figure Eleven.<br />

+PRX<br />

–DSJ<br />

–CNJ<br />

+PRX<br />

+DSJ<br />

+CNJ<br />

–PRX<br />

–DSJ<br />

–CNJ<br />

–PRX<br />

+DSJ<br />

+CNJ<br />

FIGURE ELEVEN: CLASSIFICATORY THEMATIC RELATIONS<br />

–EXT +EXT<br />

+FST –FST +FST –FST<br />

COMPONENTIAL1 COMPONENTIAL2 TYPOLOGICAL1 TYPOLOGICAL2<br />

An arm is A BODY<br />

PART.<br />

The neck is not part of<br />

THE HEAD.<br />

A flower is part of A<br />

BOUQUET.<br />

Hawaii is not part of<br />

CONTINENTAL<br />

USA.<br />

AN ARM is a body<br />

part.<br />

THE NECK is not part<br />

of the head.<br />

A FLOWER is part of a<br />

bouquet.<br />

HAWAII is not part of<br />

the continental USA.<br />

A penguin is A BIRD. A PENGUIN is a bird.<br />

A penguin is A<br />

NONFLIER.<br />

A PENGUIN is a<br />

nonflier.<br />

John is a SMOKER. JOHN is a smoker.<br />

John is a<br />

NONSMOKER.<br />

JOHN is a nonsmoker.<br />

Notice that any particular characteristic of an object might be expressed in several different ways.<br />

For example, in (70, 80a), black is treated as an inalienable characteristic while in (70, 80b) it is<br />

treated as a class.


(80) a. ATTRIBUTIVE: He is black.<br />

b. TYPOLOGICAL: He is a black.<br />

Similarly, in (81a) poor is treated as an alienable characteristic; in (81b) it is treated as a class.<br />

(81) a. ASSOCIATIVE: He is poor.<br />

b. TYPOLOGICAL: The poor need assistance.<br />

Since the same characteristic can fit more than one of our proposed thematic relations, it might appear<br />

that the system we have described is unnecessarily redundant or complex. But this is not the case.<br />

Different individuals classify and define the same things in numerous, diverse ways. For example,<br />

one can classify United States judges as members of a particular branch of government or as<br />

nonmembers of other branches:<br />

(82) a. Judges are part of the judicial branch of government.<br />

b. The judicial branch of government includes judges.<br />

(83) a. Judges are not part of the legislative branch of government.<br />

b. The legislative branch of government does not include judges.<br />

Further, some speakers may view (82) as an INALIENABLE classification, others as ALIENABLE,<br />

and these particular assignments are relatively stable. Consider the possible assignments when<br />

attempting to classify a word like teenager. Assignments into different cells of the figures above is<br />

often a matter of personal beliefs, habit and experience. For example, in a random poll, it was found<br />

that most students in an introductory <strong>linguistic</strong>s class did not view the neck as part of the head;<br />

however, several did, some with great conviction: “Well, after all, the neck goes with the head in<br />

decapitation,” one student remarked ominously.<br />

Lastly, observe that care must be taken in comparing meanings. For example, the assignment of the<br />

number π to the class of irrational numbers and the description of an individual as a irrational person<br />

do not employ the same meaning of irrational:<br />

(84) a. TYPOLOGICAL: Pi (π) is irrational.<br />

b. CIRCUMSTANTIAL: John is irrational.<br />

The feature opposition [±DIMENSIONAL] is the last semantic feature we will consider. This<br />

opposition, in addition to the others discussed previously, will figure prominently in our discussion<br />

of semantic networks below.<br />

285


286<br />

4.16 PROTOTYPES AND STRENGTH OF ASSOCIATION<br />

As we noted above, the nonpositional thematic relations must be related to the positional ones, if only<br />

to account for the fact that the same set of markers appears for both in most of the world’s languages.<br />

This is not to say that languages never distinguish the two sets. In fact, in English, forms like<br />

here/there/where are never used for nonpositional relations, as the following pairs show.<br />

(85) a. I know where he turned; it was here, into this street.<br />

b. *I know where he turned; it was there, into a frog.<br />

(86) a. I know where that chandelier hung; it was here, over this table.<br />

b. *I know where that chandelier cost; it was here, over two dollars.<br />

(87) a. I know where John decided; it was there, on the boat.<br />

b. *I know where John decided; it was here, on this ring.<br />

The distinction between [+PST] (literal) and [–PST] (metaphorical) uses of markers is not sharp. A<br />

more realistic characterization must recognize a gradation from expressions that are invariably<br />

considered [+PST] by speakers to those that never or rarely are. This same gradation or strength of<br />

association operates in many areas of semantic categorization. For example, using a scale from 4<br />

(most strength of association) to 0 (no strength of association), we might categorize nouns as<br />

referring to a location in space in the following way:<br />

(88) a. PST4: desert, planet<br />

b. PST3: bed, office<br />

c. PST2: eye, lettuce<br />

d. PST1: law, phrase<br />

e. PST0: some, the<br />

This classification asserts that speakers primarily use the word desert to denote a place (i.e., a desert<br />

is a dry sandy place), whereas the word law is rarely used to signify a place (cf. It is stated in the<br />

law), and the word some (for all practical purposes) never is. Exactly how many numbers are needed<br />

in such a scale is an empirical matter. Suppose we begin by proposing a five–point scale from 0 up<br />

to 4. The assignment of nouns and other expressions to specific classes will also depend on<br />

investigation: clearly, all speakers will not agree with the judgments in (88).<br />

Psychologists like Eleanor Rosch have researched such categorizations and noted that speakers<br />

formulate prototypes, that is, typical examples of categories. For example, most American English<br />

speakers feel that the robin is the prototypical bird, so a sentence like A robin is sort of a bird is<br />

generally considered very odd. This contrasts with sentences like A bat is sort of a bird, which seem<br />

acceptable. On the basis of such work on prototypes, one might propose, the following scale of<br />

“birdiness” for American English speakers:


(89) a. BIRD4: robin<br />

A robin is a bird.<br />

*A robin is sort of a bird.<br />

b. BIRD3: chicken<br />

A chicken is a bird.<br />

?A chicken is sort of a bird.<br />

c. BIRD2: bat<br />

*A bat is a bird.<br />

A bat is sort of a bird.<br />

d. BIRD1: kite<br />

*A kite is a bird.<br />

?A kite is sort of a bird.<br />

e. BIRD0: hammer<br />

*A hammer is a bird.<br />

*A hammer is sort of a bird.<br />

Examples like the above show that it is possible to construct prototype scales for a number of<br />

different categories. Suppose we use the concept of prototype to categorize various expressions<br />

containing positional markers in an effort to deal with the complex problem of specifying the<br />

meanings and uses of prepositions. The progression we find along the PST–scale moves from true<br />

positional expressions, those that denote a location ([PST4] and [PST3]), to expressions of condition,<br />

circumstance, or manner ([PST1] and [PST0]), with [PST2] expressions lying somewhere in between.<br />

For example, consider the following phrases, in particular, what constitutes an appropriate response<br />

to the request made:<br />

(90) a. [PST4]: live in Ann Arbor<br />

1. As a location:<br />

REQUEST: Please tell me where he lives.<br />

RESPONSE: He lives in Ann Arbor.<br />

2. As a manner or condition:<br />

REQUEST: Please tell me how he lives.<br />

*RESPONSE: He lives in Ann Arbor.<br />

b. [PST3]: live in a pigsty (=live amid filth)<br />

1. As a location:<br />

REQUEST: Please tell me where he lives.<br />

RESPONSE: He lives in a pigsty.<br />

287


288<br />

2. As a manner or condition:<br />

REQUEST: Please tell me how he lives.<br />

?RESPONSE: He lives in a pigsty.<br />

RESPONSE: He lives like a pig.<br />

c. [PST2]: live in luxury<br />

1. As a location:<br />

REQUEST: Please tell me where he lives.<br />

?RESPONSE: He lives in luxury.<br />

2. As a manner or condition:<br />

REQUEST: Please tell me how he lives.<br />

RESPONSE: He lives in luxury.<br />

RESPONSE: He lives like a king.<br />

d. [PST1]: live on a budget<br />

1. As a location:<br />

REQUEST: Please tell me where he lives.<br />

*RESPONSE: He lives on a budget.<br />

2. As a manner or condition:<br />

REQUEST: Please tell me how he lives.<br />

RESPONSE: He lives on a budget.<br />

e. [PST0]: live on a shoestring<br />

1. As a location:<br />

REQUEST: Please tell me where he lives.<br />

*RESPONSE: He lives on a shoestring.<br />

2. As a manner or condition:<br />

REQUEST: Please tell me how he lives.<br />

RESPONSE: He lives on a shoestring.<br />

These examples are proffered to illustrate a progression from concrete expressions, with maximum<br />

strength of association to location in space, to ever more figurative ones, where the strength of<br />

association to true location diminishes. Notice, for example, that the answer He lives in a pigsty in<br />

(90b1) does not supply the precise information requested, though it is an acceptable response.<br />

The most concrete of the four types are the [PST4] relations. These are most concrete because they<br />

can be verified by a human or machine vision system (He is on the roof). The most figurative of the<br />

four are the [PST0] relations. These are the true idioms, that is, those expressions whose meaning


cannot be derived from the (literal) meaning of their parts (He is on hand). Sometimes the same<br />

phrase can be interpreted at either extreme. For example, He is on the wagon can refer to his actual<br />

position or to his state of sobriety. Somewhere in between these extremes are the [PST3], [PST2],<br />

and [PST1] relations.<br />

[PST3] expressions are not completely metaphorical, because they co–occur with true positional<br />

markers like here, there, where, etc. (I couldn’t possibly live here, in this pigsty or His hopes must<br />

lie somewhere, but I don’t know where). Because they add more information than just position, they<br />

cannot be consider [PST4]; hence, they have slightly less strength of association to position.<br />

The difference between [PST4] and [PST3] expressions is also manifested in the wide variation<br />

possible for the introductory preposition. The verb live in (90a) can be followed by virtually any<br />

positional preposition including, on, under, behind, among, around, and so on. However, the<br />

prepositions used in expressions like (90b) are highly idiosyncratic. In the case of an expression like<br />

rest one’s hopes on, possibly the only other preposition than on that can be used is in; in the case of<br />

live in a pigsty, the preposition seems invariable.<br />

[PST2] and [PST1] expressions have a meaning that is more concrete than fully idiomatic, yet not<br />

really positional. The meaning of such expressions can be deduced from the meanings of their parts,<br />

and, more significantly, the force of the preposition used is still felt to the extent that related<br />

prepositions can be substituted, albeit restrictively (live in/amidst luxury or live on/within/by a<br />

budget). The difference between these two classes is that, while [PST2] expressions might<br />

conceivably be used locatively, [PST1] cannot be used locatively except with great license. [PST1]<br />

expressions are true expressions of circumstance or manner.<br />

To integrate the five–point scale with the features we have been discussing, let us refer to expressions<br />

that are [PST4], [PST3], or [PST2] as [+POSITIONAL], those that are [PST1] or [PST0] as<br />

[–POSITIONAL].<br />

The distinctions presented here are not always clear cut, and the degree to which speakers feel the<br />

literal and/or positional sense of an expression varies. In my own speech, (91a) seems fine, but (91b)<br />

does not.<br />

(91) a. I’ll tell you where he’s living. He’s living in the lap of luxury in New York City.<br />

b. *I’ll tell you where he’s living. He’s living on a shoestring in New York City.<br />

Both of these examples contain idiomatic expressions, but only (91a) seems to be [+POSITIONAL].<br />

Notice that the presence of a clear–cut positional expression like in New York City is not the<br />

determining factor. We have examples like the following which contain more than one locative<br />

expression:<br />

(92) a. He’s living in New York City on a shoestring.<br />

b. He’s living in New York City in a hovel.<br />

289


290<br />

Notice also that the questioning associated with examples like (91b) actually calls for an expression<br />

of manner:<br />

(93) a. QUESTION: How can he afford to live in New York City?<br />

b. RESPONSE: Certainly not on a shoestring.<br />

Further, the borderline status of (91a), somewhere between true positional and true nonpositional,<br />

i.e., [PST2], makes possible the following interchange:<br />

(94) a. QUESTION: How is he living?<br />

b. RESPONSE: In the lap of luxury.<br />

As we have noted in many places in this book, a proposal must arise from the data and be supported<br />

with examples from the data. In the present case, we need to determine how a particular expression<br />

will be classified along the PST–scale, that is, how can we determine if an expression is PST4 or<br />

PST0 or somewhere in between. As a first approximation, let us propose six criteria as a means to<br />

determining where the expression falls on the PST–scale as follows:<br />

(95) [PST4]: live in Ann Arbor<br />

a. Allow positional questions words like where, from what place, etc.: I’ll tell you<br />

where he lives; he lives in Ann Arbor. *Ann Arbor is what he lives in.<br />

b. Allow positional adverbials like there, here, etc.: Does he live right there in Ann<br />

Arbor?<br />

c. Allow positional relatives, e.g., Ann Arbor is the only place in which he can live.<br />

d. Allow free use of positional prepositions: He lives around/outside of/down in/over<br />

by Ann Arbor.<br />

e. Allow free use of directional phrases: He lives just east of Ann Arbor.<br />

f. Do not allow expressions of manner: *The only way to live is in Ann Arbor.<br />

(96) [PST3]: live in a pigsty (=live amid filth)<br />

a. Allow positional questions words like where, from what place, etc.: I’ll tell you<br />

where he lives; he lives in a pigsty.<br />

b. Allow positional adverbials like there, here, etc.: Does he live right there, in that<br />

pigsty?<br />

c. Marginally allow positional relatives, e.g., ?A pigsty is the only place in which he can<br />

live.<br />

d. Do not allow free use of positional prepositions: He lives in/*within/*amid a pigsty.<br />

e. Marginally allow use of directional phrases: ??He lives just east of a pigsty.<br />

f. Often allow expressions of manner: The only way to live is in a pigsty.


(97) [PST2]: live in luxury<br />

291<br />

a. Allow positional questions words like where, from what place, etc.: I’ll tell you<br />

where he lives; he lives in luxury.<br />

b. Do not freely allow positional adverbials like there, here, etc.: *Does he live right<br />

there, I mean in luxury?<br />

c. Do not allow positional relatives, e.g., *Luxury is the only place in which he can live.<br />

d. Allow only limited variety of positional prepositions: live in/amid/amidst/within<br />

luxury; *live out of/around/behind luxury; ?live beyond luxury.<br />

e. Do not allow directional phrases: *He lives just south of luxury.<br />

f. Allow expressions of manner: The only way to live is in luxury. (cf. The only way to<br />

live is luxuriously.)<br />

(98) [PST1]: live on a budget<br />

a. Do not allow positional questions words like where, from what place, etc.: *I’ll tell<br />

you where he lives; he lives on a budget.<br />

b. Do not allow positional adverbials like there, here, etc.: *Does he live right there, I<br />

mean on that budget?<br />

c. Do not allow positional relatives, e.g., *A budget is the only place on which he can<br />

live.<br />

d. Allow only limited variety of positional prepositions: live on/within/by a budget;<br />

*live out of/around/behind a budget. (cf. live according to a budget).<br />

e. Do not allow directional phrases: *He lives just south of a budget.<br />

f. Allow expressions of manner: The only way to live is on a budget.<br />

(99) [PST0]: live on a shoestring<br />

a. Do not allow positional questions words like where, from what place, etc.: *I’ll tell<br />

you where he lives; he lives on a shoestring.<br />

b. Do not allow positional adverbials like there, here, etc.: *Does he live right there, I<br />

mean on that shoestring?<br />

c. Do not allow positional relatives, e.g., *A shoestring is the only place on which he can<br />

live.<br />

d. Do not allow even limited variety of positional prepositions: *live upon a shoestring.<br />

e. Do not allow directional phrases: *He lives just south of a shoestring.<br />

f. Allow expressions of manner: One way I don’t want to live is on a shoestring.<br />

As these examples how, a major problem for semantics is categorizing and specifying all the various<br />

expressions with prepositions that native speakers know. One of the factors that makes this problem<br />

so thorny is the variability that exists from speaker to speaker. In phonology and syntax, many rules<br />

and principles can be generalized across all speakers despite dialectal differences. In semantics, the<br />

data are often elusive, there is considerable variability from speaker to speaker, and it is often<br />

difficult to formulate principles with precision. As we have noted, semantic analysis is typically a


292<br />

wicked problem in the sense mentioned in the Introduction (Page 5). The hypothesis here is that the<br />

problem might be solved using the concept of prototypes. The examples above support that<br />

hypothesis. Attempting to apply and test the hypothesis with other examples of non–idiomatic and<br />

idiomatic uses of specific thematic relations leads to examples like the following:<br />

(100) a. He put the milk into the refrigerator (ILLATIVE – [PST4]).<br />

He put all his eggs into one basket (ILLATIVE – [PST4] or [PST0]).<br />

b. He took the milk out of the refrigerator (ELATIVE – [PST4]).<br />

He took the wind out of my sails (ELATIVE – [PST4] or [PST0]).<br />

c. He bought the book from Bill (EFFERENTIAL – [PST4]).<br />

It’s like taking candy from a baby (EFFERENTIAL – [PST4] or [PST0]).<br />

To be viable, the hypothesis must now be tested against the representation of thematic relations in<br />

as many other examples and languages as possible. Further, it must be integrated with the other<br />

aspects of semantics that we have considered.<br />

4.17 THE PERCEPTUAL BASIS OF SEMANTICS<br />

Our discussion of semantics has centered on the hypothesis that thematic relations such as<br />

EFFECTIVE, AFFECTIVE, ELATIVE, ILLATIVE, etc. are actually categorial labels for<br />

constellations of semantic features. Each one of the semantic features can be precisely defined in<br />

terms of human (or machine) perception. Given this approach, the use of one thematic marker<br />

(preposition, postposition, grammatical case, etc.) for a variety of thematic relations can be attributed<br />

to the presence of identical features in those relations.<br />

This approach overcomes the loss of descriptive adequacy that theories of case relations mentioned<br />

above have shared. In those systems, the common features associated with thematic relations are not<br />

expressible, and it becomes an accident that the same marker is used across relations. Further, as we<br />

saw, there was a loss of explanatory adequacy as well.<br />

The theory outlined and justified above overcomes these deficiencies. In addition to explicating the<br />

cross–categorial uses of thematic markers, the semantic features can serve as the basis of a<br />

knowledge representation system. People use language to communicate, to share information, to ask<br />

questions, to express feelings, and so on. Somehow, grammars must interface with other cognitive<br />

systems to represent the general knowledge that people have and use during everyday<br />

communication. To see how this might be possible, let us look again at the features that define<br />

thematic relations.<br />

As Figures Nine and Ten reveal, different clusters of features define different thematic relations. A<br />

feature cluster such as [+PST, –TMP, –DIM, –EXT, +FST, +PRX, –DSJ, –CNJ] has the following<br />

meanings:


(101) a. +PST POSITIONAL INVOLVING LOCATION<br />

b. –TMP TEMPORAL LOCATION IN SPACE, NOT TIME<br />

c. –DIM NONDIMENSIONAL NOT CONCERNED WITH MEASUREMENT<br />

d. –EXT NONEXTENSIONAL PINPOINTED LOCATION<br />

e. +FST FIRST ORDER LOCATION RELATIVE TO POINT, LINE,<br />

OR SURFACE<br />

f. +PRX PROXIMAL INVOLVING CONTACT<br />

g. –DSJ NONDISJUNCTURAL NOT EMPHASIZING PARTING<br />

h. –CNJ NONCONJUNCTURAL NOT EMPHASIZING JOINING<br />

Thus, the cluster of features in (101) defines the relation LOCATIVE1 (see Figure Nine on Page 277)<br />

realized in English in such phrases as on walls or on Mars as they would occur in sentences like<br />

Pictures are found on walls and Martians are found on Mars.<br />

Changing one or more feature specifications produces different thematic relations as follows:<br />

(102) [+PST, +TMP, +DIM, –EXT, +FST, +PRX, –DSJ, –CNJ] defines expressions like on<br />

Sunday (still LOCATIVE1) as it might occur in a sentence like Church services often occur<br />

on Sunday.<br />

(103) [+PST, –TMP, –DIM, –EXT, –FST, +PRX, –DSJ, –CNJ] defines expressions like in water<br />

(LOCATIVE2), in sentences like Fish are found in water.<br />

(104) [–PST, –TMP, –DIM, –EXT, –FST, +PRX, –DSJ, –CNJ] defines expressions like in Latin<br />

(ATTRIBUTIVE), which underlie sentences like The poem is in Latin.<br />

(105) [–PST, –TMP, +DIM, –EXT, –FST, +PRX, –DSJ, –CNJ] defines COMPONENTIAL2<br />

expressions like A wing is part of a bird which underlie sentences like All birds have wings.<br />

As these examples show, sets of semantic features specify individual thematic relations. On a higher<br />

level of organization, that of knowledge representation, sets of thematic relations can be used to<br />

construct a semantic network.<br />

293


294<br />

4.18 SEMANTIC NETWORKS<br />

Semantic networks consist of nodes and links. For example, they might contain a node FISH–1<br />

(‘cold–blooded aquatic vertebrate’) and FISH–2 (‘attempt to catch FISH–1’). The node FISH–1 is<br />

connected to the node BODY_OF_WATER–1 (‘a body of water’) by a LOCATIVE2 link, thereby<br />

expressing the fact that fish are found in water. FISH–1 is also connected to TROUT–1 by a<br />

TYPOLOGICAL2 link indicating that one type of fish is a trout. Further, since TROUT–1 is a type<br />

of FISH–1, TROUT–1 “inherits” the LOCATIVE2 link to BODY_OF_WATER–1; thus, TROUT–1<br />

are found in BODY_OF_WATER–1.<br />

The difficulty with semantic networks available in the literature is that they lack independent criteria<br />

for specifying what can be a link in a network. We can overcome that deficiency here. Each link in<br />

the network can be defined as a cluster of semantic features, that is, as a thematic relation. For<br />

example, consider (106) and (107), where each arrow indicates a pointer (link) from one node in a<br />

network to another node, and where the thematic relation left of the arrow names the pointer.<br />

NODE ONE POINTER NODE TWO<br />

(106) a. LIVING_THING–1 ––TYP2 ––> ENTITY–1<br />

b. LIVING_THING–1 ––EFC ––> REPRODUCTION–1<br />

c. LIVING_THING–1 ––EFC ––> INGESTION–1<br />

d. LIVING_THING–1 ––AFC ––> DEATH–1<br />

e. LIVING_THING–1 ––AFC ––> GROWTH–1<br />

f. LIVING_THING–1 ––IPS ––> LIFE–1<br />

This list encodes the information that a LIVING_THING–1 is a type of ENTITY–1, that it can be an<br />

agent (EFC) of REPRODUCTION–1 and INGESTION–1, that it can experience (AFC) DEATH–1<br />

and GROWTH–1, and that it is an inalienable possessor (IPS) of LIFE–1.<br />

(107) a. ANIMAL–1 ––TYP2 ––> LIVING_THING–1<br />

b. ANIMAL–1 ––EFC ––> MOVEMENT–1<br />

c. ANIMAL–1 ––AFC ––> SLEEP–1<br />

d. ANIMAL–1 ––AFC ––> SENSATION–1<br />

e. ANIMAL–1 ––IPS ––> SPONTANEITY–1<br />

f. ANIMAL–1 ––APS ––> HOME–1<br />

This list encodes the information that an ANIMAL is a type of LIVING_THING–1 which can be an<br />

agent (EFC) of MOVEMENT–1, which can experience (AFC) SLEEP–1 and SENSATION–1, and<br />

which inalienably possesses (IPS) SPONTANEITY–1 and alienably possesses (APS) HOME–1.<br />

Each link in representations like the above can be made bi-directional so that information can be<br />

retrieved in reverse. For example, the network can proceed from ENTITY–1 to LIVING_THING–1<br />

in (106a) and then from LIVING_THING–1 to ANIMAL–1 in (107a), or it can proceed in reverse.


As a further example, consider the fragment of the network in (108).<br />

(108) a. HUMAN–1 ––TYP2 ––> ANIMAL–1<br />

b. HUMAN–1 ––EFC ––> SPEECH–1<br />

c. HUMAN–1 ––EFC ––> WRITING–1<br />

d. HUMAN–1 ––EFC ––> IDEA–1<br />

e. HUMAN–1 ––EFC ––> TOOL–1<br />

f. HUMAN–1 ––EFC ––> REASON–1<br />

g. HUMAN–1 ––AFC ––> JOY–1<br />

h. HUMAN–1 ––IPS ––> LANGUAGE–1<br />

I. HUMAN–1 ––IPS ––> KINSHIP–1<br />

j. HUMAN–1 ––IPS ––> RACE–1<br />

k. HUMAN–1 ––APS ––> JOB–1<br />

l. HUMAN–1 ––APS ––> SPOUSE–1<br />

m. HUMAN–1 ––APS ––> CLOTHING–1<br />

n. HUMAN–1 ––APS ––> NAME–1<br />

o. HUMAN–1 ––APS ––> TOOL–1<br />

This list encodes the information that a HUMAN–1 is a type of ANIMAL–1 which can be an agent<br />

(EFC) of SPEECH–1, WRITING–1, IDEA–1, TOOL–1, and REASON–1, which can experience<br />

(AFC) JOY–1, which inalienably possesses (IPS) LANGUAGE–1, KINSHIP–1, and RACE–1 and<br />

alienably possesses (APS) JOB–1, SPOUSE–1, CLOTHING–1, NAME–1 and TOOL–1.<br />

The lists in (106) ) (108) are intended to encode information as people do; therefore, there are<br />

apparent redundancies. Notice for example that (108) specifies that humans own (APS) and use<br />

(EFC) tools. It is certainly possible for humans to use tools but not own any, e.g., some of one’s<br />

neighbors. It is also possible for humans to own tools but never use any of them.<br />

One problem with the above examples is that they do not account for variability and deviations from<br />

expected cases. To solve that problem, we can once again use the concept of prototypes. Each one<br />

of the links in the semantic network can contain a strength of association indicating how strong the<br />

link is. All links are assumed by default to have the highest strength of association on the scale from<br />

0 (lowest) to 4 (highest). When a link does not have the highest strength of association, the particular<br />

strength is indicated here in square brackets. For example, a simple network for BIRD–1 (the animal)<br />

might be the following:<br />

(109) a. BIRD–1 ––IPS ––> BILL–1<br />

b. BIRD–1 ––IPS ––> WING–1<br />

c. BIRD–1 ––APS ––> NEST–1<br />

d. BIRD–1 ––EFC ––> FLY–1<br />

e. BIRD–1 ––EFC ––> LAY_EGGS–1<br />

f. WING–1 ––INS ––> FLY–1<br />

g. FLY–1 ––TYP2 ––> LOCOMOTION–1<br />

h. AIR–1 ––LOC2 ––> FLY–1<br />

295


296<br />

The link from BIRD–1 to FLY–1 has the highest strength of association [4] by default, indicating that<br />

the prototypical bird is an agent (EFC) of FLY–1. However, there are some birds that can’t fly. We<br />

might encode that information in the following special link:<br />

(110) PENGUIN–1 ––EFC[0] ––> FLY–1<br />

Thus, although most birds (robins, sparrows, wrens, etc.) will inherit the link indicating that they are<br />

capable of flight, penguins will not because they have a specific link in the network which indicates<br />

that they cannot fly. This method is intended to capture that fact that it is quite exceptional for a bird<br />

not to be able to fly.<br />

4.19 POSTSCRIPT<br />

We began this chapter by noting that semantic analysis presents linguists with some of the thorniest<br />

problems about language they are likely to encounter. The problem of meaning is immense because,<br />

among other things, it is difficult to know where grammar ends and knowledge of the word begins.<br />

Consider, for example, what is involved in the interpretation of the following sentences which are<br />

fairly typical of the kinds of sentences people come across on a regular basis:<br />

(111) a. Wouldn’t you really love to Buick home tonight? (from a TV commercial)<br />

b. They need to adore me, so Christian–Dior me. (from the musical Evita)<br />

c. Do–it–yourself–ers generally have to call in an expert.<br />

d. Last night’s come–from–behind win by Michigan was an upset.<br />

e. “Could the most anticipated New Year’s Eve party in our lifetimes really usher in a<br />

digital nightmare when our wired–up–the–wazoo civilization grinds to a halt.”<br />

(Newsweek, 6/2/97, p. 54).<br />

f. The future isn’t what it used to be. (from the movie “Deterence”)<br />

g. Those who give up liberty for security will lose both and deserve neither. (Benjamin<br />

Franklin)<br />

h. It is better to keep your mouth shut and only appear stupid than to open it and remove<br />

all doubt. (Mark Twain)<br />

i. Thomas Demery, an ex-Birmingham developer and former top federal housing<br />

official, asked executives doing business with his agency to donate to an overseas<br />

charity whose founders solicited supporters of African guerillas who have slaughtered<br />

unarmed civilians, records and interviews show. (Detroit Free Press, 9/5/89)<br />

While the semantic networks described above might serve as a start in representing knowledge, it is<br />

clear from data like the above that much work remains to be done to account for how people<br />

understand ordinary language in ordinary situations.


EXERCISES FOR CHAPTER FOUR<br />

In many ways, <strong>linguistic</strong>s is grammatical detective work. It is knowing what questions to ask, which<br />

results to consider and which to dismiss, and how to arrive at the most generalized overall<br />

description. Remember that the underlying principles of language are logical, not arbitrary. But, as<br />

we have seen again and again, they are also hidden from obvious conscious notice.<br />

1. One of the best clues to determining underlying thematic relations is the prepositions that show<br />

up in paraphrases. For example, consider what the case of the safe is in (i).<br />

(i) The safe contains the jewels.<br />

Determining underlying thematic relation (like determining part of speech) often benefits from<br />

considerations of meaning. However, there are also many pitfalls to relying on meaning alone.<br />

While it is useful to ask oneself what role the phrase the safe plays in (i), this is not the best<br />

way to begin. Of potentially greater reliability are paraphrases. Consider (ii).<br />

(ii) The jewels are contained in the safe.<br />

Since the preposition in shows up in the paraphrase, a good guess is that the N3 the safe in (i)<br />

is LOCATIVE. Of course, we could have a genuine exception here, a purely idiosyncratic and<br />

unpredictable usage. Contrary to popular belief, this is NOT usually the case.<br />

Sometimes paraphrases with a particular verb are not possible. For example, there are no<br />

paraphrases with the verb fill in (iii) that realize the bucket as a prepositional phrase.<br />

(iii) He filled the bucket with water.<br />

On the other hand, we do have verbs like fill that involve the transference of something into<br />

something else. Consider (iv).<br />

(iv) He poured the water into the bucket.<br />

Given (iv), a good guess for the case of the bucket in (iii) is ILLATIVE. This guess receives<br />

support from inject which allows the complement structure of both (iii) and (iv), as we see in<br />

(v).<br />

(v) He injected the patient with it.<br />

He injected it into the patient.<br />

297


298<br />

Using this method, determine the underlying thematic relations for all the underlined phrases<br />

(watch for ambiguities).<br />

a. Bill resembles Bob.<br />

b. Mary knows the answer.<br />

c. John acts weird.<br />

d. Sue told Bill a lie.<br />

e. Mary met a bachelor.<br />

f. Kathy rode the horse.<br />

2. Another clue to determining underlying cases, is the form questioning and pronominalization<br />

take. Positional relations ordinarily are elicited by questions words like, where or when; they<br />

are replaceable by forms like there and then. Using these "tests" along with paraphrases,<br />

determine the underlying relations in the following phrases introduced by on:<br />

a. He put on the hat.<br />

b. He sat on the horse.<br />

c. He got on the plane.<br />

d. He insisted on the gin.<br />

e. They disagreed on the budget.<br />

f. They wrestled on the mat.<br />

3. Using the above clues, determine the uses of to in the following:<br />

a. He objected to her.<br />

b. He submitted to her.<br />

c. He wrote to her.<br />

d. He appeals to her.<br />

e. He went to her.


4. What other tests than those in Exercise One and Two can you use to help determine underlying<br />

thematic relations?<br />

5. Identify the thematic relations for each noun phrase in the following sentences (note<br />

ambiguities):<br />

a. The burglar inserted the key into the lock.<br />

b. The librarian shelved the books without her assistant.<br />

c. The teacher read the story to the students with enthusiasm.<br />

d. The cook from Paris cooked the meal.<br />

e. The cook from Paris broiled the chicken.<br />

f. The campus police are patrolling the corridors of buildings after dark in search of<br />

students.<br />

g. The soccer game takes place at Troy High on Saturday.<br />

h. The president elect is considered an honest man by many voters.<br />

i. The clothes are lying on the bed in disarray.<br />

j. Who put the glue in the toothpaste?<br />

6. In English, thematic relations functioning in subject or direct object positions lose their<br />

prepositions. Compare the following:<br />

a. The gardener sprinkled the flowers with water.<br />

b. The gardener sprinkled the water onto the flowers.<br />

c. The flowers were sprinkled with water by the gardener.<br />

d. The water was sprinkled onto the flowers by the gardener.<br />

In (a) and (b), the subject is EFC; in (c), the subject is AFC; in (d), the subject is ASC. Find<br />

as many different examples of thematic relations serving as subject as you can. Then, do the<br />

same for direct object.<br />

299


300<br />

7. How would CASE GRAMMAR describe the syntax of the following sentences?<br />

a. The boy chopped down the tree with an axe.<br />

b. John traveled from Greece to Rome.<br />

c. Sally set the table for her mother.<br />

d. In July, the harvest was ruined by rain.<br />

e. Bill hates zucchini with a passion.<br />

8. Say as much as you can, in as explicit a form as you can, about the syntax and semantics of<br />

following ambiguous sentences.<br />

a. The robot moved the patient with the nurse.<br />

b. The nurse moved the patient with a broken arm.<br />

9. Identify the thematic relations introduced by the prepositions with and without in the following<br />

(as always, note ambiguities):<br />

a. He made it WITH HER.<br />

b. He made it WITH LOVE.<br />

c. He made it WITHOUT TOOLS.<br />

d. I met several people WITHOUT CHILDREN.<br />

e. A person WITH LONG SOBRIETY is reliable.<br />

f. He went WITH THE CHILDREN.<br />

g. The sidewalk is level WITH THE STREET.<br />

h. He did it WITH GUSTO.<br />

i. He punched her WITH HIS FIST.<br />

j. He is WITHOUT THE NECESSARY FUNDS.


10. The following uses of the ABLATIVE case in Latin have been identified by the labels usually<br />

given by classical grammarians.<br />

a. THE ABLATIVE OF QUALITY:<br />

Vir summo ingenio (ABL) est.<br />

a man of the greatest genius he is<br />

He is a man of the greatest genius.<br />

b. THE ABLATIVE OF ATTENDANT CIRCUMSTANCES:<br />

Nudo corpore (ABL) pugnant.<br />

unprotected body they fight<br />

They fight with their bodies unprotected.<br />

c. THE ABLATIVE OF ACCOMPANIMENT:<br />

Omnibus copiis (ABL) subsequebatur.<br />

with all forces he followed<br />

He followed with all his forces.<br />

d. THE ABLATIVE OF COMPARISON:<br />

Cato est Cicerone (ABL) eloquentior.<br />

Cato is than Cicero more eloquent<br />

Cato is more eloquent than Cicero.<br />

e. THE ABLATIVE OF MANNER:<br />

Mirabili celeritate (ABL) venerunt.<br />

wonderful speed they came<br />

They came with wonderful speed.<br />

f. THE ABLATIVE OF MEANS:<br />

Pugnis (ABL) certant.<br />

with fists they fight<br />

They fight with their fists.<br />

Reclassify each of the above ablatives in our terminology, that is, find the thematic relations<br />

they express. Is there a way to generalize the Latin ablative using the RG feature matrix? If<br />

so, what is the generalization?<br />

301


302<br />

APPENDIX A: SUMMARY OF THEMATIC RELATIONS<br />

1. CASE GRAMMAR (THEMATIC RELATIONS ARE ATOMIC CATEGORIES):<br />

a. AGENTIVE: the case of the typically animate perceived instigator of the action<br />

identified in the verb (often simply called AGENT).<br />

(1) JOHN opened the door.<br />

(2) The door was opened BY JOHN.<br />

(3) THE DEAN sent a note.<br />

(4) A note was sent BY THE DEAN.<br />

(5) There was a note FROM THE DEAN.<br />

b. SOURCE: the case which identifies the origin of the state or action identified in the<br />

verb.<br />

(1) John flew FROM ITALY.<br />

(2) John ran OUT OF THE HOUSE.<br />

c. DATIVE: the case of the usually animate entity affected by the state or action identified<br />

in the verb (often called EXPERIENCER or RECIPIENT).<br />

(1) John gave the book TO BILL.<br />

(2) BILL received the book.<br />

(3) The movie appeals to HIM.<br />

(4) THE SNOW melted.<br />

b. GOAL: the case which identifies the direction of the state or action identified in the<br />

verb.<br />

(1) John flew TO ITALY.<br />

(2) John ran INTO THE HOUSE.


2. RG SEMANTICS:<br />

a. [+POSITIONAL] [–POSITIONAL]<br />

He put it into the vase. He turned it into a vase.<br />

He took it out of a vase. He made it out of a vase.<br />

b. [+POSITIONAL] ([+PST]): having the primary focus on location, orientation, or<br />

movement in space or time.<br />

c. [–POSITIONAL] ([–PST]): not having the primary focus on location, orientation, or<br />

movement in space or time.<br />

d. [+DISJUNCTURAL] ([+DSJ]): emphasizing separation, dissociation, detachment,<br />

withdrawal and the like.<br />

e. [–DISJUNCTURAL] ([–DSJ]): not emphasizing dissociative ideas.<br />

f. [+CONJUNCTURAL] ([+CNJ]): emphasizing union, association, attachment, advance<br />

and the like.<br />

g. [–CONJUNCTURAL] ([–CNJ]): not emphasizing associative ideas.<br />

3. RG SEMANTICS (THEMATIC RELATIONS ARE BUNDLES OF FEATURES):<br />

a. SOURCE: [+PST, +DSJ, –CNJ] from<br />

b. AGENT: [–PST, +DSJ, –CNJ] from, by<br />

d. GOAL: [+PST, –DSJ, +CNJ] to<br />

e. EXPERIENCER: [–PST, –DSJ, +CNJ] to<br />

303


304


CHAPTER FIVE: LANGUAGE, PEOPLE, AND COMPUTERS<br />

5.1 SYNTAX AND COGNITION<br />

As we have seen, each semantic category (thematic relation) and syntactic category (part of speech)<br />

in RG is distinguished from and related to all other such categories by a system of features, so that,<br />

in fact, each category is no more than an abbreviation for a bundle of these features in the way that<br />

a sound such as [p] is an abbreviation in phonology for a bundle of phonological features like<br />

[+CONSONANTAL], [–VOCALIC], [–VOICED], etc. The figures in the preceding chapters<br />

expresses the interface between the categories of RG and some of the more traditional categories.<br />

As we have seen, one of the distinguishing aspects of RG is that its syntactic feature matrix<br />

recognizes two supercategories not found in other theories of syntax. These are the category<br />

ADJUNCT ([–VBL]3 or, more simply, A3), which subsumes all of the traditional categories except<br />

verbs, and the category CHARACTERIZER ([–VBL, –NML]3 or, more simply, C3), which<br />

subsumes all of the remaining traditional categories except nouns. The breakdown is diagramed in<br />

(1) (see (170) in Chapter Three, Page 171).<br />

(1)<br />

[+VBL] includes VERB, AUXILIARY, MODAL, GERUND, INFINITIVE<br />

[–VBL] includes NOUN, PRONOUN, QUANTIFIER, ADJECTIVE, ADVERB,<br />

PREPOSITION, SUBORDINATOR, COORDINATOR,<br />

COMPLEMENTIZER, DETERMINER, DEGREE WORD<br />

[+NML] includes NOUN, PRONOUN, QUANTIFIER, GERUNDS<br />

[–NML] includes VERB, AUXILIARY, MODAL, ADJECTIVE, ADVERB,<br />

PREPOSITION, SUBORDINATOR, COORDINATOR,<br />

COMPLEMENTIZER, DETERMINER, DEGREE WORD<br />

Given this syntactic framework together with the phonological features described in Chapter Two<br />

and the semantic features described in Chapter Four, we have the following breakdown for the major<br />

categories of language:


306<br />

(2) PHONOLOGY (see Figure Five on Page 62):<br />

a. [αCON, –αVOC] — consonants and vowels<br />

(1) [+CON, –VOC] — consonants ([p], [t], [k], etc.)<br />

(2) [–CON, +VOC] — vowels ([a], [e], [i], [o], [u], etc.)<br />

b. [αCON, αVOC] — liquids and glides<br />

(1) [–CON, –VOC] — glides ([w], [y], etc.)<br />

(2) [+CON, +VOC] — liquids ([r], [l], etc.)<br />

(3) SEMANTICS (see Figure Nine on Page 277 and Figure Ten on Page 280):<br />

a. [αDSJ, –αCNJ] — expressions of motion and causation<br />

(1) [+DSJ, –CNJ] — source (extract, exit, take, buy, from, out of, etc.)<br />

(2) [–DSJ, +CNJ] — goal (insert, enter, give, sell, into, to, etc.)<br />

b. [αDSJ, αCNJ] — expressions of location and possession<br />

(1) [–DSJ, –CNJ] — location/possession (live, contain, have, own, with, etc.)<br />

(2) [+DSJ, +CNJ] — nonlocation/nonpossession (lack, differ, without, etc.)<br />

(4) SYNTAX (see Figure Eight on Page 183):<br />

a. [αVBL, –αNML] — verbs and nouns<br />

(1) [+VBL, –NML] — verbs (destroy, predict, refuse, etc.)<br />

(2) [–VBL, +NML] — nouns (destruction, predication, refusal, etc.)<br />

b. [αVBL, αNML] — characterizers and gerunds<br />

(1) [–VBL, –NML] — adjectives (sad), adverbs (sadly), prepositions (to), etc.<br />

(2) [+VBL, +NML] — gerunds (swimming)<br />

The central concept of RG syntax is the concept RESIDENCE which is a specific syntactic or<br />

morphological position that is associated with a specific semantic relation. For example, the category<br />

label DETERMINER or DET simply specifies a group of words that occupy a [+PRH, +X3L, +ENH]<br />

residence, that is, that occur in prehead position ([+PRH]) on the X3 level ([+X3L]) of a category<br />

whose head is a noun ([+ENH]). Every syntactic category (part of speech) in RG is defined in this<br />

way, as a constellation of syntactic features that refer only to positions in phrase structure.<br />

The full range of syntactic features in RG provide a noun phrase like all those many young<br />

philosopher kings of Greece from Rome with the diagram in (5).


(5) all those many young philosopher kings of Greece from Rome<br />

The phrasal architecture of diagrams like (5) is used in RG to specify the relationship between related<br />

<strong>structures</strong>: expressions of quantity (all), definiteness (those), and the like are always residents of the<br />

X3 level, that is, they are daughters of X3; all descriptive modifiers of the head, e.g., adjectives<br />

(young), restrictive relative clauses, and participial and prepositional phrases (from Rome), are<br />

residents of the X2 level; in X1 level prehead position reside the elements of compounds (philosopher<br />

in philosopher king); and, in X1 level posthead position reside all complements of the head X<br />

(Greece in king of Greece).<br />

As a result of such specifications, RG directly incorporates into the phrasal architecture many<br />

relationships which other grammars handle transformationally. The potential difficulty of<br />

constructing a revealing set of phrase structure rules is solved with the use of the syntactic features<br />

given in Figure Eight (Page 183). All possible phrase structure sequences in English are reducible<br />

to one phrase structure filter (PSF), namely, (6).<br />

307


308<br />

(6) [X n ([+NML]) ([–NML]) X m ([+NML]) ([–NML]) ]<br />

where m # n<br />

(6) can be interpreted as a NODE ADMISSIBILITY CONDITION, that is, a condition on what<br />

nodes can consist of. It asserts that each X level must dominate a lower X level with an equal or<br />

lesser prime value, e. g., X2 over X2, X1, or X but not X2 over X3. Further, (6) asserts that each X<br />

level may have at most one [+NML] and one [–NML] category, in that order, to the right and/or to<br />

the left of the head X.<br />

The schema (6) means that syntactic categories in RG all refer to the basic phrasal structure (7).<br />

(7)<br />

From each X level (m # n), both to the left and to the right of the head, can occur at most two<br />

elements. The first of these two is specified by the feature [+NML]; the second, by the feature<br />

[–NML]. In short, the feature opposition [±NUM] refers to specific linear positions in a hierarchy<br />

of positions, and nothing more. Thus, [+NML] is something that occurs in position α of (8); [–NML]<br />

is something that occurs in position β.<br />

(8)<br />

The feature [+NML] is the major defining feature of the English syntactic category commonly<br />

referred to as Noun. All RG syntactic categories are similarly defined. To take another example, the<br />

feature opposition [±ENH] (in the environment of noun head) refers to either α or β in (9).<br />

(9)<br />

Notice that RG syntax claims that there can be at most five units on any one level. Although RG<br />

phrase structure was worked out solely on the basic of syntactic evidence, that is, autonomously, this


number is, interestingly, the lower end of human short–term memory capacity. The claim in RG is<br />

that the severe restrictions on human short term memory demand that the syntax of human languages<br />

be organized into hierarchical units, and that the definitions of syntactic categories make reference<br />

to those hierarchical units. All twelve of the RG syntactic features are so defined.<br />

In RG syntax, there are, of course, dependencies. Consider for example the diagram (10).<br />

(10)<br />

If X is [+NML], then β is a characterizer, typically, a determiner. If X is [–NML] and δ is [+NML],<br />

then X is a transitive verb and δ is its direct object. These specifications are determined by the RG<br />

syntactic feature matrix (Figure Eight, Page 183). From such specificity, one derives the concept of<br />

residence. For example, one says that a determiner is nothing more than a class of words that resides<br />

in X3 Level Prehead position of a [+NML] category.<br />

In recent years, there has been much research on the problem of writing a computer program which<br />

can understand natural language. Such a program is called a PARSER. In fact, in the summer of<br />

1989, there was a renewed flurry of interest in developing programs for translating texts from one<br />

language into another. The Japanese, in particular, have currently invested considerable resources<br />

in the field of machine translation.<br />

An RG computer parser is based on the concept of residence. There is, therefore, a direct connection<br />

between a theory of syntax, human syntactic ability, and the algorithms necessary to make a parser<br />

work. This connection is revealed in the number of distinct advantages there are to developing a<br />

parser based on a feature–based analysis of language, as opposed to an analysis based on atomic<br />

syntactic and semantic categories.<br />

First, when a parser based on TG or on traditional grammar looks up a word, say, the, in the<br />

dictionary, it usually returns a part–of–speech specification such as [+DETERMINER]. Similarly,<br />

when it looks up available, it returns a specification such as [+ADJECTIVE]. Such categorial<br />

specifications provide very limited help in facilitating further parsing, particularly in determining<br />

what the immediate and upcoming structural possibilities are. The reason for this is that features like<br />

[+DETERMINER] and [+ADJECTIVE] have never been adequately defined in syntactic terms in<br />

either TG or traditional grammar; hence, computerized parsing programs have been hampered by the<br />

lack of an available syntactic feature framework on which to base parsing strategies.<br />

309


310<br />

On the other hand, a parser based on RG receives very useful information in a dictionary lookup.<br />

Determiners, as we have seen from Figure Eight (Page 183), are [+PRH, –PSH, +X3L, +ENH,...],<br />

which means that they occur only in prehead position on the X3 Level of noun phrases; further,<br />

adjectives are generally [+PRH, –PSH, +X2L, +ENH,...], which means that they reside in posthead<br />

position on the X2 Level of noun phrases. An adjective like available is exceptional in being marked<br />

[+PSH]. This information exactly specifies the syntactic structure that should be assigned to a<br />

sequence of words that begins, say, with the available. As a result of such precise syntactic<br />

specifications, a structural analysis of successive words in a sentence can be built and checked with<br />

great speed and accuracy by an RG parser. Therefore, the RG feature system has provided a new<br />

paradigm on which to base a parsing strategy.<br />

A second advantage of a feature system is that so–called cross categorial relationships can be very<br />

succinctly specified. Consider, for example, the word that. Traditional and transformational<br />

grammars analyze this word as either one of the following four categories: determiner, as in That<br />

man is famous; degree word, as in He is that famous; complementizer, as in I know that he is famous;<br />

and, relative pronoun, as in The man that John saw is famous. In RG, the word that receives the<br />

feature specifications in (11).<br />

(11)<br />

VBL NML OPH OCL PRH PSH ENH EVH ECH X1L X2L X3L<br />

REL – – – – + – – + – – – +<br />

CPL – – – – + – – + – – – +<br />

DET – – – – + – + – – – – +<br />

DGR – – – – + – + – – – – +<br />

As (11) indicates, ten of the twelve RG features are the same for all uses of the word that. Further,<br />

the determiner and degree word have identical feature matrices, and so do the relative pronoun and<br />

complementizer. Through this system we can see how one word can come to have such “diverse”<br />

uses. Actually, the RG description of English does not include a category REL at all; its inclusion<br />

in (11) is for comparative purposes only. Similarly, the RG description of English contains no<br />

category demonstrative pronoun, common in traditional descriptions. A sentence such as Look at<br />

that is really look at that [u], where [u] means ‘understood’ thing. The feature specifications in (11)<br />

are represented diagrammatically in (12), where the N3 [much] is an abstract quantifier (before<br />

nouns the word much is overt as in that much bread and that much money; before characterizers, it<br />

is abstract as in that famous and that happily).<br />

As (12) reveals, all instances of that reside in X3 level prehead position. A parser based on this<br />

analysis will naturally function in a highly efficient manner. When the word that is encountered in<br />

a sentence, the parser can assign it ten of the twelve possible RG features without consideration of<br />

context. Conversely, a parser based on the categories of traditional or transformational grammar is<br />

unable to assign any analysis at all to the word that without considering the context in which it is<br />

used.


(12) I know that (CPL) that (DET) man that (REL) John saw seems that (DGR) famous.<br />

A third advantage of the RG feature system is that it is completely nontransformational and allows<br />

for the direct expression of alternative constructions such as those discussed above, e.g., available<br />

books versus books available. RG syntactic constraints are stated with reference to surface structure,<br />

so that parsing is further facilitated by the complete elimination of the concept of syntactic derivation<br />

through transformation. The RG paradigm directly generates and interprets all sentences without<br />

reference to deep <strong>structures</strong> such as those found in every version of TG.<br />

The direct application of RG to computer parsing has had a salutary effect on the problem of<br />

adequately characterizing the grammar of English. In many cases, parsing difficulties have lead to<br />

a better understanding of syntax. Constraints on language structure are directly related to parsibility,<br />

311


312<br />

the ability of people or machines to understand language. For example, constraints on the internal<br />

structure of English noun phrases appear to be directly related to the problem of locating the head of<br />

the noun phrase. To see this, consider again the word that in the following:<br />

(13) a. A teacher of that language is hard to find.<br />

b. *A that language teacher is hard to find.<br />

(14) a. A teacher that clever is hard to find.<br />

b. *A that clever teacher is hard to find.<br />

(15) a. How clever (of) a teacher is she?<br />

b. That clever (of) a teacher is hard to find.<br />

c. *Very clever (of) a teacher is hard to find.<br />

These are not peculiar or disconnected data, and the explanation for the constructions is clear with<br />

an RG model. A prehead modifier in an N3 cannot have its own determiner unless it is to the left of<br />

the word of (we will see why this is so shortly). Since determiners and degree words share identical<br />

sets of RG features (see (11)), the source of the ungrammaticality of (13b) with DETERMINER–that<br />

and (14b) with DEGREE–that is the same. They violate this general phrase structure restriction on<br />

prehead modifiers in N3.<br />

On the other hand, we do have (15a) and (15b), which contain adjective phrases with their own<br />

degree modifiers to the left of of. Actually, these adjective phrases are quantificational: how clever<br />

is, abstractly, how [much] clever; that clever is that [much] clever. The occurrence of such a phrase<br />

in such a position in other theories of English syntax is an oddity. This is not the case in an RG. The<br />

X3 level prehead residence of all categories is the home of expressions of quantification. This<br />

explains the presence of of in (15a) and (15b), and it rules out (15c) because very clever lacks a<br />

quantifier.<br />

The same logic applied in (13) and (14) explains the loss of the complementizer in (16a) as compared<br />

to its presence in (17b):<br />

(16) CPL obligatorily absent:<br />

a. I am an I’d–rather–do–it–myself person.<br />

I am [ N3 [ C3 an ] [ N1 [ V3 I’d rather–do–it–myself ] [ N0 person] ] ]<br />

b. *I am a that–I’d–rather–do–it–myself person.<br />

(17) CPL obligatorily present:<br />

a. *I’d rather do it myself ought to be clear.<br />

b. That I’d rather do it myself ought to be clear.


Given the above data, the RG analysis seems justifiable: all uses of that are essentially the same<br />

word.<br />

The above generalizations are important because they link the study of syntax directly to the kinds<br />

of routines a computer parser contains, as well as to human psychology and biology. The claim of<br />

RG is that all N3 with non–quantifier heads, that is heads which are [+NML, +OCL], must have a<br />

determiner (the, those, Ø, etc.) as a PERMANENT RESIDENT (one not omissible) in X3 level<br />

prehead position. This claim can be supported independently and autonomously by examining<br />

English syntax. In turn, this claim from syntactic investigation can be related to the nature of the<br />

human language apparatus. The determiner in an English N3 acts like a cuing device with the<br />

message here comes a noun phrase. Between this cuing device and the head, there can be no other<br />

determiners; hence, we have neither (13b) nor (14b). This syntactic constraint makes it possible to<br />

write an algorithm that unambiguously finds the head of N3, a fact discovered during the writing of<br />

the first RG parser. In short, the description of the English N3 in RG has a direct relationship with<br />

computer parsing and with sentence comprehension.<br />

It is interesting to note that the determiner of N3 parallels the wh–phrase of V3 interrogatives: (i)<br />

both are prehead X3 level adjuncts ([+VBL, +PRH, +X3L]); (ii) both are permanent residents; (iii)<br />

repetitions of both are impossible, because repetitions produce self–embedded constructions like (18)<br />

and (19); both act like cuing devices.<br />

(18) *[ N3 that i [ N3 that j [ language j ] ] teacher i ]<br />

(19) *[ V3 where i [ V3 what j [ did he put [e] j [e] i ] ] ]<br />

The RG approach to grammar has uncovered some provocative connections between human language<br />

and human biology. As we have seen, the generality of the RG syntactic feature matrix makes<br />

possible the reduction of all phrases and clauses to variations on a single schema (3). In itself, this<br />

is a significant result. But the schema does not exist in theoretical isolation. We have seen that it<br />

allows at most five units per phrase, which is the lower end of human short term memory capacity.<br />

From this relationship between grammatical and psychological unit, one can formulate hypotheses<br />

about the relationship between grammatical constructs and the nature of man, for example, the<br />

hypothesis that syntactic organizing principles like verb agreement derive from constraints on human<br />

memory and human perceptual abilities. Consider, for example, the case of so–called free word order<br />

languages like Classical Latin, which has the syntactic rules in (20) and the rules of concord in (21):<br />

(20) a. The subject is in the nominative case.<br />

b. The direct object is in the accusative case.<br />

(21) a. A finite verb and its subject must agree in person and number.<br />

b. A noun and adjective must agree in case, number, and gender.<br />

313


314<br />

Given (20) and (21), the sentences in (22) could, theoretically, be uttered with the individual words<br />

in any order (NS = nominative singular, NP = nominative plural, AS = accusative singular, AP =<br />

accusative plural, 3S = third person singular, 3P = third person plural).<br />

(22) a. Custos fidelis consulem veterem ducit.<br />

NS NS AS AS 3S<br />

guard trusty consul old is leading<br />

The trusty guard is leading the old consul.<br />

b. Custodes fideles consules veteres ducunt.<br />

NP/AP NP/AP NP/AP NP/AP 3P<br />

The trusty guards are leading the old consuls.<br />

The old guards are leading the trusty consuls.<br />

The trusty consuls are leading the old guards.<br />

The old consuls are leading the trusty guards.<br />

Notice that the rules of syntax (20) and concord (21) completely disambiguate (22a). However, (22b)<br />

is presumably four–ways ambiguous, because the es–ending is either nominative or accusative plural.<br />

Needless to say, one rarely comes upon sentences like (22b) in the literature, though ambiguities are<br />

found as in any language. The point here is that so–called free word order languages like Classical<br />

Latin must have some devices like (20) and (21) to hold together the integrity of the clausal unit.<br />

Latin, like all other languages, is constrained because of human neurological limitations: humans are<br />

not clairvoyant (usually), and they operate with severe constraints on short term memory. Quite<br />

naturally, languages have invented a number of devices to handle these limitations. Concord is a<br />

means of binding phrases together when word order constraints are relaxed. In such cases, all the<br />

elements of a phrase need not be under one node. Since English is relatively poor in inflectional<br />

endings, it has very severe restrictions on word order. Therefore, most constructions in English are<br />

continuous, that is, all the elements in the construction occur successively. But there are a few<br />

constructions that are discontinuous, such as the b examples in the following pairs:<br />

(23) a. The wind blew open the barn door.<br />

b. The wind blew the barn door open.<br />

(24) a. John called up a former girl friend.<br />

b. John called a former girl friend up.<br />

Such constructions are under severe limitations of short term memory. If the direct object is too<br />

internally complex, the sentences become unacceptable:


(25) a. John called a former girl friend from Texas up.<br />

b. ?John called a former girl friend he used to date when he lived in Texas up.<br />

c. *John called a former girl friend he used to date when he was working as a rattle<br />

snake defanger in Texas up.<br />

Much more is known today about the nature of the human language apparatus than was known in<br />

1957, the year of Chomsky’s Syntactic Structures and Skinner’s Verbal Behavior. For example, a<br />

number of psychological processes can be directly connected to human <strong>linguistic</strong> abilities; in<br />

particular, man’s ability to deal with unstructured expressions is very limited. The structuring<br />

processes important in language include linear ordering, hierarchical ordering, and cuing. Thus,<br />

many studies indicate quite clearly that the justification of phrase <strong>structures</strong> must assume a very high<br />

priority in grammatical description. In the grammatical model we have described, this is exactly the<br />

case: the model attempts to draw a connection between human syntactic ability and human memory<br />

capacity.<br />

The objective of RG research is to provide a biological basis for grammatical description. In<br />

particular, the model draws a connection between human syntactic ability and human memory<br />

capacity. Let us now examine this more carefully focusing on the description and interpretation of<br />

English noun phrases (N3) and sentences (V3).<br />

As we have seen, all nouns and verbs in English are specified by the following features:<br />

(26) CLASS FEATURES EXAMPLES<br />

Common Verbs: [+VBL, –NML, +OCL] go, eat<br />

Auxiliary Verbs: [+VBL, –NML, –OCL] may, can<br />

Common Nouns: [–VBL, +NML, +OCL] cake, toy<br />

Quantifiers and Pronouns: [–VBL, +NML, –OCL] some, she<br />

Notice that verbs and nouns fall into two groups distinguished by the feature opposition [+OCL]<br />

meaning ‘open class word.’ Such common verbs and nouns must have an X3 level prehead<br />

characterizer, which is called a BINDING RESIDENT (BR). The BR itself is really an abbreviation<br />

for the cluster [–VBL, –NML, –OCL, –ECH, +X3L, –X2L, –X1L, +PRH]. This includes the<br />

categories COMPLEMENTIZER, DETERMINER, CASE (POSSESSIVE), and TENSE. The<br />

domain of a BR, which includes all nodes it C–commands, is called a NEIGHBORHOOD (see<br />

Section 3.8, Page 195 ff.). In common nouns, the BR is a determiner or POS (the possessive case);<br />

in main verbs, it is tense (PRESENT, PAST, FUTURE, CONDITIONAL, IMPERATIVE). We have<br />

representations like the following:<br />

315


316<br />

(27) N3:<br />

(28) V3:<br />

a. that vote:<br />

b. John’s vote (POS = POSSESSIVE):<br />

c. all the votes:<br />

a. Vote! (IMP = IMPERATIVE):<br />

b. John voted (PST = PAST TENSE):


In V3, complementizers are also a BR. In most indirect statements in English, a complementizer BR<br />

is optional; it is a FREE RESIDENT:<br />

(29) John thinks that Sue went.<br />

John thinks Sue went.<br />

In indirect questions in English, a complementizer BR is obligatory; it is a PERMANENT<br />

RESIDENT:<br />

(30) John wonders if Sue went.<br />

*John wonders Sue went.<br />

317


318<br />

Notice that each BR, whether a free or a permanent resident, occupies a fixed position in underlying<br />

(abstract) syntax when it does occur. If a BR, in addition, occupies a fixed position in superficial<br />

syntax, then it acts as a BARRIER to reference, that is, it does not allow categories on either “side”<br />

of it to refer to each other.<br />

English contains a number of different categories called ANAPHORS which refer to other phrases.<br />

For example, in John takes care of himself, the phrase himself refers to the phrase John. There are<br />

conditions on such reference. For example, in John told Bill to take care of himself, himself can only<br />

refer to Bill, not to John. The element [e], which we discussed in Chapter Three, is also an anaphor.<br />

As we have seen, it must be bound to a referent (see Section 3.8, Page 195 ff.). Sometimes this<br />

reference is blocked by a barrier BR. Thus, one can ask a question like What did John say that Sue<br />

bought, when the sentence has the free resident that. However, one cannot ask a question like *What<br />

did John wonder if Sue bought, when the sentence contains the permanent resident if.<br />

Those BR that are barriers include DET, POS and CPL. The position of each of these categories in<br />

both underlying and superficial syntax is fixed (when they occur). Also, each of these is a<br />

HEAD–ONLY CATEGORY, that is, a category that tolerates no prehead or posthead adjuncts on<br />

any of its own internal levels. Their structure is simply [C3 C0].<br />

The one BR that is never a barrier to reference is TNS. Its position in underlying syntax is fixed<br />

([–ENH, +EVH, –ECH, +X3L, –X2L, –X1L, +PRH, –PSH]), but its realization in superficial syntax<br />

is variable: sometimes it appears on the modal, sometimes on the main verb, sometimes on the<br />

perfective have, etc. Also, TNS can have a rather complex internal structure of its own that might<br />

include modals, perfective, negatives, emphatics, etc. Apparently, for a BR to be a barrier, its<br />

position in both underlying and superficial syntax must be fixed and simple. We will explore the<br />

reason for this below.<br />

A barrier BR establishes one of two types of RESIDENTIAL DOMAINS, which we can specify<br />

explicitly by extending the C–command relation (see Section 3.8, Page 195 ff.) as follows:<br />

(31) a. C–COMMAND: a category α C–commands another category β if the first branching<br />

category Z above α dominates β.<br />

b. L–COMMAND: a category α L–commands another category β if α C–commands<br />

β and if β is an anaphor to the left of the head of Z.<br />

c. R–COMMAND: a category α R–commands another category β if α C–commands β<br />

and if β is an anaphor to the right of the head of Z.<br />

Notice that these two new command relations simply extend the original definition and make<br />

reference to the left–to–right (linear) position of constituents. This extension is crucial to describe<br />

the restrictions on anaphoric processes in English, that is, on the rules which determine what<br />

anaphors can refer to in sentences. Given the new relations, we can make the following<br />

generalizations:


(32) a. If a barrier is a free resident (optional), its residential domain includes all items it<br />

L–commands.<br />

b. If a barrier is a permanent resident (obligatory), its residential domain includes all<br />

items it either L–commands or R–commands.<br />

c. A binding relationship cannot be formed with an empty category that falls within a<br />

residential domain.<br />

In each of the following, observe, in particular, that questioning an item commanded by the barrier<br />

BR is impossible (the b example is ungrammatical), and that the barrier BR is obligatory (the c<br />

example is ungrammatical):<br />

(33) [Bill’s vote against gun control]; common noun head vote:<br />

a. Mary criticized Bill’s vote against gun control.<br />

b. *What i did Mary criticize Bill’s vote against [N3 e ] I?<br />

c. *Mary criticized vote against gun control.<br />

d. Mary criticized the vote against gun control.<br />

(34) Indirect question:<br />

a. Mary wondered if Bill voted against gun control.<br />

b. *What i did Mary wonder if Bill voted against [N3 e ] I?<br />

c. *Mary wondered Bill voted against gun control.<br />

d. *Who i did Mary wonder if [N3 e ] I voted against gun control?<br />

e. *Who i did Mary wonder [N3 e ] I voted against gun control?<br />

(35) Indirect Statement with obligatory barrier BR:<br />

a. Mary chortled that Bill voted against gun control.<br />

b. *What i did Mary chortle that Bill voted against [N3 e ] I?<br />

c. *Mary chortled Bill voted against gun control.<br />

d. *Who i did Mary chortle that [N3 e ] I voted against gun control?<br />

e. *Who i did Mary chortle [N3 e ] I voted against gun control?<br />

In contrast to (33) – (35), observe that the data fall out differently when the barrier BR is a free<br />

resident; it is only when the barrier BR is present and L–commands the empty category that<br />

ungrammaticality results:<br />

319


320<br />

(36) Indirect Statement with optional barrier BR:<br />

a. Mary thought that Bill voted against gun control.<br />

b. What i did Mary think that Bill voted against [N3 e ] I?<br />

c. Mary thought Bill voted against gun control.<br />

d. *Who i did Mary think that [N3 e ] I voted against gun control?<br />

e. Who i did Mary think [N3 e ] I voted against gun control?<br />

Sometimes it appears as though there is no BR in an N3 with a common noun head, specifically,<br />

when the head is a plural count noun (votes) or a mass noun (water). However, in such cases, the null<br />

determiner Ø is present:<br />

(37)<br />

There are a number of reasons for positing this particular empty category. First, it allows us to<br />

distinguish between nouns that ordinarily can have determiners (all common nouns) and those that<br />

ordinarily can’t:<br />

(38) COMMON, COUNT NOUN:<br />

a. He wants those votes<br />

b. He wants Ø votes<br />

c. He wants a vote<br />

d. *He wants vote<br />

(39) COMMON, MASS NOUN:<br />

a. He wants that freedom.<br />

b. He wants Ø freedom.<br />

c. *He wants freedom.<br />

(40) NONCOMMON NOUNS (PROPER NOUNS, QUANTIFIERS, PRONOUNS):<br />

a. *He wants the John Smith.<br />

(but: Will the John Smith from Troy please stand?)<br />

b. *He wants the some.<br />

c. *He wants the them.


Given the Ø–analysis, we say that an N3 with a common noun head has an obligatory BR, whereas<br />

one with a noncommon noun head does not.<br />

A second reason for the Ø–analysis is that, with it, the following data are parallel to (33) – (36):<br />

(41) [ Ø votes against gun control]; common noun head vote:<br />

a. Mary criticized Ø votes against gun control.<br />

b. *What i did Mary criticize Ø votes against [N3 e ] I?<br />

c. *Mary criticized votes against gun control.<br />

d. Mary criticized that vote against gun control.<br />

Third, if we adopt an analysis with Ø, we can generalize the insertion of of in all the following:<br />

(42) a. A number of the systems are complicated.<br />

b. A number of those systems are complicated.<br />

c. A number of Ø systems are complicated.<br />

Given this description, we can now explore what the function of a barrier BR is. In both V3 and N3,<br />

the barrier BR, as the obligatory element, signals the beginning of the phrase. Therefore, we might<br />

suppose that, for parsing purposes, it acts like a cuing device. We see this most clearly in subject<br />

complements where the complementizer can never be left out:<br />

(43) a. That Bill voted against gun control is odd.<br />

b. * Bill voted against gun control is odd.<br />

c. *What i that Bill voted against [N3 e ] I is odd.<br />

Leaving out the complementizer in (43b) results in a miscue: it appears as though the clause Bill<br />

voted against gun control is the main clause of the sentence.<br />

In N3, the major parsing problem is locating the head. Consider the following observing the number<br />

on the verb:<br />

(44) a. The school shows play here. (Subject is shows; the verb play is plural.)<br />

b. The school show plays here. (Subject is show; the verb plays is singular).<br />

c. The school shows plays here. (Subject is school; the verb shows is singular.)<br />

d. The schools show plays here. (Subject is schools; the verb show is plural.)<br />

As these examples attest, finding the head of an N3 is not always straightforward, particularly when<br />

a compound noun interpretation like school show(s) or student teacher(s) is possible. But the<br />

language does provide a number of constraints that facilitate the correct location of the head.<br />

321


322<br />

First, the only noun in a compound noun phrase that can have its own BR is the head:<br />

(45) a. a teacher of Sanskrit<br />

a Sanskrit teacher<br />

b. a teacher of that language<br />

*a that language teacher<br />

a language teacher<br />

c. Ø teachers of that language<br />

*Ø that language teachers<br />

Ø language teachers<br />

d. a teacher that clever (is hard to find)<br />

*a that clever teacher (is hard to find)<br />

a clever teacher (is hard to find)<br />

Second, the only noun in a compound noun phrase that can be plural is the head:<br />

(46) a. a teacher of Ø languages<br />

*a Ø languages teacher<br />

a language teacher<br />

b. a wall of four feet<br />

*a four feet wall<br />

a four foot wall<br />

*a wall of four foot<br />

Third, any item occurring to the left of the BR must be separated from the BR by the word of:<br />

(47) a. A number of the systems are complicated.<br />

b. A number of Ø systems are complicated.<br />

c. *the number Ø systems ...<br />

d. The number systems are complicated.<br />

(here number systems is a compound noun)<br />

Fourth, if no overt marker is present separating a head noun from its complement, e.g., against in a<br />

vote against gun control, then of must be inserted to signal the right boundary of the head:<br />

(48) a. The student letters are here.<br />

The student of letters is here.<br />

b. His love stories are charming.<br />

His love of stories is charming.<br />

Thus, if the head noun is a singular count noun, we know what the left boundary of the head is,<br />

because in such cases the BR is overt (cf. (38c)). If the head is a plural count noun, the BR need not<br />

be overt, that is, Ø is possible (cf. (38b)). But, in such a case, we know that the plural noun must be<br />

the head because only the head can be plural in a compound noun sequence.


Summarizing, we have the following N3 constraints:<br />

(49) The N3 Constraints:<br />

323<br />

a. All N3 with a common noun head must have a BR as a permanent resident. This BR<br />

is either a determiner or the possessive case.<br />

b. Items to the left of the BR are separated from the BR by of.<br />

c. Items to the right of the head are separated from the head by of if no overt<br />

characterizer is present.<br />

d. Any noun occurring between the BR and the head cannot have any of its own X3<br />

Level elements:<br />

(1) Such nouns show no number or case distinctions of their own.<br />

(2) Such nouns have no determiners of their own.<br />

This conspiracy of restrictions works very well. There are some minor exceptions. The quantifier<br />

all does not have to be followed by of:<br />

(50) They counted all (of) the votes.<br />

There are a few sporadic N3 where a plural (usually irregular) is not the head:<br />

(51) a. I met the women delegates.<br />

b. *I met the ladies delegates.<br />

c. I met the lady delegates.<br />

Despite these minor glitches, the N3 Constraint is well established for English. We may now ask<br />

why a language should have such a constraint. Since the N3 constraint was discovered during the<br />

search for an algorithm for locating the head of an N3, it has always seemed natural to conclude that<br />

the reason for the constraint is just that, namely, to help locate the head of an N3. This conclusion<br />

concurs with the RG hypothesis that syntax and memory are linked. Let us now investigate this<br />

connection.<br />

No matter how large and internally complex an N3 becomes, we have seen that there are never more<br />

than five units on any level; that N3 always precede C3 on each level, both to the left of the head and<br />

to the right of the head; that of separates quantifiers and determiners; that of separates the head from<br />

following posthead modifiers. Thus, the essential structure of every N3 is (52) with area X<br />

specifying the bounds of the N3 Constraints.


324<br />

(52) N3<br />

+))))0)))))))3)))),<br />

...of.......DET...........N0........of...<br />

.)))0))))-<br />

8 8 X 8 8<br />

anchor cue head anchor<br />

The area marked “X” in (52) is the area in which three of the noun phrase constraints operate. Within<br />

X, there can be only one determiner and only singular nouns. Since any violation of these constraints<br />

makes it impossible to locate the head unambiguously, the suggestion is that the constraints are not<br />

arbitrary; rather, they exist to help speakers locate the head of a noun phrase.<br />

Notice that, with the constraints, ambiguity disappears. First, the word of acts like anchor points<br />

delineating the boundaries of the head. Second, if the head is singular, the noun phrase must be cued<br />

by an overt determiner; we don’t have sentences like *he is carrying book. Third, if the head is<br />

plural, the determiner need not be overt (he is carrying books), but in such cases one knows that the<br />

plural noun must be the head, because the only allowable plural between the DET and the head is the<br />

head. In short, the constraints appear to result from cognitive limitations. Humans are not<br />

clairvoyant and need structural principles to locate the heads of phrases in languages like English.<br />

The N3 Constraints are such principles.<br />

Given this analysis, we have an explanation for why the past tense has become regular in English for<br />

all persons and number, but the present tense has not. Compare (53) and (54).<br />

(53) Regular Past Tense; played for all persons and number: He/They played.<br />

(54) Irregular Present Tense: He plays versus They play.<br />

The basic problem is that singular and plural noun inflection is identical to verb inflection:<br />

(55) a. play: either a singular noun or a plural present<br />

b. plays: either a plural noun or a singular present<br />

There are many nouns in English that also function as verbs. On the other hand, there are only a few<br />

past tense verbs that are also nouns, and they are all irregular, e.g., cut and hit. Further, locating the<br />

head of an English noun phrase is not a trivial matter. There are many opportunities for ambiguity.<br />

All these potential ambiguities are eliminated by the rule of subject verb agreement. Quite simply,<br />

without the inflectional differences between singular and plural count nouns and between singular<br />

and plural present verbs, speakers would be unable to locate the head of a noun phrase. Thus, the<br />

present tense of verbs cannot become regular<br />

We have already noted in a number of places that there is substantial psycho<strong>linguistic</strong> evidence<br />

supporting the analysis of language into chunks of constituent structure. As we have seen, RG syntax


educes all phrases and clauses to variations on one structural schema (6) repeated here for<br />

convenience:<br />

(56) [X n<br />

([+NML]) ([–NML]) X m ([+NML]) ([–NML]) ] where m # n<br />

(56) is, of course, a realization of (6). Thus, the structure of even gargantuan N3 (see Chapter Three,<br />

Page 179) reduces to five chunks of constituents, the lower end of human short term memory<br />

capacity.<br />

We also suggested above that the BR acts like a cuing device signaling the obligatory left boundary<br />

(beginning) of an N3. There has been considerable psycho<strong>linguistic</strong> interest in the role of cuing. In<br />

particular, studies focusing on the word that ) what we are calling a BR ) indicate that sentence<br />

comprehension is facilitated when the BR is overt.<br />

There are two broad categories that can serve as a BR in English syntax: the determiners (DET and<br />

CPL) and the inflections (POS and TNS). Of these, only TNS lacks a fixed position in both<br />

underlying and superficial syntax, as we have seen. And, of these, only TNS does not serve as a<br />

barrier. If, in fact, the BR is a cuing device, this seems appropriate. It is hardly likely that something<br />

that serves as a cue to upcoming <strong>structures</strong> would itself have an unreliable realization.<br />

To this, we may add various studies on anchors: experimental results indicate that subjects have<br />

better access to structure at the beginning (front anchoring) and end (end anchoring) of strings of<br />

elements. One might view the two occurrences of of in (52) as anchor points defining the obligatory<br />

bounds of an N3. It is well–known that front–anchoring is very important in linear ordering and that<br />

hierarchical structure is very important in the processing of long lists. These findings are in direct<br />

accord with the model of phrase structure proposed in this book and provide a link between syntactic<br />

description and the so–called special human faculty of language.<br />

5.2 OVERVIEW OF ANAPHORA<br />

Given the above description of English syntax, let us now turn to a more in–depth analysis of<br />

reference to see how our model can account for grammatical relationships in a revealing way.<br />

English has the following types of anaphors (items which refer to phrases in a sentence):<br />

(57) a. Personal Pronouns (he, him, his; she, her, hers; they, them, their, theirs, etc.)<br />

b. Reflexive Pronouns (himself, herself, themselves, etc.)<br />

c. Reciprocal Pronouns (each other, etc.)<br />

d. Floating Quantifiers (all, both, each, etc.)<br />

e. The Empty Category [e].<br />

The basic problem is to provide a description of English which will account for the items that<br />

anaphors can and cannot refer to. For example, consider the following:<br />

325


326<br />

(58) a. Ann said that Sue hurt her. (her = Ann not Sue)<br />

b. Ann said that Sue hurt herself. (herself = Sue not Ann)<br />

We need a description of English which will account the way native speakers understand the above<br />

sentences. Specifically, native speakers know that the personal pronoun her in Ann said that Sue hurt<br />

her cannot refer to Sue, whereas herself in Ann said that Sue hurt herself must refer to Sue. The use<br />

of pronouns like her and herself is very common in everyday speech, and native speakers have no<br />

trouble determining what they can and cannot refer to. Since the number of possible sentences in<br />

English and every other language is infinite, this means that speakers must know some principles for<br />

determining the possible referents for anaphors. Our objective is to specify those principles.<br />

Among the anaphors listed above is the empty category [e] which always has a sentence internal<br />

referent. For example, a sentence like This book, the city must burn is represented as follows (see<br />

(241) on Page 196):<br />

(59)<br />

The [e] in the above diagram refers to the phrase this book, a sentence internal element. This empty<br />

category must be distinguished from the empty category [u] (=[understood]) which is not an anaphor<br />

because it has no sentence internal referent. For example, a sentence like Let’s eat means Let us eat<br />

something. We represent the meaning as “Let us eat [u]” where the referent for “[u]” is understood<br />

and not interpreted in relation to some other noun phrase in the sentence in the way [e] is.<br />

As we have seen throughout this book, syntactic principles are based on phrase structure. In regard<br />

to anaphors, we will make use of the following structural relationships described in Chapter Three:


(60) a. C–command: a category α C–commands another category β, if the first branching<br />

category Z above α dominates β.<br />

b. Neighborhood: includes all items C–commanded by the same TNS characterizer.<br />

To see how these relationships work, consider the following diagram which will serve as the basis<br />

for our entire discussion of anaphors:<br />

(61)<br />

In (61), the following relationships obtain:<br />

(62) a. N3 w C–commands N3 x, N3 y, and N3 z.<br />

b. N3 x does not C–command N3 w, but does C–command both N3 y and N3 z.<br />

c. N3 y does not C–command N3 w or N3 x, but does C–command and N3 z.<br />

d. N3 z does not C–command either N3 w or N3 x or N3 y.<br />

(63) a. N3 w and N3 x are in the same neighborhood.<br />

b. N3 y and N3 z are in the same neighborhood.<br />

c. N3 w and N3 y are not in the same neighborhood.<br />

d. N3 w and N3 z are not in the same neighborhood.<br />

e. N3 x and N3 y are not in the same neighborhood.<br />

f. N3 x and N3 z are not in the same neighborhood.<br />

327


328<br />

As a start, we recognize the following principles:<br />

(64) PRINCIPLE 1: EVERY ANAPHOR MUST AGREE WITH ITS REFERENT IN<br />

PERSON, NUMBER AND GENDER.<br />

a. Bob likes himself. (himself agrees with Bob)<br />

b. *Bob likes myself. (no agreement in person)<br />

c. *Bob likes themselves. (no agreement in number)<br />

d. *Bob likes herself. (no agreement in gender)<br />

(65) PRINCIPLE 2: A PERSONAL PRONOUN CANNOT BE IN THE SAME<br />

NEIGHBORHOOD AS ITS REFERENT.<br />

a. [ V3 Bob told him many lies ] (him … Bob)<br />

b. [ V3 Bob told Sue [ V3 that Ann likes him ] ] (him = Bob)<br />

(66) PRINCIPLE 3: A REFLEXIVE PRONOUN MUST BE IN THE SAME<br />

NEIGHBORHOOD AS ITS REFERENT.<br />

a. [ V3 Bob told himself many lies ] (himself = Bob)<br />

b. *[ V3 Bob told Sue [ V3 that Ann likes himself ] ] (himself … Bob)<br />

c. [ V3 People tell themselves lies ] (themselves = people)<br />

(67) PRINCIPLE 4: A RECIPROCAL PRONOUN MUST BE IN THE SAME<br />

NEIGHBORHOOD AS ITS REFERENT.<br />

a. [ V3 People tell each other lies ] (each other = people)<br />

b. *[ V3 People have told me [ V3 that Sue told each other lies ] ]<br />

(68) PRINCIPLE 5: A FLOATING QUANTIFIER MUST BE IN THE SAME<br />

NEIGHBORHOOD AS ITS REFERENT.<br />

a. [ V3 Both Bob and Ted told lies ] (both = Bob and Ted)<br />

b. [ V3 Bob and Ted both told lies ] (both = Bob and Ted)<br />

c. [ V3 the two men said [ V3 that the two women both told lies ] ] (both = the two women<br />

not the two men)<br />

Some examples which illustrate the above principles are as follows (the subscripted N3 refer to the<br />

basic diagram in (61):


(69) a. Bob told himself that Ann liked him.<br />

N3 w PST tell N3 x that N3 y PST like N3 z<br />

Bob told himself that Ann liked him<br />

329<br />

The N3 above himself is N3 x, and the N3 above Bob is N3 w. N3 x and N3 w are in the<br />

same neighborhood. Therefore, himself must refer to Bob. The N3 above him is N3 z,<br />

and the N3 above Bob is N3 w. N3 z and N3 w are not in the same neighborhood.<br />

Therefore, him can refer to Bob.<br />

b. *Bob told Sue that Ann liked himself.<br />

N3 w PST tell N3 x that N3 y PST like N3 z<br />

*Bob told Sue that Ann liked himself<br />

The N3 above himself is N3 z, and the N3 above Bob is N3 w. N3 z and N3 w are not in<br />

the same neighborhood. Therefore, himself cannot refer to Bob. The sentence is<br />

ungrammatical because the only N3 that himself can refer to is the one dominating<br />

Ann; this intended reference involves a conflict in gender.<br />

c. The two men told Sue that the two women both liked them.<br />

N3 w PST tell N3 x that N3 y PST like N3 z<br />

the two men told Sue that the two women both liked them<br />

The word both must refer to the two women because it is in the same neighborhood<br />

as the two women. The personal pronoun them cannot refer to the two women because<br />

N3 y and N3 z are in the same neighborhood; them can only refer to the two men<br />

d. Bob told the two men that the two women liked each other.<br />

N3 w PST tell N3 x that N3 y PST like N3 z<br />

Bob told the two men that the two women liked each other<br />

The reciprocal pronoun each other must refer to the two women because N3 y and N3 z<br />

are in the same neighborhood; each other cannot refer to the two men<br />

Given the above basic principles, let us now look at the anaphors individually. Beginning with<br />

personal pronouns, we propose the following:


330<br />

(70) PRINCIPLE 6: A PERSONAL PRONOUN CAN REFER TO ANY N3 OUTSIDE ITS<br />

OWN NEIGHBORHOOD UNLESS IT BOTH PRECEDES AND C–COMMANDS<br />

THAT N3.<br />

We see this principle illustrated in the following examples:<br />

(71) a. He told Sue that Ted liked Ann. (he … Ted)<br />

N3 w PST tell N3 x that N3 y PST like N3 z<br />

he told Sue that Ted liked Ann<br />

N3 w precedes and C–commands N3 y; therefore, a personal pronoun in N3 w slot cannot<br />

refer to a noun in N3 y slot.<br />

b. Bob told Sue that he liked Ann. (he = Bob)<br />

N3 w PST tell N3 x that N3 y PST like N3 z<br />

Bob told Sue that he liked Ann<br />

N3 y neither precedes nor C–commands N3 w; the two phrases are in different<br />

neighborhoods; therefore, a personal pronoun in N3 y slot can refer to a noun in N3 w<br />

slot.<br />

c. Bob told Sue that Ted liked her. (her = Sue)<br />

N3 w PST tell N3 x that N3 y PST like N3 z<br />

Bob told Sue that Ted liked her<br />

N3 z neither precedes nor C–commands N3 x; the two phrases are in different<br />

neighborhoods; therefore, a personal pronoun in N3 z slot can refer to a noun in N3 x<br />

slot.<br />

d. Bob told her that Ted liked Sue. (her … Sue)<br />

N3 w PST tell N3 x that N3 y PST like N3 z<br />

Bob told her that Ted liked Sue<br />

N3 x precedes and C–commands N3 z; therefore, a personal pronoun in N3 x slot cannot<br />

refer to a noun in N3 z slot.


e. Bob told Ann that Sue liked her. (her = Ann; her =/ Sue)<br />

N3 w PST tell N3 x that N3 y PST like N3 z<br />

Bob tell Ann that Sue liked her<br />

331<br />

N3 z neither precedes nor C–commands N3 x, and the two phrases are in different<br />

neighborhoods, so a personal pronoun in the N3 z slot can refer to a noun in the N3 x<br />

slot, and her can refer to Ann. But, since Sue and her are in the same neighborhood,<br />

her cannot refer to Sue even though they agree in person, number, and gender.<br />

Turning to reflexive and reciprocal pronouns, we have the following principle and illustrative<br />

examples:<br />

(72) PRINCIPLE 7: A REFLEXIVE OR RECIPROCAL PRONOUN MUST BE<br />

R–COMMANDED BY ITS REFERENT IN ITS OWN NEIGHBORHOOD.<br />

R–command: a category α R–commands another category β if the first branching category<br />

Z above α dominates β and if β is an anaphor to the right of the head of Z.<br />

a. Bob told himself that Sue liked him. (himself = Bob)<br />

N3 w PST tell N3 x that N3 y PST like N3 z<br />

Bob told himself that Sue liked him<br />

The first branching category above N3 w is the top V3. The top V3 dominates N3 x. The<br />

head of the top V3 is the V0 tell. N3 x is to the right of tell. Thus, N3 w R–commands<br />

N3 x; further, both phrases are in the same neighborhood, so himself can refer to Bob.<br />

Since N3 z neither precedes nor C–commands N3 w, and both phrases are in different<br />

neighborhoods, a personal pronoun in the N3 z slot can refer to a noun in the N3 w slot.<br />

b. *Bob told Ann that Sue liked himself. (himself … Bob)<br />

N3 w PST tell N3 x that N3 y PST like N3 z<br />

Bob told Ann that Sue liked himself<br />

N3 w R–commands N3 z but the two phrases are not in the same neighborhood;<br />

therefore, a reflexive pronoun in N3 z slot cannot refer to a noun in N3 w slot.


332<br />

c. Bob told Ann that Sue liked herself. (herself = Sue; herself =/ Ann)<br />

N3 w PST tell N3 x that N3 y PST like N3 z<br />

Bob told Ann that Sue liked herself<br />

N3 y R–commands N3 z and both phrases are in the same neighborhood; therefore, a<br />

reflexive pronoun in N3 z slot can refer to a noun in N3 y slot, and herself can refer to<br />

Sue. But, even though N3 x R–commands N3 z, herself cannot refer to Ann because the<br />

two phrases are in different neighborhoods.<br />

d. *Herself told Ann that Sue liked Kay.<br />

*Kay told Ann that herself liked Sue.<br />

N3 w PST tell N3 x that N3 y PST like N3 z<br />

*herself told Ann that Sue liked Kay<br />

*Kay told Ann that herself liked Sue<br />

Neither sentence is possible because the reflexives do not have any R–commanding<br />

referent in their own neighborhoods.<br />

e. The two men told Sue that the two women liked each other.<br />

N3 w PST tell N3 x that N3 y PST like N3 z<br />

the two men told Sue that the two women liked each other<br />

The phrase each other must refer to the two women because it is in the same<br />

neighborhood as the two women.<br />

f. *The two men told Sue that Ann liked each other.<br />

N3 w PST tell N3 x that N3 y PST like N3 z<br />

the two men told Sue that Ann liked each other<br />

The phrase each other has no possible referent in its own neighborhood so the<br />

sentence is ungrammatical.<br />

.<br />

Turning to floating quantifiers, consider the following principle and illustrative diagram:<br />

(73) PRINCIPLE 8: A FLOATING QUANTIFIER MUST BE L–COMMANDED BY ITS<br />

REFERENT IN ITS OWN NEIGHBORHOOD.<br />

L–command: a category α L–commands another category β if the first branching category<br />

Z above α dominates β and if β is an anaphor to the left of the head of Z.


(74)<br />

The behavior of floating quantifiers is illustrated in the following examples:<br />

(75) a. The men will all tell the women to buy it.<br />

N3 w will FUT N3 x tell N3 y to buy N3 z<br />

the men will all tell the women to buy it<br />

333<br />

The first branching category above N3 w is the top V3. The top V3 dominates N3 x. The<br />

head of the top V3 is the V0 tell. N3 x is to the left of tell. Thus, N3 w L–commands<br />

N3 x, so all can refer to the men.<br />

b. The men will tell all the women to buy it.<br />

N3 w will FUT N3 x tell N3 y to buy N3 z<br />

the men will tell all the women to buy it<br />

The first branching category above N3 w is the top V3, and the head of the top V3 is<br />

the V0 tell. Since all occurs to the right of tell, it cannot refer back to the men. All<br />

is inside the N3 y, so all quantifiers women. We know that all is inside N3 y because<br />

it cannot be separated from the rest of the elements within N3 y:<br />

[1] All the women were told to buy it.<br />

[2] *The women were told all to buy it.


334<br />

To the principles above, we add the following two principles for formally determining the subject and<br />

object of a verb:<br />

(76) PRINCIPLE 9: SUBJECTS MUST C–COMMAND AND PRECEDE THEIR VERBS<br />

AND NOUNS.<br />

(77) PRINCIPLE 10: OBJECTS MUST C–COMMAND AND FOLLOW THEIR VERBS<br />

AND NOUNS.<br />

These principles are illustrated in the following diagram and examples:<br />

(78)<br />

a. The girls will all want to dress themselves. (no N3 y)<br />

The girls will all want to dress each other. (no N3 y)<br />

N3 w will FUT N3 x want N3 y to dress N3 z<br />

the girls will all want to dress themselves<br />

The first branching category above N3 w is the top V3.<br />

The top V3 dominates N3 x. The head of the top V3 is the V0 want. N3 x is to the left<br />

of want. Thus, N3 w L–commands N3 x, so all can refer to the girls.<br />

The top V3 dominates N3 z. The head of the top V3 is the V0 want. N3 z is to the right<br />

of want. Thus, N3 w R–commands N3 z, so themselves can refer to the girls.


Also: N3 w is the subject of both want and dress since it C–commands and precedes<br />

both verbs; N3 z is the object of dress since it C–commands and follows dress.<br />

335<br />

The verb want has no object because there is no N3 which C–commands and follows<br />

it. Because there is no object, there is nothing between want and to, so they contract<br />

to wanna.<br />

b. The girls will all want the boys to dress themselves.<br />

The girls will all want the boys to dress each other.<br />

N3 w will FUT N3 x want N3 y to dress N3 z<br />

the girls will all want the boys to dress themselves<br />

N3 w is the subject of want since it C–commands and precedes want; N3 y is the subject<br />

of dress since it C–commands and precedes dress. N3 y is the object of want since it<br />

C–commands and follows want; N3 z is the object of dress since it C–commands and<br />

follows dress. As above, the referent for all is the girls; however, the referent for<br />

themselves is the boys: the first branching category above N3 y is the V2, V2<br />

dominates N3 z, and N3 z contains an anaphor to the right of the head of V2.<br />

Lastly, we consider the following principle for the interpretation of [e], the empty anaphor:<br />

(79) PRINCIPLE 11: [e] CAN BE ANYWHERE EXCEPT IN A RESIDENTIAL<br />

DOMAIN. THUS, [e] CANNOT BE C–COMMANDED BY A PERMANENT<br />

RESIDENT OR L–COMMANDED BY A FREE RESIDENT.<br />

a. Binding residents and barriers.<br />

[1] Binding resident (BR) – the C3 dominated by the lowest recursion of X3 (DET<br />

or POS in N3; TNS or CPL in V3).<br />

[2] Barrier BR – a C3 whose position is constant (DET, POS, CPL) – acts as a<br />

cuing device to structure.<br />

b. Residents and residential domains.<br />

[1] Permanent residents – those that are obligatory (e.g. whether in I wonder<br />

whether he went). The domain of a permanent resident is all items it<br />

C–commands.<br />

[2] Free residents – those that are optional (e.g. that in He said (that) she knew me).<br />

The domain of a free resident is all items it L–commands.


336<br />

c. Empty category condition (ECC): An empty anaphor [X3 e] within some immediate<br />

neighborhood must be bound to a V3 Level phrase of the same type in the extended<br />

neighborhood.<br />

d. Wh–binding condition (WHBC): all phrases in the extended neighborhood must be<br />

bound to an [e]. Usually, but not always, such phrases contain a WH–word, e.g., who,<br />

which, at what time, etc.<br />

Principle 11 is illustrated in the following examples discussed previously:<br />

(80) [Bill’s vote against gun control]; common noun head vote:<br />

a. Mary criticized Bill’s vote against gun control.<br />

b. *What i did Mary criticize Bill’s vote against [N3 e ] I?<br />

c. *Mary criticized vote against gun control.<br />

d. Mary criticized the vote against gun control.<br />

(81) Indirect question:<br />

a. Mary wondered if Bill voted against gun control.<br />

b. *What i did Mary wonder if Bill voted against [N3 e ] I?<br />

c. *Mary wondered Bill voted against gun control.<br />

d. *Who i did Mary wonder if [N3 e ] I voted against gun control?<br />

e. *Who i did Mary wonder [N3 e ] I voted against gun control?<br />

(82) Indirect Statement with obligatory barrier BR:<br />

a. Mary chortled that Bill voted against gun control.<br />

b. *What i did Mary chortle that Bill voted against [N3 e ] I?<br />

c. *Mary chortled Bill voted against gun control.<br />

d. *Who i did Mary chortle that [N3 e ] I voted against gun control?<br />

e. *Who i did Mary chortle [N3 e ] I voted against gun control?<br />

(83) Indirect Statement with optional barrier BR:<br />

a. Mary thought that Bill voted against gun control.<br />

b. What i did Mary think that Bill voted against [N3 e ] I?<br />

c. Mary thought Bill voted against gun control.<br />

d. *Who i did Mary think that [N3 e ] I voted against gun control?<br />

e. Who i did Mary think [N3 e ] I voted against gun control?


EXERCISES FOR CHAPTER FIVE<br />

1. Account for the reference of all of the anaphors in the following examples:<br />

a. The little girls i want to dress themselves i.<br />

b. The little girls i say that they i dressed each other i.<br />

c. The little girls i [e] i that [e] i dressed themselves i are cute.<br />

d. The little girls i have all i dressed alike.<br />

e. The little girls i all i want to dress each other i.<br />

2. Determine the subjects of each use of swim in the following:<br />

a. John wants to swim in the ocean.<br />

b. John wants you to swim in the ocean.<br />

c. It is forbidden to swim in the ocean.<br />

d. It is forbidden for you to swim in the ocean.<br />

e. You are forbidden to swim in the ocean.<br />

3. Explain the ungrammaticality of the following:<br />

a. *What did John put the coats in the closet?<br />

b. *Which books does John think is good?<br />

c. *John wants her to drive himself to the party.<br />

d. *Each other like(s) the women.<br />

e. *The women who is next to himself like John.<br />

4. What principle(s) account for the following sets of data?<br />

a. That John hit something is clear.<br />

*What i is that John hit [e] i clear?<br />

What i is it clear that John hit [e] i?<br />

b. John denied the claim that his car hit the tree.<br />

*What i did John deny the claim that his car hit [e] i?<br />

What i did John deny that his car hit [e] i?<br />

337


338


SUPPLEMENT ONE: THE NATURE OF HUMAN LANGUAGE<br />

I. FUNDAMENTAL EMPIRICAL PROBLEMS FOR LINGUISTICS.<br />

A. The GRAMMATICAL CHARACTERIZATION PROBLEM: to account for the<br />

LINGUISTIC COMPETENCE of native speakers, that is, the unconscious knowledge<br />

they have of their native language.<br />

Crucial Question: What is the nature of the unconscious knowledge that all native speakers<br />

have?<br />

1. PHONOLOGY.<br />

a. (1) [t]: wait, write, vote, suit,<br />

(2) [d]: wade, ride, load, feed<br />

(3) [D]: waiter, writer, voter, suitor;<br />

wader, rider, loader, feeder<br />

b. (1) [ ]: ploud<br />

(2) [ ]: plouder<br />

(3) [ ]: plout<br />

2. MORPHOLOGY.<br />

a. (1) [t]: kicked, stopped, laughed<br />

(2) [d]: plunged, crammed, loved<br />

(3) [cd]: hunted, raided, relented<br />

b. (1) [ ]: goob<br />

(2) [ ]: nork<br />

(3) [ ]: frist<br />

3. SEMANTICS.<br />

a. (1) in: John ran in the street.<br />

(2) to: John ran to the street.<br />

(3) into: John ran into the street.<br />

(4) on: John ran on the street.<br />

(5) from: John ran from the street.<br />

(6) out of: John ran out of the street.<br />

b. (1) John fell...<br />

(2) John went...<br />

(3) John emerged...


340<br />

4. SYNTAX.<br />

Judgements: ?Questionable; *No good; **Garbage<br />

a. Sentence Adverbs: [ultimately]<br />

The student will read the book.<br />

(1) Ultimately the student will read the book.<br />

(2) ** The ultimately student will read the book.<br />

(3) The student ultimately will read the book.<br />

(4) The student will ultimately read the book.<br />

(5) * The student will read ultimately the book.<br />

(6) ** The student will read the ultimately book.<br />

(7) The student will read the book, ultimately.<br />

(8) ? The student will read the book ultimately.<br />

b. Manner Adverbs: [thoroughly]<br />

The student will read the book.<br />

(1) * Thoroughly the student will read the book.<br />

(2) ** The thoroughly student will read the book.<br />

(3) * The student thoroughly will read the book.<br />

(4) The student will thoroughly read the book.<br />

(5) * The student will read thoroughly the book.<br />

(6) ** The student will read the thoroughly book.<br />

(7) The student will read the book thoroughly.<br />

c. Miscellaneous Adverbs: [hardly]<br />

The student will read the book.<br />

(1) * Hardly the student will read the book.<br />

(2) ** The hardly student will read the book.<br />

(3) ? The student hardly will read the book.<br />

(4) The student will hardly read the book.<br />

(5) * The student will read hardly the book.<br />

(6) ** The student will read the hardly book.<br />

(7) * The student will read the book hardly.<br />

Crucial Fact: The knowledge that native speakers have of their native language is<br />

substantially uniform and largely unconscious.


B. The GRAMMATICAL REALIZATION PROBLEM: to account for the LINGUISTIC<br />

PERFORMANCE of native speakers, that is, the way in which they acquire and use their<br />

native language.<br />

Crucial Question: How do children acquire their native language?<br />

Crucial Question: How do native speakers produce and understand their native language?<br />

1. Comparison of native and second language acquisition.<br />

NATIVE LANGUAGE SECOND LANGUAGE<br />

Data fragmentary Data detailed and specific<br />

Data haphazard Data organized<br />

Data often defective Data fully grammatical<br />

Speech sole input Speech and writing inputs<br />

Unconscious Conscious and deliberate<br />

Novel sentences Patterns and drills<br />

Almost no instruction Formal instruction by experts<br />

2. Characteristics of native language acquisition.<br />

a. Rapid: Native language acquisition is completed in a remarkably short period for all<br />

normal children.<br />

b. Comprehension proceeds ahead of production (Kevin, age 14 months):<br />

(1) Production: approximately 10 words<br />

mommy, daddy, cookie, pops, balloon, coca-cola, truck; some; up, down, sit<br />

(2) Comprehension: approximately 100 words and phrases<br />

341<br />

helicopter, plane, Volkswagon; Burt, Bambi, Donald Duck; cheese, milk, hot<br />

dog; teeth, toes, belly button<br />

up in high chair; go play piano; give daddy some; don’t spill it; don’t throw it<br />

on the floor; let’s go get changed; brush your hair; etc.<br />

c. Not dependent on peripheral sensory mechanisms; language develops even in cases<br />

of blindness, deafness, and mutism.


342<br />

d. Not dependent on intelligence; language develops except in cases of severe<br />

intellectual disability.<br />

e. Creative.<br />

(1) Expressions with no adult models.<br />

Allgone itchy. (after being scratched)<br />

I do it Kevin's-self.<br />

Do I have a jack sized bed?<br />

open = sharpen or inflate<br />

dirty = unpeeled<br />

big water = lake<br />

(2) Overgeneralization.<br />

throwed for threw<br />

mans for men<br />

(3) Imitation without comprehension.<br />

f. Predictable.<br />

I do it twelve times. (it = go to sleep)<br />

I'm having a nervous breakdown.<br />

(1) Children make the same kinds of mistakes.<br />

He goed there.<br />

Him goed there.<br />

I goed the truck.<br />

(2) Children use the same strategy.<br />

g. Uniform: the stages of acquisition.<br />

(1) Primitive sentences.<br />

Noun truck<br />

Modifier + Noun pretty baby<br />

Noun + Noun daddy coat<br />

Verb + Noun see truck<br />

Verb + Noun + Noun see baby shoe


(2) The differentiation of word classes.<br />

Pivot (modifier) and Open (noun) classes.<br />

(a) Time One - around 24-27 months<br />

Pivot One Open<br />

that horsie<br />

a truck<br />

my car<br />

pretty baby<br />

more milk<br />

343<br />

Pivot One includes determiners (the, a), demonstratives (this, that),<br />

possessives (my), adjectives (pretty, big), and quantifiers (more).<br />

(b) Time Two - about three months later<br />

(Dem) + (Det) + Pivot Two + Open<br />

that a my truck<br />

that the big truck<br />

* that my a truck<br />

* my a that truck<br />

Pivot Two includes possessives, quantifiers, and adjectives.<br />

(c) Time Three - about three months later<br />

(Det) + (Adj) + Open<br />

a big cup<br />

*a my cup<br />

*a more cup<br />

Pivot Three consists only of possessives and quantifiers.


344<br />

(3) Relevance of word order.<br />

(a) Time Two<br />

* your that truck<br />

Yours is that truck.<br />

(b) Time Three<br />

* the more milk<br />

The more milk you drink the bigger you'll grow.<br />

(4) Relevance of imitation.<br />

(a) that doed<br />

(b) allgone shoe<br />

(c) big a truck<br />

(5) Relevance of memorization.<br />

The number of pivot/open combinations recorded in one study in successive<br />

months was: 14, 24, 54, 89, 350, 1400, 2500+<br />

h. Dependent on maturation.<br />

(1) Immediate memory limitations: the magic number 7 ± 2.<br />

(2) Cognitive limitations.<br />

Crucial Fact: Language acquisition proceeds in children unconsciously with almost the<br />

complete lack of instruction.<br />

3. Characteristics of the normal use of language.<br />

a. Rapidity of the speech process.<br />

(1) Slurring.<br />

(2) Voice Identification.<br />

b. Simultaneous integration of all components of grammar.<br />

c. One time exposure to sentences.<br />

Crucial Fact: Ordinary use of language does not require paper and pencil analysis


II. THEORIES OF LANGUAGE.<br />

A. Myths.<br />

1. Parental instruction.<br />

2. The need/pleasure hypothesis.<br />

B. Philosophical/Psychological Theories.<br />

1. EMPIRICISM (BEHAVIORISM, NURTURISM).<br />

John Locke (1632-1704); George Berkeley (1685-1753); David Hume (1711-1776)<br />

345<br />

The empiricist approach claims that human beings are born with very little in the way<br />

of instinctive behavior, that is, they are born with very little in the way of innate<br />

mechanisms for acquiring knowledge about language or anything else. Most of what<br />

they comes to know is a product of their experiences with the physical and social<br />

world. Human beings learn by imitating, associating, generalizing, and so on.<br />

2. RATIONALISM (MENTALISM, NATIVISM).<br />

Rene Descartes (1596-1650); Baruch Spinoza (1632-1677); Gottfried Wilhelm von<br />

Leibniz (1646-1716)<br />

The rationalist approach claims that human beings are born with a rich and detailed<br />

system of innate mechanisms which determine the way in which they acquire<br />

knowledge and interpret the data of everyday experience.<br />

C. Medical evidence.<br />

1. The relationship between sex and maturation.<br />

2. Interlocking of speech and motor milestones.<br />

3. Critical period for language acquisition -<br />

CEREBRAL LATERALIZATION<br />

a. Cerebral lateralization - the asymmetric specialization of the brain for language. In<br />

most humans, language is under the dominant control of the left hemisphere.


346<br />

b. Arguments for cerebral lateralization.<br />

(1) Electrical stimulation of the brain.<br />

(2) Anesthetization of the brain (injection of amobarbital into the carotid artery).<br />

(3) Hemispherectomy.<br />

(4) Aphasia studies.<br />

c. Arguments for the critical period.<br />

(1) Necessity for exposure before puberty.<br />

(2) Language in those who are intellectually disabled.<br />

(3) The effects of congenital deafness.<br />

(4) The effects of sudden acquired deafness.<br />

(5) The nature of second language acquisition.<br />

D. Levels of adequacy.<br />

1. OBSERVATIONAL ADEQUACY.<br />

2. DESCRIPTIVE ADEQUACY.<br />

3. EXPLANATORY ADEQUACY.


III. The theory of LINGUISTIC UNIVERSALS.<br />

Linguistic universals are potential characteristics of natural human languages. The complete<br />

list of possible universals is called CORE GRAMMAR. Linguistic universals derive from<br />

the capacities and limitations of the human language apparatus.<br />

A. SUBSTANTIVE UNIVERSALS: stipulations on the features which can occur in a<br />

natural language.<br />

1. Phonology (see pages 58-9 in LA for the interpretation of symbols in square brackets).<br />

a. [±NASAL].<br />

(1) [+NASAL]: [m], [n], [õ]<br />

Air leaves vocal apparatus through the nose.<br />

(2) [–NASAL]: [p], [b]. [t], [d], [k], [g]<br />

b. [±VOICED].<br />

Air leaves vocal apparatus through the mouth.<br />

(1) [+VOICED]: [b], [m], [d], [n], [g], [õ]<br />

Vocal cords are vibrating.<br />

(2) [–VOICED]: [p], [t], [k]<br />

c. *[±AURAL].<br />

Vocal cords are not vibrating.<br />

Air leaves vocal apparatus through the ears<br />

347


348<br />

2. Syntax.<br />

a. [±PREHEAD]; [±POSTHEAD].<br />

PREHEAD HEAD POSTHEAD<br />

all those new books about syntax available<br />

(1) [+PREHEAD, –POSTHEAD]: those and new<br />

(a) those new books<br />

(b) *books new those, *books those new<br />

(2) [–PREHEAD, +POSTHEAD]: about syntax<br />

(a) those books about syntax<br />

(b) *those about syntax books<br />

(3) [+PREHEAD, +POSTHEAD]: available<br />

(a) those available books<br />

(b) those books available<br />

b. *[±EVEN-NUMBERED-WORD].<br />

3. Semantics.<br />

a. [±DISJUNCTIVE].<br />

(1) [+DISJUNCTIVE]: emphasizing parting<br />

(2) [–DISJUNCTIVE]: not emphasizing parting<br />

b. [±CONJUNCTIVE].<br />

(1) [+CONJUNCTIVE]: emphasizing joining<br />

(2) [–CONJUNCTIVE]: not emphasizing joining<br />

c. DISJUNCTIVE CONJUNCTIVE<br />

(1) from + –<br />

(2) to – +<br />

(3) in – –<br />

(4) out of + +<br />

f. *[±INSCRIBED-CIRCLE > x].


B. FORMAL UNIVERSALS: stipulations on the organization of grammars and on the form<br />

and functioning of grammatical rules.<br />

1. The feature system of language must permit cross-categorial reference:<br />

a. [+NASAL]: m, n, õ<br />

b. [–NASAL]: p, b, t, d, k, g<br />

c. [+ANTERIOR]: m, p, b, n, t, d<br />

d. [–ANTERIOR]: õ, k, g<br />

e. [+CORONAL]: t, d, n<br />

f. [–CORONAL]: m, p, b, õ, k, g<br />

2. The feature system must allow precise identification.<br />

a. [+NASAL, +VOICED, +ANTERIOR, –CORONAL]: m<br />

b. [+NASAL, +VOICED, +ANTERIOR, +CORONAL]: n<br />

c. [+NASAL, +VOICED, –ANTERIOR, +CORONAL]: ñ<br />

d. [+NASAL, +VOICED, –ANTERIOR, –CORONAL]: õ<br />

3. The rules of language are structure dependent; they cannot involve counting.<br />

a. Sentence Adverbs: [ultimately]<br />

The student will read the book.<br />

(1) Ultimately the student will read the book.<br />

(2) The student ultimately will read the book.<br />

(3) The student will ultimately read the book.<br />

(4) The student will read the book, ultimately.<br />

b. Units.<br />

349


350<br />

c. Justification of units.<br />

(1) REFERENCE.<br />

(a) Who will read the book?<br />

(b) The student said that he will read the book.<br />

(c) What will the student do?<br />

(2) OMISSION.<br />

(a) The student said he would read the book if he had to________.<br />

(b) This student will read the book, and that one will ________ too.<br />

(3) PLACEMENT.<br />

(a) Ultimately the student will read the book.<br />

(b) The student ultimately will read the book.<br />

(c) The student will ultimately read the book.<br />

(d) The student will read the book, ultimately.<br />

d. Immediate memory limitations: chunking.<br />

(1) Telephone numbers.<br />

(2) Word lists versus structured sentences.<br />

(a) the little boy is playing in the backyard<br />

(b) fence girl under long the looking is a tall<br />

C. Relating grammatical characterization to grammatical realization; attaining explanatory<br />

adequacy.<br />

1. PHONOLOGY.<br />

a. (1) [m]: impossible, imbalance<br />

(2) [n]: intangible, indiscrete<br />

(3) [õ]: incorrigible, ingratitude<br />

b. (1) [m], [p], [b] are [+ANTERIOR, –CORONAL]<br />

(2) [n], [t], [d] are [+ANTERIOR, +CORONAL]<br />

(3) [õ], [k], [g] are [–ANTERIOR, –CORONAL]<br />

c. ASSIMILATE the nasal to the following consonant.


2. MORPHOLOGY.<br />

a. (1) [t]: kicked, stopped, laughed<br />

(2) [d]: plunged, crammed, loved<br />

(3) [cd]: hunted, raided, relented<br />

b. (1) [p], [t], [k], [f], [s], etc. are [–VOICED]<br />

(2) [b], [d], [g], [v], [z], etc. are [+VOICED]<br />

c. (1) use [t] after [–VOICED] sounds<br />

(2) use [d] after [+VOICED] sounds<br />

(3) use [cd] after [t] and [d]<br />

(a) *huntt/*huntd/hunted<br />

(b) hurted/goed/ketchuped<br />

3. SEMANTICS.<br />

a. (1) into: John ran into the street.<br />

(2) from: John ran from the street .<br />

b. (1) run, go: [±DISJUNCTIVE, ±CONJUNCTIVE]<br />

(2) emerge: [+DISJUNCTIVE, –CONJUNCTIVE]<br />

(3) enter: [–DISJUNCTIVE, +CONJUNCTIVE]<br />

4. SYNTAX.<br />

a. Data on Sentence Adverbs: [ultimately]<br />

b. Sentences contain three basic units.<br />

351


352<br />

c. Syntactic Representations.<br />

(1) Labelling of Units.<br />

(a) Traditional Grammar.<br />

SUBJECT = Person or thing performing the action of the verb.<br />

OBJECT = Person or thing affected by the action of the verb.<br />

(b) Modern Structural Grammar.<br />

S = SENTENCE DET = DETERMINER<br />

VP = VERB PHRASE MOD = MODAL<br />

NP = NOUN PHRASE NEG = NEGATIVE<br />

V = VERB N = NOUN<br />

(2) Structure versus Function.<br />

(a) The student will burn the money.<br />

(b) The student will earn the money.<br />

(c) The student will have the money.<br />

(3) Phrase Structure Rules ( Parentheses indicate optional elements).<br />

(a) S ÷ NP + AUX + VP<br />

(b) VP ÷ V + (NP)<br />

(c) NP ÷ (DET) + N<br />

(d) AUX ÷ MOD + (NEG)


D. The generality of <strong>linguistic</strong>s universals.<br />

Comparison of Language and Vision.<br />

1. Ambiguity in Isolation.<br />

a. Linguistic.<br />

353<br />

(1) This baby is too young to stand up by himself.<br />

(2) This baby is too young to be stood up.<br />

(3) This baby is too young either to stand up by himself or to be stood up by<br />

someone else.<br />

(4) This baby is too young to stand up.<br />

b. Visual. Necker Cube:<br />

c. General characteristics.<br />

(1) Interpretation is unconscious.<br />

(2) Interpretation is involuntary.


354<br />

2. Ambiguity in Context.<br />

a. Linguistic.<br />

(1) The farmer looked over the fence.<br />

(2) The farmer looked under the fence.<br />

(3) The farmer looked under the fence, and the farmer looked over the fence.<br />

b. Visual.<br />

c. General characteristics.<br />

(1) Interpretation is unconscious.<br />

(2) Interpretation is involuntary.<br />

(3) Interpretation is uniform.


3. Ellipsis.<br />

a. Linguistic.<br />

(1) John likes apples, Sue likes oranges, and Bill likes pears.<br />

(2) John likes apples, Sue, oranges, and Bill, pears.<br />

(3) *John, apples, Sue, oranges, and Bill likes pears.<br />

b. Visual.<br />

c. General characteristics.<br />

(1) Sophisticated pattern matching.<br />

(2) Closure (Gestalt psychology).<br />

355


356<br />

4. Contextual sensitivity.<br />

a. Linguistic.<br />

(1) The chickens are ready to eat.<br />

(2) The chickens are ready to lay eggs.<br />

(3) The chickens are ready to be plucked.<br />

(4) The chickens are ready to cook.<br />

b. Visual.<br />

c. General characteristics.<br />

(1) Interpretation is unconscious.<br />

(2) Contextual information automatically processed.


5. Complexity.<br />

a. Linguistic.<br />

(1) People who believe that the world is flat are nuts.<br />

(2) Bill said that to him that the world is flat is idiotic.<br />

(3) Bill said that that the world is flat is ridiculous.<br />

(4) That that the world is flat is idiotic is surprising to Bill.<br />

(5) Who is that that the world is flat is idiotic surprising to?<br />

(6) Who is it surprising to that it is idiotic that the world is flat?<br />

b. Visual<br />

357


358<br />

c. General characteristics.<br />

(1) GRAMMATICAL/UNGRAMMATICAL<br />

(a) Grammatical:<br />

She is mixing up her children.<br />

She is mixing her children up.<br />

(b) Ungrammatical:<br />

*She her children mixing up is.<br />

(2) ACCEPTABLE/UNACCEPTABLE<br />

(a) Acceptable:<br />

He passed up the chance to look up the name.<br />

(b) Unacceptable:<br />

*He passed the chance to look the name up up.<br />

(3) Important points:<br />

(a) Acceptability is a technical <strong>linguistic</strong> concept that has nothing to do with<br />

appropriateness.<br />

(b) Acceptability is only an issue when the question of brain capacities<br />

arises.<br />

(c) None of the following sentences involve acceptability:<br />

[1] John mixed up the recipe.<br />

[2] John screwed up the recipe.<br />

[3] John fucked up the recipe.<br />

(4) Examples:<br />

(a) Grammatical but Unacceptable: They attributed the painting [that was<br />

stolen from the Louvre last night despite the intensive security throughout<br />

the building] to Picasso.<br />

(b) Ungrammatical but Acceptable: They attributed to Picasso the painting<br />

[that was stolen from the Louvre last night despite the intensive security<br />

throughout the building].<br />

(c) Ungrammatical and Unacceptable: They attributed to Picasso [a<br />

Spanish-born French painter, sculptor, graphic artist and ceramist,<br />

considered by many to be the greatest artist of the 20th century] the<br />

painting [that was stolen from the Louvre last night despite the intensive<br />

security throughout the building].


6. Incongruity.<br />

a. Linguistic.<br />

(1) Bill convinced Mary that the world is round, but she didn't believe him.<br />

359<br />

(2) Now that the surgeon has removed all of his vital organs, John feels better than<br />

he ever has.<br />

b. Visual.<br />

c. General characteristics.<br />

(1) Automatic pattern matching.<br />

(2) Integration of <strong>linguistic</strong> and pragmatic facts.


360<br />

7. Rules.<br />

a. Linguistic.<br />

(1) John saw the man walking toward the railroad station? (3 ways ambiguous)<br />

(2) What did John see the man walking toward? (unambiguous)<br />

b. Visual: Kopfermann Cubes.<br />

c. General characteristics.<br />

(1) The interpretations are rule governed.<br />

(2) The initial interpretation is automatic, unconscious and involuntary.


E. Linguistic universals and human mental abilities.<br />

1. Memory Limitations<br />

a. John called up a girl<br />

b. John called a girl up.<br />

c. John called up a girl he used to go with.<br />

d. ?John called a girl he used to go with up.<br />

e. John called up a girl he used to go with back in Idaho before he left for college.<br />

f. *John called a girl he used to go with back in Idaho before he left for college up.<br />

2. Complexity Limitations.<br />

361<br />

a. MULTIPLE BRANCHING CONSTRUCTION: one with no internal structure,<br />

that is, no internal dependency relationships. Multiple branching constructions simply<br />

involve a string of concatenated elements.<br />

(1) I saw John, Bill, Mary, Sue,...<br />

(2) [John] + [Bill] + [Mary] + [Sue] + ...<br />

b. RIGHT BRANCHING CONSTRUCTION: one whose internal dependency<br />

relationships branch to the right, that is, the most deeply embedded constituent is the<br />

one furthest to the right.<br />

(1) This is the cat that saw the rat that ate the cheese...<br />

(2) [this is [the cat that caught [the rat that ate the cheese] ] ]<br />

c. LEFT BRANCHING CONSTRUCTION: one whose internal dependency<br />

relationships branch to the left, that is, the most deeply embedded constituent is the<br />

one furthest to the left.<br />

(1) Mary's brother's wife's dog is named Spot.<br />

(2) [ [ [ [Mary’s] brother’s] wife’s] dog]


362<br />

d. NESTED CONSTRUCTION: phrase A and phrase B form a nested construction<br />

if phrase B falls totally within phrase A , and if there is some nonnull element to to<br />

the left and to the right of phrase B within A.<br />

(1) John called Sue up yesterday.<br />

(2) John [called [Sue] up] yesterday.<br />

e. CENTER (SELF)-EMBEDDED CONSTRUCTION: phrase B is self-embedded<br />

in A if B is nested in A and, furthermore, B is a phrase of the same type as A.<br />

(1) (a) Something upset Ann.<br />

(b) That something annoyed Sue upset Ann.<br />

(c) That that something pleased John annoyed Sue upset Ann<br />

(2) (a) The man killed the cat.<br />

(b) The man that the woman loves killed the cat.<br />

(c) The man that the woman that the boy annoyed loves killed the cat.<br />

(3) (a) When the cat died, the boy cried.<br />

(b) Because when the cat died the boy cried, the girl left.<br />

(c) Even though because when the cat died a boy cried the girl left, the<br />

doctor was not concerned.<br />

(4) (a) When the man saw the woman who grabbed the dog because the boy said<br />

that it bit the girl who was sick, he laughed.<br />

(b) Als der Mann die Frau die den Hund weil der Knabe dass er das Mädchen<br />

das krank war biss sagte packte sah, lachte er.<br />

(c) When the man the woman who the dog because the boy that it the girl<br />

that sick was bit said grabbed saw, laughed he.<br />

(5) It upset Ann that it annoyed Sue that something pleased John. (=1c)<br />

(6) The cat was killed by the man who is loved by the woman who was annoyed by<br />

the boy. (=2c)<br />

(7) The doctor was not concerned even though the girl left because a boy cried<br />

when the cat died. (=3c)<br />

(8) Als der Mann die Frau sah, die den Hund packte, weil der Knabe sagte, dass er<br />

das Mädchen das krank war biss, lachte er. (=4b)


IV. TYPES OF LANGUAGES.<br />

A. Classification.<br />

1. Natural Languages.<br />

a. Animal Languages.<br />

b. Human Languages.<br />

(1) Vocal/auditory.<br />

(2) American Sign Language<br />

2. Artificial Languages.<br />

a. Non-natural Human Languages.<br />

b. Computer Languages.<br />

(1) Programming languages: BASIC, LISP, Pascal.<br />

(2) Word processors: Applewriter, Word Perfect.<br />

B. Characteristics.<br />

1. Animal Languages.<br />

a. Type One.<br />

363<br />

(1) Description: the system consists of a fixed number of signals each one of which<br />

is associated with a specific range of eliciting conditions or internal states.<br />

(2) Example: Howling Monkeys<br />

(a) voluminous roar ‘defense of group territory’<br />

(b) rapid grunting (male) ‘response to a disturbance’<br />

(c) terrible bark (female) ‘response to a disturbance’<br />

(d) purr ‘mother/young relationship’<br />

(e) series of cries (usually three) ‘a falling infant’<br />

(3) Example: Honey Bees<br />

(a) round dance: food is less than 20 feet away<br />

(b) sickle dance: food is from 20 to 60 feet away<br />

(c) tail-wagging dance: food is more than 60 feet away.


364<br />

b. Type Two.<br />

(1) Description: the system consists of a fixed number of <strong>linguistic</strong> dimensions<br />

each one of which is associated with a non<strong>linguistic</strong> dimension such that<br />

selection of a point along one indicates a corresponding point along the other.<br />

(2) Example: Honey Bees - the tail-wagging dance.<br />

2. Human Language.<br />

The direction of the food source is also conveyed by this dance, the sun being<br />

used as a reference point. A tail-wagging dance proceeding on the vertical<br />

honeycomb upward means that the food is in the direction of the sun; if<br />

downward, it means the food is in the direction opposite the sun; if 60 degrees<br />

left of straight up, it means the food is 60 degrees to the left of the sun; etc.<br />

The system consists of an INFINITE NUMBER OF SIGNALS each one of which<br />

involves the pairing of a superficial sound structure with an underlying semantic<br />

structure. There is NO ONE-TO-ONE CORRESPONDENCE BETWEEN SOUND<br />

AND MEANING.<br />

a. AMBIGUITY (one sound, more than one meaning).<br />

(1) Lexical level.<br />

(a) After making the right turn at the corner,...<br />

(b) After making the left turn at the corner,...<br />

(2) Phrasal level.<br />

(a) He looked over the fence.<br />

(b) He hit the lady with the hat.<br />

(3) Sentential level.<br />

(a) Visiting relatives can be boring.<br />

(b) The chickens are ready to eat.<br />

(4) Examples from the speech of children.<br />

(a) Milk.<br />

(b) Mommy sock.


. PARAPHRASE (one meaning, more then one sound).<br />

(1) Adult speech.<br />

(a) The nurse gave the shots to the students.<br />

(b) The nurse gave the students the shots.<br />

(c) The shots were given to the students by the nurse.<br />

(d) The students were given the shots by the nurse.<br />

(2) Examples from the speech of children.<br />

(a) Get it baby up.<br />

(b) Get it me up.<br />

(c) Get baby up.<br />

c. Disparity in meaning.<br />

(1) (a) John is eager to please.<br />

(b) John is easy to please.<br />

(2) (a) Bill appeared to John to behave himself.<br />

(b) Bill appealed to John to behave himself.<br />

d. Cultural constraints.<br />

(1) I'm very sorry to hear that your wife<br />

(a) passed away.<br />

(b) died.<br />

(c) kicked the bucket.<br />

(d) went to heaven.<br />

(2) Would you mind<br />

(a) leaving a specimen in that container.<br />

(b) leaving a urine specimen in that container.<br />

(c) going peepee in that paper cup.<br />

(d) taking a leak.<br />

3. Computer languages: word processors.<br />

a. Based on mathematical operations like counting, e.g., go to the fifth page of a<br />

document.<br />

b. Memories are flawless and expandable.<br />

c. Equipped with special operations: SEARCH, COPY, CUT, PASTE, etc.<br />

365


366<br />

d. Controlled by magic words that are ad hoc.<br />

e. Anything can be a unit for the purposes of movement, insertion, deletion, or<br />

substitution of text.<br />

(1) INPUT: The student will read the book.<br />

(2) OUTPUT:<br />

(a) Movement: will between read and the<br />

The student read Will the book.<br />

(b) Insertion: s' teacher after student<br />

The students' teacher will read the book.<br />

(c) Deletion: h, stu, and ent<br />

Ted will read the book.<br />

(d) Substitution: sha for wi<br />

The student shall read the book.<br />

f. Based on the computer's capacities.<br />

V. THE EVOLUTION OF HUMAN LANGUAGE.<br />

A. Theories of the evolution of human language.<br />

1. CONTINUITY THEORY I: a straight line evolution of language with only<br />

QUANTITATIVE differences.<br />

a. Links <strong>linguistic</strong> competence with intelligence.<br />

b. Can't measure intelligence across species.<br />

2. CONTINUITY THEORY II: a straight line evolution of language with<br />

QUALITATIVE differences, with a step-wise accumulation of skills.<br />

a. Ignores PHYLOGENETIC relationships.<br />

b. Subhuman primates should have the closest languages to human languages.<br />

3. DISCONTINUITY THEORY: human language is species specific to man, like bipedal<br />

gait. It is the result of anatomical and neurological specializations.<br />

a. INNATENESS HYPOTHESIS.<br />

b. UNIVERSAL (CORE )GRAMMAR.


B. Innovations in the STRUCTURE of the language apparatus.<br />

1. Neurological.<br />

1,2,3: Primary sensory cortex<br />

7: Secondary sensory area<br />

4,6: Primary motor cortex<br />

9: Motor area for the hand (Exner's center)<br />

44: Motor area for the face (Broca's area)<br />

40: Supramarginal gyrus<br />

39: Angular gyrus<br />

17: Primary visual area<br />

18,19: Secondary visual area<br />

41,42: Primary auditory area<br />

22: Secondary auditory area (Wernieke's area)<br />

367


368<br />

a. Development of the supramarginal and angular gyri.<br />

b. LIMBIC and NON-LIMBIC stimuli.<br />

(1) Limbic stimuli are concerned with survival: eating, drinking, sleeping,<br />

reproduction, self-preservation, etc.<br />

(2) Non-limbic stimuli are not concerned with survival: seeing, hearing,<br />

speaking, etc.<br />

c. Asymmetry of the temporal lobes.<br />

d. Increase in the relative size of the primary auditory area.<br />

2. Vocal<br />

a. Lowering of the larynx.<br />

(1) Optimally efficient system (the tilde "˜" above the vowel means that the<br />

vowel is nasal):<br />

m õ b g ˜e õ e o<br />

CONSONANT + + + + – – – –<br />

NASAL + + – – + + – –<br />

ANTERIOR + – + – + – + –<br />

(2) Human languages about 50% efficient.<br />

(3) Neanderthal Man couldn’t produce: [i], [u], [a], [k], [g], [õ]<br />

b. Development of the alveolar ridge.<br />

c. Increased prominence in the muscles of the lips and complexity of the muscles<br />

associated with articulation.<br />

3. Auditory: slight anatomical changes, reasons unknown


C. Innovations in the FUNCTIONING of the language apparatus.<br />

1. Neurological.<br />

a. Cerebral lateralization.<br />

b. Localization of language to specific areas.<br />

c. Cross-modal associations.<br />

2. Vocal.<br />

a. The use of the tongue and pharyngeal wall to modify phonations.<br />

b. The use of the nasal and oral separation.<br />

3. Auditory.<br />

a. Ear most sensitive to sounds within frequency range of 250-4000 cycles per<br />

second--range of normal speech.<br />

b. 50-65 decibel range for normal conversation.<br />

VI. LIMITATIONS ON THE FORM OF NATURAL LANGUAGE.<br />

A. Ambiguity and Paraphrase.<br />

B. Sentence complexity and memory.<br />

C. Rules not mathematically based. Rules based on structure.<br />

D. Inability of the brain to utilize an analytical procedure while it is already in the process<br />

of performing that procedure.<br />

1. That that John surprised Sue worried Fred.<br />

2. The man that the woman that the dog bit loves left.<br />

E. Empty Categories ([e]) and Contraction.<br />

1. a. They have won the game.<br />

b. They’ve won the game.<br />

2. a. They could have won the game.<br />

b. Could i they [e] i have won the game?<br />

c. *Could they’ve won the game?<br />

369


370


SUPPLEMENT TWO: GRAMMAR REVIEW<br />

SYNTACTIC CATEGORIES (THE PARTS OF SPEECH)<br />

NOUN: Nouns are identifiable on the basis of several criteria. First, they can occur after definite<br />

articles, e.g., the book, after indefinite articles, e.g., a book. Second, noun are inflected to show<br />

number distinctions, e.g., one book versus two books, and to indicate possession, e.g., the book’s<br />

cover. Third, nouns fulfill a number of specific functions in sentences. For instance, they can be<br />

used as the subject of a verb, e.g., The book ends sadly, as the object of a verb, e.g., John likes that<br />

book, and as the object of a preposition, e.g., There are no pictures in the book. Nouns are variously<br />

subcategorized as follows:<br />

PROPER NOUNS are those which refer to specific individuals, places, or things, e.g., John,<br />

Rome, and English; COMMON NOUNS are non–specific in reference, e.g., man, city, and<br />

language.<br />

CONCRETE NOUNS are those which refer to tangible objects, e.g., cow, fence, and painting;<br />

ABSTRACT NOUNS name intangible things, e.g., admiration, gravity, and painting. Notice<br />

that some nouns have both concrete and abstract references.<br />

COUNT NOUNS are those which are numerable, e.g., tree, leg, and linguist; MASS NOUNS<br />

are not numerable, e.g., butter, water, and furniture. Notice that one does not ordinarily say<br />

butters, waters, and furnitures (but, the waters of the Nile).<br />

. COLLECTIVE NOUNS are those which refer to groups of items, e.g., herd, crowd, and mob.<br />

PRONOUN: A pronoun is a word which is used in place of a noun phrase, e.g., he, she, who, myself,<br />

etc. The various subclasses of pronouns are as follows:<br />

PERSONAL PRONOUNS refer to the speaker, the hearer, or the person or thing spoken<br />

about, e.g., I, me, you, and him.<br />

REFLEXIVE PRONOUNS are object pronouns which refer back to the subject of the clause<br />

in which they occur, e.g., myself, itself, and themselves.<br />

INTENSIVE PRONOUNS emphasize a preceding noun or pronoun, e.g. myself, itself, and<br />

themselves. The form of reflexive and intensive pronouns is the same. In I myself saw myself<br />

in the mirror, the first myself is intensive, the second is reflexive.<br />

INDEFINITE PRONOUNS refer to indefinite persons and things, e.g., someone, anybody,<br />

and everything.<br />

POSSESSIVE PRONOUNS are those which take the place of possessive nouns, e.g., her, his,<br />

and its.


372<br />

DEMONSTRATIVE PRONOUNS are used to designate particular persons or things, e.g.,<br />

this, that, and these.<br />

RELATIVE PRONOUNS are those which introduce relative clauses, e.g., who, whom, and<br />

which.<br />

INTERROGATIVE PRONOUNS are used in place of nouns in questions, e.g., who, which<br />

and what.<br />

RECIPROCAL PRONOUNS express mutual actions or relationships, e.g., each other and<br />

one another.<br />

VERB: A verb is a word which serves to express an action, an occurrence, or a state of being, e.g.,<br />

shot in The inspector shot the bandit, blow up in The school blew up, be in That girl is clever. Verbs<br />

are identifiable by a variety of inflectional distinctions, including tense, person, number, and voice.<br />

The subclasses of verbs are as follows:<br />

TRANSITIVE VERBS are those which take objects, e.g., break in John broke the vase, and<br />

destroy in John destroyed the vase.<br />

INTRANSITIVE VERBS are those which do not take objects, e.g., break in The vase broke,<br />

and disappear in The vase disappeared.<br />

COPULATIVE VERBS are those which link the subject with a nominal or adjectival<br />

complement, e.g., appear in John appears healthy, and be in John was the king for two years.<br />

ADJECTIVE: An adjective is a word which qualifies, limits, or otherwise modifies the meaning of<br />

a noun, e.g. pretty, little, and white. In English, adjectives occur in two principal positions, either<br />

before the nouns they modify, e.g., the rebellious student, or after verbs like be, e.g., the student is<br />

rebellious. The two positions are called, respectively, the ATTRIBUTIVE POSITION and the<br />

PREDICATE POSITION. Adjectives are inflected to show one of three degrees of comparison:<br />

the POSITIVE DEGREE, the COMPARATIVE DEGREE, and the SUPERLATIVE DEGREE.<br />

The comparative degree is used when two items are being compared; the superlative is used when<br />

three or more items are being compared. For example: John is a good boy (positive degree); John<br />

is a better boy than Bill (comparative degree); John is the best boy in the class (superlative degree).<br />

ADVERB: An adverb is a word which modifies a verb or an adjective, e.g., quickly in John ran<br />

quickly, and unbelievably in John is unbelievably clever. Like adjectives, adverbs are compared in<br />

the positive, comparative, and superlative degree, e.g., Mary cleans her house thoroughly all the time<br />

(positive), Mary cleans her house more thoroughly on weekdays than on weekends (comparative),<br />

and Mary cleans her house (the) most thoroughly before her mother–in–law comes to visit<br />

(superlative).


CONJUNCTION: A conjunction is a word which connects one grammatical category or<br />

grammatical construction with another. There are two basic types of conjunctions:<br />

COORDINATING and SUBORDINATING. A coordinating conjunction connects elements in<br />

such a way as to indicate approximately equal order or rank amongst the elements, e.g., John and<br />

Harry, on the table or on the desk, and Sit down and eat your spinach. A subordinating conjunction<br />

on the other hand, connects elements in such a way as to place one in a lower order or rank with<br />

respect to the other, e.g., Sit down, while you are eating your spinach.<br />

PREPOSITION: A preposition is a word which introduces a phrase ending in a noun, or the<br />

equivalent of a noun, and which typically serves as an adverbial or adjectival modifier, e.g., John ran<br />

into the yard, and John is in the yard.<br />

SYNTACTIC CONSTRUCTIONS<br />

SENTENCE: A sentence is a structured expression consisting minimally of two main constituents,<br />

a SUBJECT, which specifies the topic of the expression, and a PREDICATE, which specifies what<br />

is asserted of the topic. There are four principal types of sentences: DECLARATIVE, those which<br />

make statements, e.g., John wrote Helen a letter; INTERROGATIVE, those which ask questions,<br />

e.g., Did John write Helen a letter; IMPERATIVE, those which give a command or make a request,<br />

e.g., Please, write Helen a letter; and EXCLAMATORY, those which express strong or sudden<br />

feeling, e.g., What a beautiful letter John wrote Helen!<br />

CLAUSE: Like sentences, clauses are also expressions which contain a subject and a predicate. All<br />

clauses must contain a tensed verb. Clauses are of two types: INDEPENDENT and DEPENDENT<br />

(or SUBORDINATE). An independent clause is one which can stand alone; hence, a sentence is an<br />

independent clause. A dependent clause is one which occurs in conjunction with an independent<br />

clause. When a sentence consists of only one independent clause, it is called a SIMPLE sentence;<br />

when it consists of two or more independent clauses and no dependent clauses, it is called a<br />

COMPOUND sentence; and when it contains one or more dependent clauses, it is called a<br />

COMPLEX sentence.<br />

PHRASE: A phrase is any group of words which serves as a unit within a clause. Phrases are<br />

usually named for their most distinctive element, called the HEAD, e.g., noun phrase, verb phrase,<br />

prepositional phrase, and so on.<br />

373


374<br />

MORPHOLOGY<br />

Most grammars divide the study of sentence structure into two areas, MORPHOLOGY, which deals<br />

with the internal structure of words, and SYNTAX, which deals with the way words are combined<br />

to form sentences. In morphology, the basic units under investigation are the morphemes of a<br />

language. By definition, a MORPHEME is a minimal unit of meaning, that is, a meaningful<br />

sequence of sounds which is not divisible into smaller meaningful units, e.g., ball. It is important not<br />

to equate morphemes with either words or syllables; in both theory and practice, there is no necessary<br />

coincidence between a morpheme and either of these units. For example, the English noun hands is<br />

one word consisting of one syllable, but having two morphemes: hand, which defines a specific body<br />

part, and s which indicates plural. Conversely, finger has two syllables but is only one morpheme.<br />

One cannot divide the word finger into smaller meaningful units: the sequences fing, inger, ger, etc.<br />

are all without content. Even the sequence fin, which does have meaning in English, is not part of<br />

the morphological structure of finger, because its meaning is unrelated to the meaning of the whole<br />

word.<br />

Morphemes are variously classified by linguists as BOUND or FREE and as ROOTS or AFFIXES.<br />

A BOUND MORPHEME is one which cannot occur as an independent word, e.g., the un– meaning<br />

‘not’ in untrustworthy, unappreciative, unnecessary, etc. A FREE MORPHEME is one which can<br />

stand alone, e.g., the morpheme trust. In English, bound morphemes constitute a relatively small<br />

class of items, while the number of free morphemes is very large. In other languages, the situation<br />

is often quite different. For example, Classical Greek has very few free morphemes, but a great<br />

number of bound ones. In Vietnamese, almost all of the morphemes are classified as free.<br />

A ROOT is a morpheme which constitutes the core element of a word or group of words of closely<br />

related meaning. For example, the morpheme trust serves as the root in all of the following words:<br />

trusted, untrustworthy, mistrustful, entrust, and so on. An AFFIX is a bound morpheme added to<br />

the beginning of a word (in which case it is called a PREFIX) or to the end of a word (in which case<br />

it is called a SUFFIX). Some common affixes in English are un–, mis–, con–, ex–, –ly, –ing, –ness,<br />

and –er. That part of a word to which affixes are added is called a STEM. In English, the stem and<br />

the root of a word are usually the same string; in other languages, they differ.<br />

Affixes that are added to roots to indicate grammatical relationships are known as INFLECTIONAL<br />

ENDINGS, and the process of combining these endings with roots is called INFLECTION. The<br />

–s used to indicate the plural of English nouns is an example of an inflectional ending, as is the –ed<br />

used to indicate past tense. Comparatively speaking, English is very poor in inflectional endings.<br />

Other languages have highly developed inflectional systems. For example, in Latin, Russian, and<br />

Finnish, the form of a noun changes depending on whether it is used as the subject of a verb or as the<br />

object. In English, nouns are not inflected for this particular contrast, although some pronouns are,<br />

e.g., I/me, she/her, he/him, we/us, they/them, who/whom. When applied to SUBSTANTIVES (nouns,<br />

pronouns, and adjectives) inflection is referred to as DECLENSION; when applied to verbs, it is<br />

called CONJUGATION.


SOME INFLECTIONAL CATEGORIES<br />

PERSON: the inflectional category in pronouns and verbs that refers to the three–way distinction<br />

between the speaker (FIRST PERSON), e.g., I am tall, the hearer (SECOND PERSON), e.g., You<br />

are tall, and someone or something else (THIRD PERSON), e.g., He (she, it) is tall.<br />

NUMBER: an inflectional category in substantives and verbs that refers to the distinction between<br />

singular, e.g., the house IS big, and plural, e.g., the houses ARE big.<br />

TENSE: an inflectional category in verbs which indicates distinctions in the TIME (PRESENT,<br />

PAST, FUTURE) and the ASPECT (PROGRESSIVE, PERFECTIVE) of an action or state. For<br />

example, the verb phrase is looking is in the present progressive tense, that is, it indicates an action<br />

which is going on in the present; the verb phrase has looked is in the present perfective tense, that<br />

is, it indicates an action that was completed in the past. Strictly speaking, tense is only partially an<br />

inflectional category in English, since it is signaled both by independent words, e.g., forms of the<br />

verbs be and have and by endings, e.g., –ing and –ed.<br />

VOICE: an inflectional category in verbs that refers to the distinction between ACTIVE and<br />

PASSIVE. An active verb is one whose subject is viewed as performing the action it defines, e.g.,<br />

John killed the tigers; a passive verb is one whose subject is viewed as undergoing the action it<br />

defines, e.g., the tigers were killed by John.<br />

MODE/MOOD: an inflectional category in verbs that refers to the distinction between<br />

INDICATIVE, CONDITIONAL, and IMPERATIVE. The indicative mode expresses ordinary<br />

statements (he stopped); the conditional mode expresses conditions (he would stop); the imperative<br />

mode expresses commands (stop!).<br />

CASE: an inflectional category which indicates the relationship of substantives to other words in a<br />

sentence. In English, the opposition he/him/his is a case opposition: he is used to indicate the subject<br />

(NOMINATIVE CASE), him to indicate the object (OBJECTIVE or ACCUSATIVE CASE), and<br />

his to indicate the possessor (POSSESSIVE or GENITIVE).<br />

GENDER: an inflectional category in substantives that refers to the tripartite distinction between<br />

MASCULINE, FEMININE, and NEUTER. In English, only the third person singular pronouns<br />

show gender distinctions, e.g., he, she, and it; moreover, the distinction is based on sex. In other<br />

languages, e.g., German, gender is a grammatical category of substantives and bears no relationship<br />

to sex.<br />

375


376<br />

SUPPLEMENT THREE (PART I): TYPOLOGICAL CLASSIFICATION<br />

ANALYTIC LANGUAGES (ISOLATING LANGUAGES): words consist of single<br />

morphemes; most words consist only of a root. Mandarin Chinese, Vietnamese, Cantonese,<br />

Cambodian. Examples in Mandarin adapted from Norman J., Chinese, Cambridge, 1988:<br />

1. Ta chī fàn le.<br />

he eat food past<br />

‘He ate the food.’<br />

2. Ta chī le fàn.<br />

he eat past food<br />

‘He ate the food.’<br />

3. Júzi w4 chī le.<br />

orange I eat past<br />

‘I ate the orange.’<br />

AGGLUTINATING LANGUAGES: words consist of a stem and one or more clearly<br />

identifiable affixes. Finnish, Hungarian, Estonian, Swahili, Turkish. Examples in Estonian<br />

adapted from Oinas, F., Basic Course in Estonian, Indiana University, 1966:<br />

1. Ta on kohvikus.<br />

he is coffee–house–in<br />

‘He is in the coffee house.’<br />

2. Lähme kohvikusse.<br />

go–we coffee–house–into<br />

‘Let us go into the coffee house.’<br />

3. Ma tulen uuest kohvikust.<br />

I come new–from coffee–house–from<br />

‘I am coming out of the new coffee house.’<br />

4. Cases:<br />

nominative kohvik the coffee house<br />

genitive kohviku of the coffee house<br />

partitive kohvikut the coffee house<br />

illative kohvikusse into the coffee house<br />

inessive kohvikus in the coffee house<br />

elative kohvikust out of the coffee house<br />

allative kohvikule to the coffee house<br />

adessive kohvikul by the coffee house<br />

ablative kohvikult from the coffee house<br />

translative kohvikuks for the coffee house<br />

essive kohvikuna as the coffee house<br />

terminative kohvikuni up to the coffee house<br />

comitative kohvikuga with the coffee house<br />

abessive kohvikuta without the coffee house


SUPPLEMENT THREE (PART II): TYPOLOGICAL CLASSIFICATION<br />

INFLECTIONAL LANGUAGES (FUSIONAL LANGUAGES): words consist of stem and<br />

affixes which often mark several grammatical categories simultaneously. Greek, Latin, Sanskrit,<br />

Russian. Examples in Latin (NomSg=nominative singular, NomPl=nominative plural,<br />

AccSg=accusative singular, AccPl=accusative plural, 3Sg=third person singular, 3Pl=third person<br />

plural):<br />

1. Custos fidelis consulem veterem ducit.<br />

NomSg NomSg AccSg AccSg 3Sg<br />

guard trusty consul old is leading<br />

‘The trusty guard is leading the old consul.’<br />

2. Custodes fideles consules veteres ducunt.<br />

NomPl/AccPl NomPl/AccPl NomPl/AccPl NomPl/AccPl 3Pl<br />

‘The trusty guards are leading the old consuls.’<br />

‘The old guards are leading the trusty consuls.’<br />

‘The trusty consuls are leading the old guards.’<br />

‘The old consuls are leading the trusty guards.’<br />

POLYSYNTHETIC LANGUAGES: words consist of long strings of stems and affixes, which<br />

may translate as an entire English sentence. American Indian languages. Examples in Ayacucho<br />

Quechua adapted from Parker, G., Ayacucho Quechua Grammar and Dictionary, Mouton, 1969:<br />

Verbs can be inflected for both actor and object in different persons and number.<br />

1. riku–yki ‘I see you.’<br />

2. riku–yki–čik ‘I see you all.’<br />

3. riku–yki–ku ‘We see you.’<br />

riku: ‘see’<br />

yki: first person singular actor and second person singular object<br />

čik: marks object as plural<br />

ku: marks actor as plural<br />

4. riku–wanki ‘You see me.’<br />

5. riku–wanki–čik ‘You all see me.’<br />

6. riku–wanki–ku ‘We see you.’<br />

wanki: second person singular actor and first person singular object<br />

čik: marks actor as plural<br />

ku: marks object as plural<br />

377


378<br />

GERMANIC:<br />

SUPPLEMENT FOUR (PART I): HISTORICAL CLASSIFICATION<br />

LEXICON: INDO–EUROPEAN<br />

love (n) mother father brother break (v) three five hundred heart<br />

ENGLISH: love mother father brother break three five hundred heart<br />

MID ENGLISH: love moder fader brother breke thre fīf hund(red) herte<br />

OLD ENGLISH: lufu mōdor fœder brōþor brecan þrī fīf(e) hund heorte<br />

GERMAN: liebe mutter vater bruder brechen drei fünf hundert herz<br />

DUTCH: liefde moeder vader broeder breken drie vijf honderd hart<br />

GREEK:<br />

ANCIENT GREEK: erōs mētēr patēr adelphos hrēgnūmi treis pente hekaton kardia<br />

CELTIC:<br />

IRISH: searc māthair athair brāthir brisim trī cóic cēt croidhe<br />

WELSCH: serch mam tad brawd torri tri pump cant calon<br />

ITALIC:<br />

LATIN: amor māter pater frater frangere trēs quinque centum cor<br />

rumpere<br />

ROMANCE:<br />

SPANISH: amor madre padre hermano romper tres cinco ciento corazón<br />

PORTUGUESE: amor mãe pai irmão quebrar três cinco cem coração<br />

ITALIAN: amore madre padre fratello rompere tre cinque cento cuore<br />

FRENCH: amour mère père frère rompre trois cinq cent coeur<br />

RUMANIAN: amor mamă tată frate frînge trei cinci sută inimă<br />

rupe<br />

BALTO–SLAVIC:<br />

RUSSIAN: ljubov' mat' otec brat lomat' tri pyat' sto serdce<br />

CHURCH SLAVIC: ljuby mati ot0c0 brat lomiti tr0je petь sßto srßd0ce<br />

INDO–IRANIAN:<br />

SANSKRIT: kāma– mātar– pitar– bhrātar– bhañj– trayas páñca çatam hr;d–<br />

HINDI: muhabbat mátá báp bháí torná tīn pãc sau dil<br />

AVESTAN: kan– mātar– pitar– brātar– sčand– ›rāyō panča satcm zcrcd–


ALTAIC:<br />

SUPPLEMENT FOUR (PART II): HISTORICAL CLASSIFICATION<br />

LEXICON: NON–INDO–EUROPEAN<br />

love (n) mother father brother break (v) three five hundred heart<br />

JAPANESE: ai haha chichi kyôdai kowareru san go hyaku shinzô<br />

SINO–TIBETAN:<br />

CHINESE: ai mßchīn fùchin syūngdì nùngpwò sān wß băi syīn<br />

URALIC:<br />

FINNISH: rakkaus äiti isä veli rikkoa kolme viisi sata sydän<br />

AUSTRONESIAN:<br />

SAMOAN: alofa tinā tamā uso 1 talepe 4 tolu lima selau fatu<br />

HAWAIIAN: aloha makuahine makua kua'ana 2 wāhi 4 kolu lima hanele pu'uwai<br />

AFRO–ASIATIC:<br />

CHADIC:<br />

HAUSA: so 5 ūwa ōba wā 3 kária úku biál darí zúts-ia<br />

SEMITIC:<br />

ARABIC: h;ubb §imm §ab(u) §ax yiksir talaate xamse miyye §alb<br />

UTO–AZTECAN:<br />

COMANCHE kamaku–ru– 5 pia ahpu–§ samohpu–§ tahparu– pihihtu– makekitu–§ pihi<br />

NOTES:<br />

1 uso = brother of a man; tuagane = brother of a woman<br />

2 kua'ana = older sibling of the same sex; kaina = younger sibling of the same sex; kuāne = sibling of a female;<br />

etc.<br />

3 wā = older male sibling; kāne = younger male sibling<br />

4 There are many verbs for break depending on the nature of the thing broken, e.g., hard things, brittle things,<br />

things that break easily, bones, etc.<br />

5 There is no noun meaning love; these are verb forms.<br />

379


380<br />

SUPPLEMENT FIVE (PART I): LANGUAGES OF AFRICA AND THE MID EAST*<br />

Family Branch Group Representative Languages Principal Locations Number of Speakers<br />

Afro–Asiatic<br />

(241)<br />

Chadic Hausa N Nigeria; Niger; Cameroon 39,000,000<br />

Semitic Hebrew Isreal 5,000,000<br />

Tigrinya S Eritrea; N Ethiopia 4,000,000<br />

Amharic Ethopia 20,000,000<br />

Arabic Egypt; Iraq; Syria; Morocco 230,000,000<br />

Hamitic Berber Tamazight W Algeria; N Morocco 3,000,000<br />

Kabyle W Kabylia; N Algeria 3,000,000<br />

Shilha W Algeria; S Morocco 3,000,000<br />

Cushitic Somali Somalia; Kenya; Ethiopia; Djibouti 4,000,000<br />

Galla (Oromo) W Ethopia; N Kenya 9,000,000<br />

Omotic Wolaytta SE Ethopia 2,000,000<br />

Khoisan (31) Nama (Hottentot) Namibia 146,000<br />

Niger–Congo<br />

(1032)<br />

Nilo–Sarahan<br />

(138)<br />

Sandawe Tanzania 70,000<br />

Mande Mende Sierra Leone 2,000,000<br />

West Atlantic Fula Senegal; Nigeria; Cameroon 13,000,000<br />

Wolof Senegal 7,000,000<br />

Kwa Akan Ghana; Côte d’Ivoire 7,000,000<br />

Yoruba SW Nigeria; Benin 20,000,000<br />

Igbo (Ibo) Nigeria 17,000,000<br />

Ewe S Togo; SE Ghana 3,000,000<br />

Benue–Congo Efik SE Nigeria 6,000,000<br />

Tiv SE Nigeria; Cameroon 2.000,000<br />

Bantu Swahili Tanzania; Kenya; Zaire; Uganda 49,000,000<br />

Zulu S Africa; Lesotho 9,000,000<br />

Xhosa S Africa 8,000,000<br />

Gur (Voltaic) More Burkina Faso 4,000,000<br />

Adamawa–Ubangian Sango Central African Republic 4,000,000<br />

Nilo–Hamitic Maasai Kenya; Tanzania 689,000<br />

Nilotic Luo Kenya; Nyanza; Tanzania 4,000,000<br />

* There is much scholarly debate on the classification of languages. The various subdivisions in Figure Four I, II, III, IV, and V reflect only<br />

major distinctions generally recognized. The approximate number of languages in each family is in parentheses (data from Ruhlen 1987).<br />

Statistics for individual languages with more than 1 million speakers are from The World Almanac and Book of Facts, 1997, Mahwah, NJ:<br />

World Almanac Books. Statistics for individual languages with less than 1 million speakers are from Grimes 1992.


SUPPLEMENT FIVE (PART II): AMERICAN INDIAN LANGUAGES<br />

Family Branch Group Representative Languages Principal Locations Number of Speakers<br />

Algonquian (15) Cree Canada; USA 46,700<br />

Andean–Equatorial<br />

(163)<br />

Ojibwa Canada; USA 51,000<br />

Arapaho Wyoming; W Oklahoma 1,500<br />

Blackfoot S Alberta; Montana 9,000<br />

Andean Quechua Peru; Equador; Bolivia; Argentina 8,000,000<br />

Aymara Bolivia; Peru 2,000,000<br />

Equatorial Guarani Paraguay 4,000,000<br />

Eskimo–Aleut (9) Eskimo Inuit Canadian Arctic; Greenland 68,500<br />

Yupik Alaska; Siberia 17,000<br />

Aleut Aleut Aleutian Islands 700<br />

Ge–Pano–Carib (117) Carib Northern South America 100,000<br />

Hokan (28) Yuman Diegueño Baja California less than 400<br />

Tequistlatecan Tequistlatec Mexico 5,000<br />

Iroquoian (7) Mohawk N New York 3,000<br />

Cherokee E Oklahoma; W North Carolina 22,500<br />

Caddoan (4) Pawnee N Central Oklahoma 200<br />

Na–Dené (34) Tlingit SE Alaska 2,000<br />

Athapaskan Navajo New Mexico; Arizona; Utah 130,000<br />

Apache Oklahoma; New Mexico; Arizona 14,300<br />

Chipewyan N Alberta; Saskatchewan 4,000<br />

Oto–Manguean (17) Otomian Zapotec S Mexico 500,000<br />

Mixtecan Mixtec S Mexico 250,000<br />

Penutian (68) Nez Perce N Idaho 500<br />

Mayan Quiche Guatemala 885,000<br />

Mosan (27) Squamish SW British Columbia 20<br />

Siouan–Yuchi (11) Dakota (Sioux) S Manitoba; Nebraska; Minnesota 19,000<br />

Crow S Montana 5,500<br />

Winnebago Wisconsin; E Nebraska 1,500<br />

Uto–Aztecan (25) Hopi NE Arizona 5,000<br />

Shoshonean Comanche W Oklahoma 500<br />

Takic Luiseño S California 100<br />

Sonoran Huichol Mexico 12,500<br />

Aztecan Nahuatl (Aztec) Southern Mexico 1,000,000<br />

381


382<br />

SUPPLEMENT FIVE (PART III): INDO–EUROPEAN LANGUAGES<br />

Family Branch Group Representative Languages Principal Locations Number of Speakers<br />

Indo–European<br />

(144)<br />

Albanian Albanian Albania; Yugoslavia 5,000,000<br />

Anatolian Hittite Ancient Asia Minor Extinct<br />

Armenian Armenian Armenia; Iran; Syria; Lebanon 5,000,000<br />

Balto–Slavic Baltic Lithuanian Lithuania 3,000,000<br />

Latvian Latvia 2,000,000<br />

Slavic Russian Russia 280,000,000<br />

Serbo–Croatian Serbia; Croatia; Bosnia 20,000,000<br />

Czech Czechoslovakia 12,000,000<br />

Polish Poland 44,000,000<br />

Celtic Brythonic Welsh Wales 580,000<br />

Goidelic Irish Ireland 120,000<br />

Germanic East Gothic Eastern Europe Extinct<br />

North Danish Denmark 5,000,000<br />

Norwegian Norway 5,000,000<br />

Swedish Sweden; Finland 9,000,000<br />

West Dutch Netherlands; Belgium 21,000,000<br />

English England, America 487,000,000<br />

German Germany 124,000,000<br />

Greek Greek Greece 12,000,000<br />

Indo–Iranian Indic Sanskrit Ancient India Extinct<br />

Bengali Bangladesh; India 204,000,000<br />

Hindi India 457,000,000<br />

Urdu Pakistan; India 104,000,000<br />

Punjabi India; Pakistan 95,000,000<br />

Iranian Pashto Afghanistan; Pakistan 21,000,000<br />

Persian Iran; Afghanistan 35,000,000<br />

Italic Latin Roman Empire Extinct<br />

Romance French France 125,000,000<br />

Romanian Romania; Moldova 26,000,000<br />

Italian Italy 62,000,000<br />

Portuguese Portugal; Brazil 186,000,000<br />

Spanish Spain; Central and South America 401,000,000


SUPPLEMENT FIVE (PART IV): LANGUAGES OF EAST ASIA & THE PACIFIC<br />

Family Branch Group Representative Languages Principal Locations Number of Speakers<br />

Australian (170) Pama–Nyungan Walbiri Australia 3,000<br />

Austro–Asiatic<br />

(155)<br />

Dyirbal Australia 40 to 50<br />

Mon–Khmer Khmer Kampuchea; Vietnam; Thailand 9,000,000<br />

Vietnamese Vietnam 63,000,000<br />

Nung Vietnam; China 2,000,000<br />

Munda Santali E India; Nepal 5,000,000<br />

Nicobarese Central Nicobarese Nicobar Islands 5,000<br />

Austronesian (959) Formosan Atayal Taiwan 41,000<br />

Western Malay–Indonesian Indonesia; Thailand 164,000,000<br />

Toba Batak Indonesia 4,000,000<br />

Javanese Java 64,000,000<br />

Sundanese Java 26,000,000<br />

Madurese Madura 10,000,000<br />

Tagalog Philippines 56,000,000<br />

Cebuano Philippines 12,000,000<br />

Malagasy Madagascar 12,000,000<br />

Oceanic Samoan Samoa 328,000<br />

Maori New Zealand 100,000<br />

Tahitian Tahiti 125,000<br />

Hawaiian Hawaii 2,000<br />

Indo–Pacific (731) Motu Papua New Guinea 15,000<br />

Sino–Tibetan (258) Tibeto–Burman Tibetan SW China; N India; Nepal 5,000,000<br />

Burmese Mayanmar (Burma) 31,000,000<br />

Newari Nepal 500,000<br />

Sinitic Mandarin Mandarin China 999,000,000<br />

Wu Wu Chiang Jiang delta, China 65,000,000<br />

Min Taiwanese Taiwan 50,000,000<br />

Yue Cantonese Guangdong province, China 70,000,000<br />

Hakka Hakka SE China 34,000,000<br />

Tai (57) Thai Thailand 52,000,000<br />

Shan E Mayanmar (Burma) 3,000,000<br />

Lao Thailand; Laos 4,000,000<br />

383


384<br />

SUPPLEMENT FIVE (PART V): OTHER LANGUAGES OF EUROPE AND ASIA<br />

Family Branch Group Representative Languages Principal Locations Number of Speakers<br />

Altaic (63) Turkic Turkish Turkey 61,000,000<br />

Azerbaijani Azerbaijan; Iran; Turkey 15,000,000<br />

Tartar Russia 8,000,000<br />

Uzbek Uzbekistan 14,000,000<br />

Mongolian Mongol Mongolian People’s Republic 6,000,000<br />

Manchu–Tungus Evenki Russia 24,000<br />

Manchu Northeast China less than 1,000<br />

Japanese Japanese Japan 126,000,000<br />

Korean Korean North Korea; South Korea 76,000,000<br />

Caucasian (38) Kartvelian Georgian Georgia; Azerbaijan; Turkey 4,000,000<br />

Svan Georgia 35,000<br />

Northwest Kabardian Northwest Caucasus; Russia 370,00<br />

Northeast Dagestanian Avar Northeast Caucasus 483,000<br />

Lezgian (Lezgi) Russia; Azerbaijan 383,000<br />

Nakh Chechen Chechnia 945,000<br />

Dravidian (28) Telugu Southeast India 75,000,000<br />

Tamil India; Sri Lanka 73,000,000<br />

Kannada S India 45,000,000<br />

Malayalam S India 36,000,000<br />

Paleosiberian (5) Chukchi Northeast Siberia 10,900<br />

Uralic (24) Finno–Ugric Finnic Finnish Finland 6,000,000<br />

Estonian Estonia 1,000,000<br />

Ugric Hungarian Hungary 14,000,000<br />

Samoyedic Nenets Arctic Russia 27,000


SUPPLEMENT SIX: LANGUAGES AND LANGUAGE GROUPS<br />

(Roman numerals in square brackets refer to the Parts in Supplement Five)<br />

Adamawa–Ubangian [I]<br />

Afro–Asiatic [I]<br />

Akan [I]<br />

Albanian [III]<br />

Aleut [II]<br />

Algonquian [II]<br />

Altaic [V]<br />

Amharic [I]<br />

Anatolian [III]<br />

Andean [II]<br />

Andean–Equatorial [II]<br />

Apache [II]<br />

Arabic [I]<br />

Arapaho [II]<br />

Armenian [III]<br />

Atayal [IV]<br />

Athapaskan [II]<br />

Australian [IV]<br />

Austronesian [IV]<br />

Austro–Asiatic [IV]<br />

Avar [V]<br />

Aymara [II]<br />

Azerbaijani [V]<br />

Aztec [II]<br />

Aztecan [II]<br />

Baltic [III]<br />

Balto–Slavic [III]<br />

Bantu [I]<br />

Bengali [III]<br />

Benue–Congo [I]<br />

Berber [I]<br />

Blackfoot [II]<br />

Brythonic [III]<br />

Burmese [IV]<br />

Caddoan [II]<br />

Cantonese [IV]<br />

Carib [II]<br />

Caucasian [V]<br />

Cebuano [IV]<br />

Celtic [III]<br />

Central Nicobarese [IV]<br />

Chadic [I]<br />

Chechen [V]<br />

Cherokee [II]<br />

Chipewyan [II]<br />

Chukchi [V]<br />

Comanche [II]<br />

Cree [II]<br />

Crow [II]<br />

Cushitic [I]<br />

Czech [III]<br />

Dagestanian [V]<br />

Dakota [II]<br />

Danish [III]<br />

Diegueño [II]<br />

Dravidian [V]<br />

Dutch [III]<br />

Dyirbal [IV]<br />

East Germanic [III]<br />

Efik [I]<br />

English [III]<br />

Equatorial [II]<br />

Eskimo [II]<br />

Eskimo–Aleut [II]<br />

Estonian [V]<br />

Evenki [V]<br />

Ewe [I]<br />

Finnic [V]<br />

Finnish [V]<br />

Finno–Ugric [V]<br />

Formosan [IV]<br />

French [III]<br />

Fula [I]<br />

Galla [I]<br />

Georgian [V]<br />

German [III]<br />

Germanic [III]<br />

Ge–Pano–Carib [II]<br />

Goidelic [III]<br />

Gothic [III]<br />

Greek [III]<br />

Guarani [II]<br />

Gur [I]<br />

Hakka [IV]<br />

Hamitic [I]<br />

Hausa [I]<br />

Hawaiian [IV]<br />

Hebrew [I]<br />

Hindi [III]<br />

Hittite [III]<br />

Hokan [II]<br />

Hopi [II]<br />

Hottentot [I]<br />

Huichol [II]<br />

Hungarian [V]<br />

Ibo [I]<br />

Igbo [I]<br />

Indic [III]<br />

Indo–European [III]<br />

Indo–Iranian [III]<br />

Indo–Pacific [IV]<br />

Inuit [II]<br />

Iranian [III]<br />

Irish [III]<br />

Iroquoian [II]<br />

Italian [III]<br />

Italic [III]<br />

Japanese [V]<br />

Javanese [IV]<br />

Kabardian [V]<br />

Kabyle [I]<br />

Kannada [V]<br />

Kartvelian [V]<br />

Khmer [IV]<br />

Khoisan [I]<br />

Korean [V]<br />

Kwa [I]<br />

Lao [IV]<br />

Latin [III]<br />

Latvian [III]<br />

Lezgi [V]<br />

Lezgian [V]<br />

Lithuanian [III]<br />

Luiseño [II]<br />

Luo [I]<br />

Maasai [I]<br />

385


386<br />

Madurese [IV]<br />

Malagasy [IV]<br />

Malayalam [V]<br />

Malay–Indonesian [IV]<br />

Manchu [V]<br />

Manchu–Tungus [V]<br />

Mandarin [IV]<br />

Mande [I]<br />

Maori [IV]<br />

Mayan [II]<br />

Mende [I]<br />

Min [IV]<br />

Mixtec [II]<br />

Mixtecan [II]<br />

Mohawk [II]<br />

Mongol [V]<br />

Mongolian [V]<br />

Mon–Khmer [IV]<br />

More [I]<br />

Mosan [II]<br />

Motu [IV]<br />

Munda [IV]<br />

Nahuatl [II]<br />

Nakh [V]<br />

Nama [I]<br />

Navajo [II]<br />

Na–Dené [II]<br />

Nenets [V]<br />

Newari [IV]<br />

Nez Perce [II]<br />

Nicobarese [IV]<br />

Niger–Congo [I]<br />

Nilotic [I]<br />

Nilo–Hamitic [I]<br />

Nilo–Sarahan [I]<br />

North Germanic [III]<br />

Northeast Caucasian [V]<br />

Northwest Caucasian [V]<br />

Norwegian [III]<br />

Nung [IV]<br />

Oceanic [IV]<br />

Ojibwa [II]<br />

Omotic [I]<br />

Oromo [I]<br />

Otomian [II]<br />

Oto–Manguean [II]<br />

Paleosiberian [V]<br />

Pama–Nyungan [IV]<br />

Pashto [III]<br />

Pawnee [II]<br />

Penutian [II]<br />

Persian [III]<br />

Polish [III]<br />

Portuguese [III]<br />

Punjabi [III]<br />

Quechua [II]<br />

Quiche [II]<br />

Romance [III]<br />

Romanian [III]<br />

Russian [III]<br />

Samoan [IV]<br />

Samoyedic [V]<br />

Sandawe [I]<br />

Sango [I]<br />

Sanskrit [III]<br />

Santali [IV]<br />

Semitic [I]<br />

Serbo–Croatian [III]<br />

Shan [IV]<br />

Shilha [I]<br />

Shoshonean [II]<br />

Sinitic [IV]<br />

Sino–Tibetan [IV]<br />

Siouan–Yuchi [II]<br />

Sioux [II]<br />

Slavic [III]<br />

Somali [I]<br />

Sonoran [II]<br />

Spanish [III]<br />

Squamish [II]<br />

Sundanese [IV]<br />

Svan [V]<br />

Swahili [I]<br />

Swedish [III]<br />

Tagalog [IV]<br />

Tahitian [IV]<br />

Tai [IV]<br />

Taiwanese [IV]<br />

Takic [II]<br />

Tamazight [I]<br />

Tamil [V]<br />

Tartar [V]<br />

Telugu [V]<br />

Tequistlatec [II]<br />

Tequistlatecan [II]<br />

Thai [IV]<br />

Tibetan [IV]<br />

Tibeto–Burman [IV]<br />

Tigrinya [I]<br />

Tiv [I]<br />

Tlingit [II]<br />

Toba Batak [IV]<br />

Turkic [V]<br />

Turkish [V]<br />

Ugric [V]<br />

Uralic [V]<br />

Urdu [III]<br />

Uto–Aztecan [II]<br />

Uzbek [V]<br />

Vietnamese [IV]<br />

Voltaic [I]<br />

Walbiri [IV]<br />

Welsh [III]<br />

West Germanic [III]<br />

West Atlantic [I]<br />

Western Austronesian [IV]<br />

Winnebago [II]<br />

Wolaytta [I]<br />

Wolof [I]<br />

Wu [IV]<br />

Xhosa [I]<br />

Yoruba [I]<br />

Yue [IV]<br />

Yuman [II]<br />

Yupik [II]<br />

Zapotec [II]<br />

Zulu [I]


SUPPLEMENT SEVEN: SOME ALPHABETS<br />

ROMAN GREEK CYRILLIC HEBREW ARABIC<br />

A a Α α alpha А а a א 0aleph,0alef ا \ 0alif<br />

B b Β β beta Б б be ב bēth ب ` bā<br />

C c Γ γ gamma В в ve ג gimel ت d tā<br />

D d Δ δ delta Г г ge ד dāleth ث h thā<br />

E e Ε ε epsilon Д д de ה hē ج l jim<br />

F f Ζ ζ zeta Е е je ו vav, waw ح p hā<br />

G g Η η eta Ё ё jo ז zayin خ t khā<br />

H h Θ θ theta Ж ж že ח h;eth د v dāi<br />

I i Ι ι iota З з ze ט t;eth ذ x dhāi<br />

J j Κ κ kappa И и i י yod, yodh ر z rā<br />

K k Λ λ lambda Й й í krátkcjc ך, כ kāph ز | zāy<br />

L l Μ μ mu К к ka ל lamedh س sin<br />

M m Ν ν nu Л л el ם, מ mēm ش … shin<br />

N n Ξ ξ xi М м em ןנ nūn ص ‰ s;ād<br />

O o Ο ο omicron Н н en ס samekh ض d;ād<br />

P p Π π pi О о o ע 0ayin ط ‘ t;ā<br />

Q q Ρ ρ rho П п pe ף, פ pē ظ • z;ā<br />

R r Σ σ, ς sigma Р р er ץ, צ sade, s;adhe ع 0yn<br />

S s Τ τ tau С с es ק qōph غ ghayn<br />

T t Υ υ upsilon Т т te ר rēsh ف ¡ fā<br />

U u Φ φ phi У у u ש sin ق ¥ qāf<br />

V v Χ χ chi Ф ф ef ש shin ك © kaf<br />

W w Ψ ψ psi Х х xa ת tāv, tāw ل − lam<br />

X x Ω ω omega Ц ц ce م ± mim<br />

Y y Ч ч čB a ن μ nun<br />

Z z Ш ш ša ﻩ ¹ hā<br />

387<br />

Щ щ šB čB a و ½ wāw<br />

Ъ ъ tvB órdi–j znák ي Á yā<br />

Ы ы i–<br />

Ь ь mB áxkcj znák<br />

Э э e<br />

Ю ю ju<br />

Я я ja


388


SUPPLEMENT EIGHT: SAMPLE PARSES FROM THE LANGTECH PARSER<br />

SAMPLE PARSES ILLUSTRATING BASIC SENTENCE PATTERNS<br />

(1) INTRANSITIVE:<br />

the senator resigned<br />

The clause “the senator resigned” is a statement.<br />

The phrase “the senator” is a noun phrase and the subject of the verb “resigned.”<br />

The word “resigned” is a past tense verb.<br />

The word “resigned” is the main verb of “the senator resigned.”<br />

The word “senator” is a singular count noun.<br />

The word “senator” is the head of the noun phrase “the senator.”<br />

The word “the” is a determiner specifying the noun “senator.”<br />

389


390<br />

(2) TRANSITIVE (DIRECT OBJECT COMPLEMENT ON V1):<br />

the senator admired the president<br />

The clause “the senator admired the president” is a statement.<br />

The phrase “the president” is a noun phrase and the direct object of the verb “admired.”<br />

The phrase “the senator” is a noun phrase and the subject of the verb “admired.”<br />

The word “admired” is a past tense verb.<br />

The word “admired” is the main verb of “the senator admired the president.”<br />

The word “president” is a singular count noun.<br />

The word “president” is the head of the noun phrase “the president.”<br />

The word “senator” is a singular count noun.<br />

The word “senator” is the head of the noun phrase “the senator.”<br />

The word “the” is a determiner specifying the noun “president.”<br />

The word “the” is a determiner specifying the noun “senator.”


(3) COPULATIVE (PREDICATE COMPLEMENT ON V2):<br />

the senator became the president<br />

The clause “the senator became the president” is a statement.<br />

The phrase “the president” is a noun phrase describing the subject “senator.”<br />

The phrase “the senator” is a noun phrase and the subject of the verb “became.”<br />

The word “became” is a past tense verb.<br />

The word “became” is the main verb of “the senator became the president.”<br />

The word “president” is a singular count noun.<br />

The word “president” is the head of the noun phrase “the president.”<br />

The word “senator” is a singular count noun.<br />

The word “senator” is the head of the noun phrase “the senator.”<br />

The word “the” is a determiner specifying the noun “senator.”<br />

The word “the” is a determiner specifying the noun “president.”<br />

391


392<br />

(4) COPULATIVE (PREDICATE COMPLEMENT ON V2):<br />

the senator turned red<br />

The clause “the senator turned red” is a statement.<br />

The phrase “red” is an adjective phrase describing the subject “senator.”<br />

The phrase “the senator” is a noun phrase and the subject of the verb “turned.”<br />

The word “red” is an adjective.<br />

The word “senator” is a singular count noun.<br />

The word “senator” is the head of the noun phrase “the senator.”<br />

The word “the” is a determiner specifying the noun “senator.”<br />

The word “turned” is a past tense verb.<br />

The word “turned” is the main verb of “the senator turned red.”


(5) INTRANSITIVE WITH A MANNER ADVERB:<br />

the senator resigned angrily<br />

The clause “the senator resigned angrily” is a statement.<br />

The phrase “angrily” is an adverb phrase modifying the verb “resigned.”<br />

The phrase “the senator” is a noun phrase and the subject of the verb “resigned.”<br />

The word “angrily” is a manner adverb.<br />

The word “resigned” is a past tense verb.<br />

The word “resigned” is the main verb of “the senator resigned angrily.”<br />

The word “senator” is a singular count noun.<br />

The word “senator” is the head of the noun phrase “the senator.”<br />

The word “the” is a determiner specifying the noun “senator.”<br />

393


394<br />

(6) INTRANSITIVE WITH PREDICATE ADJECTIVE:<br />

the senator resigned angry<br />

The clause “the senator resigned angry” is a statement.<br />

The phrase “angry” is a predicate adjective referring back to the subject “senator.”<br />

The phrase “the senator” is a noun phrase and the subject of the verb “resigned.”<br />

The word “angry” is an adjective.<br />

The word “resigned” is a past tense verb.<br />

The word “resigned” is the main verb of “the senator resigned angry.”<br />

The word “senator” is a singular count noun.<br />

The word “senator” is the head of the noun phrase “the senator.”<br />

The word “the” is a determiner specifying the noun “senator.”


(7) TRANSITIVE (DIRECT OBJECT + MANNER ADVERB):<br />

fred left the country quickly<br />

The clause “fred left the country quickly” is a statement.<br />

The phrase “fred” is a noun phrase and the subject of the verb “left.”<br />

The phrase “quickly” is an adverb phrase modifying the verb “left.”<br />

The phrase “the country” is a noun phrase and the direct object of the verb “left.”<br />

The word “country” is a singular count noun.<br />

The word “country” is the head of the noun phrase “the country.”<br />

The word “fred” is a proper noun.<br />

The word “left” is a past tense verb.<br />

The word “left” is the main verb of “fred left the country quickly.”<br />

The word “quickly” is a manner adverb.<br />

The word “the” is a determiner specifying the noun “country.”<br />

395


396<br />

(8) TRANSITIVE (DIRECT OBJECT + MANNER ADVERB):<br />

fred left the country happily<br />

The clause “fred left the country happily” is a statement.<br />

The phrase “fred” is a noun phrase and the subject of the verb “left.”<br />

The phrase “happily” is an adverb phrase modifying the verb “left.”<br />

The phrase “the country” is a noun phrase and the direct object of the verb “left.”<br />

The word “country” is a singular count noun.<br />

The word “country” is the head of the noun phrase “the country.”<br />

The word “fred” is a proper noun.<br />

The word “happily” is a manner adverb.<br />

The word “left” is a past tense verb.<br />

The word “left” is the main verb of “fred left the country happily.”<br />

The word “the” is a determiner specifying the noun “country.”


(9) fred left the country happy<br />

a. TRANSITIVE (DIRECT OBJECT + OBJECTIVE COMPLEMENT):<br />

The clause “fred left the country happy” is a statement.<br />

The phrase “fred” is a noun phrase and the subject of the verb “left.”<br />

The phrase “happy” is an adjective phrase describing “country.”<br />

The phrase “the country” is a noun phrase and the direct object of the verb “left.”<br />

The word “country” is the head of the noun phrase “the country.”<br />

The word “country” is a singular count noun.<br />

The word “fred” is a proper noun.<br />

The word “happy” is an adjective.<br />

The word “left” is a past tense verb.<br />

The word “left” is the main verb of “fred left the country happy.”<br />

The word “the” is a determiner specifying the noun “country.”<br />

397


398<br />

b. TRANSITIVE (DIRECT OBJECT + SUBJECTIVE COMPLEMENT):<br />

The clause “fred left the country happy” is a statement.<br />

The phrase “fred” is a noun phrase and the subject of the verb “left.”<br />

The phrase “happy” is a predicate adjective referring back to the subject “fred.”<br />

The phrase “the country” is a noun phrase and the direct object of the verb “left.”<br />

The word “country” is the head of the noun phrase “the country.”<br />

The word “country” is a singular count noun.<br />

The word “fred” is a proper noun.<br />

The word “happy” is an adjective.<br />

The word “left” is a past tense verb.<br />

The word “left” is the main verb of “fred left the country happy.”<br />

The word “the” is a determiner specifying the noun “country.”


(10) TRANSITIVE (DIRECT OBJECT + INDIRECT OBJECT):<br />

she gave them to us<br />

The clause “she gave them to us” is a statement.<br />

The phrase “she” is a noun phrase and the subject of the verb “gave.”<br />

The phrase “them” is a noun phrase and the direct object of the verb “gave.”<br />

The phrase “to us” is a prepositional phrase and the indirect object of the verb “gave.”<br />

The phrase “us” is a noun phrase and the object of the preposition “to.”<br />

The word “gave” is a past tense verb.<br />

The word “gave” is the main verb of “she gave them to us.”<br />

The word “she” is a third person singular feminine subject pronoun.<br />

The word “them” is a third person plural object pronoun.<br />

The word “to” is a preposition introducing the prepositional phrase “to us"<br />

The word “us” is a first person plural object pronoun.<br />

399


400<br />

(11) TRANSITIVE (DIRECT OBJECT + PREPOSITIONAL PHRASE):<br />

she put them near us<br />

The clause “she put them near us” is a statement.<br />

The phrase “near us” is a prepositional phrase and a complement of the verb “put.”<br />

The phrase “she” is a noun phrase and the subject of the verb “put.”<br />

The phrase “them” is a noun phrase and the direct object of the verb “put.”<br />

The phrase “us” is a noun phrase and the object of the preposition “near.”<br />

The word “near” is a preposition introducing the prepositional phrase “near us"<br />

The word “put” is a past tense verb.<br />

The word “put” is the main verb of “she put them near us.”<br />

The word “she” is a third person singular feminine subject pronoun.<br />

The word “them” is a third person plural object pronoun.<br />

The word “us” is a first person plural object pronoun.


(12) TRANSITIVE (DOUBLE OBJECT):<br />

she gave us them<br />

The clause “she gave us them” is a statement.<br />

The phrase “she” is a noun phrase and the subject of the verb “gave.”<br />

The phrase “them” is a noun phrase and the direct object of the verb “gave.”<br />

The phrase “us” is a noun phrase and the indirect object of the verb “gave.”<br />

The word “gave” is a past tense verb.<br />

The word “gave” is the main verb of “she gave us them.”<br />

The word “she” is a third person singular feminine subject pronoun.<br />

The word “them” is a third person plural object pronoun.<br />

The word “us” is a first person plural object pronoun.<br />

401


402<br />

(13) TRANSITIVE (DOUBLE OBJECT):<br />

they elected a democrat the president<br />

The clause “they elected a democrat the president” is a statement.<br />

The phrase “a democrat” is a noun phrase and the direct object of the verb “elected.”<br />

The phrase “the president” is a noun phrase and the object complement of the verb “elected.”<br />

The phrase “they” is a noun phrase and the subject of the verb “elected.”<br />

The word “a” is a determiner specifying the noun “democrat.”<br />

The word “democrat” is a singular count noun.<br />

The word “democrat” is the head of the noun phrase “a democrat.”<br />

The word “elected” is a past tense verb.<br />

The word “elected” is the main verb of “they elected a democrat the president.”<br />

The word “president” is a singular count noun.<br />

The word “president” is the head of the noun phrase “the president.”<br />

The word “the” is a determiner specifying the noun “president.”<br />

The word “they” is a third person plural subject pronoun.


(14) TRANSITIVE (SENTENTIAL COMPLEMENT; INDIRECT STATEMENT):<br />

I know that she went<br />

The clause “I know that she went” is a statement.<br />

The clause “she went” is an indirect statement.<br />

The clause “that she went” is a complement clause of the verb “know.”<br />

The phrase “I” is a noun phrase and the subject of the verb “know.”<br />

The phrase “she” is a noun phrase and the subject of the verb “went.”<br />

The word “I” is a first person singular subject pronoun.<br />

The word “know” is a present tense verb.<br />

The word “know” is the main verb of “I know that she went.”<br />

The word “she” is a third person singular feminine subject pronoun.<br />

The word “that” is a complementizer specifying the complement clause “she went.”<br />

The word “went” is a past tense verb.<br />

The word “went” is the main verb of “that she went.”<br />

403


404<br />

(15) TRANSITIVE (SENTENTIAL COMPLEMENT; INDIRECT STATEMENT):<br />

I know she went<br />

The clause “I know she went” is a statement.<br />

The clause “she went” is an indirect statement.<br />

The phrase “I” is a noun phrase and the subject of the verb “know.”<br />

The phrase “she went” is a complement clause of the verb “know.”<br />

The word “I” is a first person singular subject pronoun.<br />

The word “know” is a present tense verb.<br />

The word “know” is the main verb of “I know she went.”<br />

The word “Ø” is a complementizer specifying the complement clause “she went.”<br />

The word “she” is a third person singular feminine subject pronoun.<br />

The word “went” is a past tense verb.<br />

The word “went” is the main verb of “she went.”


(16) TRANSITIVE (SENTENTIAL COMPLEMENT; INDIRECT STATEMENT):<br />

I know that man is mortal<br />

The clause “I know that man is mortal” is a statement.<br />

The clause “man is mortal” is an indirect statement.<br />

The clause “that man is mortal” is a complement clause of the verb “know.”<br />

The phrase “I” is a noun phrase and the subject of the verb “know.”<br />

The phrase “man” is a noun phrase and the subject of the verb “Is.”<br />

The phrase “mortal” is a predicate adjective referring back to the subject “man.”<br />

The word “I” is a first person singular subject pronoun.<br />

The word “Is” is a third person singular present tense verb.<br />

The word “Is” is the main verb of “man is mortal.”<br />

The word “know” is a present tense verb.<br />

The word “know” is the main verb of “I know that man is mortal.”<br />

The word “man” is the head of the noun phrase “man.”<br />

The word “mortal” is an adjective.<br />

The word “Ø” is an abstract empty determiner specifying the noun “man.”<br />

The word “that” is a complementizer specifying the complement clause “man is mortal.”<br />

405


406<br />

The clause “I know that man is mortal” is a statement.<br />

The clause “that man is mortal” is a complement clause of the verb “know.”<br />

The clause “that man is mortal” is an indirect statement.<br />

The phrase “I” is a noun phrase and the subject of the verb “know.”<br />

The phrase “mortal” is a predicate adjective referring back to the subject “man.”<br />

The phrase “that man” is a noun phrase and the subject of the verb “Is.”<br />

The word “I” is a first person singular subject pronoun.<br />

The word “Is” is a third person singular present tense verb.<br />

The word “Is” is the main verb of “that man is mortal.”<br />

The word “know” is a present tense verb.<br />

The word “know” is the main verb of “I know that man is mortal.”<br />

The word “man” is the head of the noun phrase “that man.”<br />

The word “mortal” is an adjective.<br />

The word “Ø” is a complementizer specifying the complement clause “that man is mortal.”<br />

The word “that” is a determiner specifying the noun “man.”


(17) TRANSITIVE (SENTENTIAL COMPLEMENT; INDIRECT QUESTION):<br />

I know whether she went<br />

The clause “I know whether she went” is a statement.<br />

The clause “whether she went” is an indirect question.<br />

The phrase “I” is a noun phrase and the subject of the verb “know.”<br />

The phrase “she” is a noun phrase and the subject of the verb “went.”<br />

The word “I” is a first person singular subject pronoun.<br />

The word “know” is a present tense verb.<br />

The word “know” is the main verb of “I know whether she went.”<br />

The word “she” is a third person singular feminine subject pronoun.<br />

The word “went” is a past tense verb.<br />

The word “went” is the main verb of “whether she went.”<br />

The word “whether” is an interrogative pronoun.<br />

407


408<br />

(18) TRANSITIVE (SENTENTIAL COMPLEMENT; INDIRECT QUESTION):<br />

I know where she went<br />

The clause “I know where she went” is a statement.<br />

The clause “where she went” is an indirect question.<br />

The phrase “I” is a noun phrase and the subject of the verb “know.”<br />

The phrase “she” is a noun phrase and the subject of the verb “went.”<br />

The phrase “[e]” is the referent of “where” and the empty modifier phrase of the verb “went.”<br />

The word “I” is a first person singular subject pronoun.<br />

The word “know” is a present tense verb.<br />

The word “know” is the main verb of “I know where she went.”<br />

The word “she” is a third person singular feminine subject pronoun.<br />

The word “went” is a past tense verb.<br />

The word “went” is the main verb of “where she went.”<br />

The word “where” is an interrogative pronoun.


(19) TRANSITIVE (SENTENTIAL COMPLEMENT; INDIRECT QUESTION):<br />

I know who went<br />

The clause “I know who went” is a statement.<br />

The clause “who went” is an indirect question.<br />

The phrase “I” is a noun phrase and the subject of the verb “know.”<br />

The phrase “[e]” is the referent of “who” and the empty subject noun phrase of the verb “went.”<br />

The word “I” is a first person singular subject pronoun.<br />

The word “know” is a present tense verb.<br />

The word “know” is the main verb of “I know who went.”<br />

The word “went” is a past tense verb.<br />

The word “went” is the main verb of “who went.”<br />

The word “who” is an interrogative pronoun.<br />

409


410<br />

(20) TRANSITIVE (SENTENTIAL COMPLEMENT; INDIRECT QUESTION):<br />

I know who he admires<br />

The clause “I know who he admires” is a statement.<br />

The clause “who he admires” is an indirect question.<br />

The phrase “I” is a noun phrase and the subject of the verb “know.”<br />

The phrase “[e]” is an abstract empty noun phrase and the direct object of the verb “admires.”<br />

The word “admires” is a third person singular present tense verb.<br />

The word “admires” is the main verb of “who he admires.”<br />

The word “he” is a third person singular masculine subject pronoun.<br />

The word “I” is a first person singular subject pronoun.<br />

The word “know” is a present tense verb.<br />

The word “know” is the main verb of “I know who he admires.”<br />

The word “who” is an interrogative pronoun.


(21) TRANSITIVE (DIRECT OBJECT + S COMPLEMENT; INDIRECT STATEMENT):<br />

he told me that she went<br />

The clause “he told me that she went” is a statement.<br />

The clause “that she went” is a complement clause of the verb “told.”<br />

The clause “she went” is an indirect statement.<br />

The phrase “he” is a noun phrase and the subject of the verb “told.”<br />

The phrase “me” is a noun phrase and the direct object of the verb “told.”<br />

The phrase “she” is a noun phrase and the subject of the verb “went.”<br />

The word “he” is a third person singular masculine subject pronoun.<br />

The word “me” is a first person singular object pronoun.<br />

The word “she” is a third person singular feminine subject pronoun.<br />

The word “that” is a complementizer specifying the complement clause “she went.”<br />

The word “told” is a past tense verb.<br />

The word “told” is the main verb of “he told me that she went.”<br />

The word “went” is a past tense verb.<br />

The word “went” is the main verb of “that she went.”<br />

411


412<br />

(22) TRANSITIVE (DIRECT OBJECT + S COMPLEMENT; INDIRECT STATEMENT):<br />

he told me she went<br />

The clause “he told me she went” is a statement.<br />

The clause “that she went” is a complement clause of the verb “told.”<br />

The clause “she went” is an indirect statement.<br />

The phrase “he” is a noun phrase and the subject of the verb “told.”<br />

The phrase “me” is a noun phrase and the direct object of the verb “told.”<br />

The word “he” is a third person singular masculine subject pronoun.<br />

The word “me” is a first person singular object pronoun.<br />

The word “Ø” is a complementizer specifying the complement clause “she went.”<br />

The word “she” is a third person singular feminine subject pronoun.<br />

The word “told” is a past tense verb.<br />

The word “told” is the main verb of “he told me she went.”<br />

The word “went” is a past tense verb.<br />

The word “went” is the main verb of “that she went.”


(23) TRANSITIVE (DIRECT OBJECT + S COMPLEMENT; INDIRECT QUESTION):<br />

he told me whether she went<br />

The clause “he told me whether she went” is a statement.<br />

The clause “whether she went” is a complement clause of the verb “told.”<br />

The clause “whether she went” is an indirect question.<br />

The phrase “he” is a noun phrase and the subject of the verb “told.”<br />

The phrase “me” is a noun phrase and the direct object of the verb “told.”<br />

The phrase “she” is a noun phrase and the subject of the verb “went.”<br />

The word “he” is a third person singular masculine subject pronoun.<br />

The word “me” is a first person singular object pronoun.<br />

The word “she” is a third person singular feminine subject pronoun.<br />

The word “told” is a past tense verb.<br />

The word “told” is the main verb of “he told me whether she went.”<br />

The word “went” is a past tense verb.<br />

The word “went” is the main verb of “whether she went.”<br />

The word “whether” is an interrogative pronoun.<br />

413


414<br />

(24) TRANSITIVE (DIRECT OBJECT + S COMPLEMENT; INDIRECT QUESTION):<br />

he told me where she went<br />

The clause “he told me where she went” is a statement.<br />

The clause “where she went” is a complement clause of the verb “told.”<br />

The clause “where she went” is an indirect question.<br />

The phrase “he” is a noun phrase and the subject of the verb “told.”<br />

The phrase “me” is a noun phrase and the direct object of the verb “told.”<br />

The phrase “she” is a noun phrase and the subject of the verb “went.”<br />

The phrase “[e]” is the referent of “where” and the empty modifier phrase of the verb “went.”<br />

The word “he” is a third person singular masculine subject pronoun.<br />

The word “me” is a first person singular object pronoun.<br />

The word “she” is a third person singular feminine subject pronoun.<br />

The word “told” is a past tense verb.<br />

The word “told” is the main verb of “he told me where she went.”<br />

The word “went” is a past tense verb.<br />

The word “went” is the main verb of “where she went.”<br />

The word “where” is an interrogative pronoun.


(25) TRANSITIVE (DIRECT OBJECT + S COMPLEMENT; INDIRECT QUESTION):<br />

he told me who [e] went<br />

The clause “he told me who went” is a statement.<br />

The clause “who went” is an indirect question.<br />

The phrase “me” is a noun phrase and the direct object of the verb “told.”<br />

The phrase “he” is a noun phrase and the subject of the verb “told.”<br />

The phrase “[e]” is the referent of “who” and the empty subject noun phrase of the verb “went.”<br />

The word “me” is a first person singular object pronoun.<br />

The word “he” is a third person singular masculine subject pronoun.<br />

The word “told” is a past tense verb.<br />

The word “told” is the main verb of “he told me who went.”<br />

The word “went” is a past tense verb.<br />

The word “went” is the main verb of “who went.”<br />

The word “who” is an interrogative pronoun.<br />

415


416<br />

(26) TRANSITIVE (DIRECT OBJECT + S COMPLEMENT; INDIRECT QUESTION):<br />

he told me who she admires<br />

The clause “he told me who she admires” is a statement.<br />

The clause “who she admires” is an indirect question.<br />

The phrase “me” is a noun phrase and the direct object of the verb “told.”<br />

The phrase “he” is a noun phrase and the subject of the verb “told.”<br />

The phrase “[e]” is an abstract empty noun phrase and the direct object of the verb “admires.”<br />

The word “admires” is a third person singular present tense verb.<br />

The word “admires” is the main verb of “who she admires.”<br />

The word “he” is a third person singular masculine subject pronoun.<br />

The word “me” is a first person singular object pronoun.<br />

The word “she” is a third person singular feminine subject pronoun.<br />

The word “told” is a past tense verb.<br />

The word “told” is the main verb of “he told me who she admires.”<br />

The word “who” is an interrogative pronoun.


(27) TRANSITIVE (PREPOSITIONAL PHRASE OBJECT):<br />

he relies on her advice<br />

The clause “he relies on her advice” is a statement.<br />

The phrase “he” is a noun phrase and the subject of the verb “relies.”<br />

The phrase “her advice” is a noun phrase and the object of the preposition “on.”<br />

The phrase “her” is a possessive phrase specifying “advice.”<br />

The phrase “on her advice” is a prepositional phrase and a complement of the verb “relies.”<br />

The word “advice” is a singular mass noun.<br />

The word “advice” is the head of the noun phrase “her advice.”<br />

The word “he” is a third person singular masculine subject pronoun.<br />

The word “her” is a third person singular feminine possessive pronoun.<br />

The word “on” is a preposition introducing the prepositional phrase “on her advice.”<br />

The word “POS” is a determiner specifying the noun “advice.”<br />

The word “relies” is a third person singular present tense verb.<br />

The word “relies” is the main verb of “he relies on her advice.”<br />

417


418<br />

(28) INTRANSITIVE (PREPOSITIONAL PHRASE MODIFIER):<br />

he went on her advice<br />

The clause “he went on her advice” is a statement.<br />

The phrase “he” is a noun phrase and the subject of the verb “went.”<br />

The phrase “her advice” is a noun phrase and the object of the preposition “on.”<br />

The phrase “her” is a possessive phrase specifying “advice.”<br />

The phrase “on her advice” is a prepositional phrase and a modifier of the verb “went.”<br />

The word “advice” is a singular mass noun.<br />

The word “advice” is the head of the noun phrase “her advice.”<br />

The word “he” is a third person singular masculine subject pronoun.<br />

The word “her” is a third person singular feminine possessive pronoun.<br />

The word “on” is a preposition introducing the prepositional phrase “on her advice.”<br />

The word “POS” is a determiner specifying the noun “advice.”<br />

The word “went” is a past tense verb.<br />

The word “went” is the main verb of “he went on her advice.”


(29) TRANSITIVE (PREPOSITIONAL PHRASE OBJECT):<br />

she sat on the hat<br />

The clause “she sat on the hat” is a statement.<br />

The phrase “on the hat” is a prepositional phrase and a complement of the verb “sat.”<br />

The phrase “she” is a noun phrase and the subject of the verb “sat.”<br />

The phrase “the hat” is a noun phrase and the object of the preposition “on.”<br />

The word “hat” is a singular count noun.<br />

The word “hat” is the head of the noun phrase “the hat.”<br />

The word “on” is a preposition introducing the prepositional phrase “on the hat.”<br />

The word “sat” is the main verb of “she sat on the hat.”<br />

The word “sat” is a past tense verb.<br />

The word “she” is a third person singular feminine subject pronoun.<br />

The word “the” is a determiner specifying the noun “hat.”<br />

419


420<br />

(30) TRANSITIVE (PARTICLE + DIRECT OBJECT):<br />

she put on the hat<br />

The clause “she put on the hat” is a statement.<br />

The phrase “she” is a noun phrase and the subject of the verb “put.”<br />

The phrase “the hat” is a noun phrase and the direct object of the verb “put.”<br />

The word “hat” is a singular count noun.<br />

The word “hat” is the head of the noun phrase “the hat.”<br />

The word “on” is a particle (intransitive preposition).<br />

The word “put” is the main verb of “she put on the hat.”<br />

The word “put” is a past tense verb.<br />

The word “she” is a third person singular feminine subject pronoun.<br />

The word “the” is a determiner specifying the noun “hat.”


(31) TRANSITIVE (DIRECT OBJECT + PARTICLE):<br />

she put the hat on<br />

The clause “she put the hat on” is a statement.<br />

The phrase “she” is a noun phrase and the subject of the verb “put.”<br />

The phrase “the hat” is a noun phrase and the direct object of the verb “put.”<br />

The word “hat” is a singular count noun.<br />

The word “hat” is the head of the noun phrase “the hat.”<br />

The word “on” is a particle (intransitive preposition).<br />

The word “put” is a past tense verb.<br />

The word “put” is the main verb of “she put the hat on.”<br />

The word “she” is a third person singular feminine subject pronoun.<br />

The word “the” is a determiner specifying the noun “hat.”<br />

421


422<br />

(32) TRANSITIVE (DIRECT OBJECT + PARTICLE):<br />

she put the hat right on<br />

The clause “she put the hat right on” is a statement.<br />

The phrase “right” is an adverb phrase modifying the particle “on.”<br />

The phrase “she” is a noun phrase and the subject of the verb “put.”<br />

The phrase “the hat” is a noun phrase and the direct object of the verb “put.”<br />

The word “hat” is a singular count noun.<br />

The word “hat” is the head of the noun phrase “the hat.”<br />

The word “on” is a particle (intransitive preposition).<br />

The word “put” is a past tense verb.<br />

The word “put” is the main verb of “she put the hat right on.”<br />

The word “she” is a third person singular feminine subject pronoun.<br />

The word “right” is an adverb.<br />

The word “the” is a determiner specifying the noun “hat.”


(33) TRANSITIVE (COMPLEMENTARY INFINITIVE):<br />

she asked to go<br />

The clause “she asked to go” is a statement.<br />

The phrase “she” is a noun phrase and the subject of the verb “asked.”<br />

The phrase “to go” is an infinitive complement of the verb “asked.”<br />

The word “asked” is a past tense verb.<br />

The word “asked” is the main verb of “she asked to go.”<br />

The word “go” is an infinitive verb.<br />

The word “she” is a third person singular feminine subject pronoun.<br />

The word “to” is the infinitive marker introducing the infinitive phrase “to go.”<br />

423


424<br />

(34) TRANSITIVE (DIRECT OBJECT + COMPLEMENTARY INFINITIVE):<br />

she asked him to go<br />

The clause “she asked him to go” is a statement.<br />

The phrase “him” is a noun phrase and subject of the infinitive verb “go.”<br />

The phrase “him” is a noun phrase and the direct object of the verb “asked.”<br />

The phrase “she” is a noun phrase and the subject of the verb “asked.”<br />

The phrase “to go” is an infinitive complement of the verb “asked.”<br />

The word “asked” is a past tense verb.<br />

The word “asked” is the main verb of “she asked him to go.”<br />

The word “go” is an infinitive verb.<br />

The word “him” is a third person singular masculine object pronoun.<br />

The word “she” is a third person singular feminine subject pronoun.<br />

The word “to” is the infinitive marker introducing the infinitive phrase “to go.”


(35) TRANSITIVE (PREPOSITIONAL OBJECT WITH INFINITIVE):<br />

she prayed for him to win<br />

The clause “she prayed for him to win” is a statement.<br />

The phrase “for him to win” is a prepositional phrase and a complement of the verb “prayed.”<br />

The phrase “him” is a noun phrase and the subject of the verb “win.”<br />

The phrase “him” is a noun phrase and the object of the preposition “for.”<br />

The phrase “she” is a noun phrase and the subject of the verb “prayed.”<br />

The word “for” is a preposition introducing the prepositional phrase “for him to win.”<br />

The word “him” is a third person singular masculine object pronoun.<br />

The word “prayed” is a past tense verb.<br />

The word “prayed” is the main verb of “she prayed for him to win.”<br />

The word “she” is a third person singular feminine subject pronoun.<br />

The word “to” is the infinitive marker introducing the infinitive phrase “to win.”<br />

The word “win” is an infinitive verb.<br />

425


426<br />

(36) TRANSITIVE (PREPOSITIONAL OBJECT WITH INFINITIVE):<br />

she relied on him to finish<br />

The clause “she relied on him to finish” is a statement.<br />

The phrase “him” is a noun phrase and the object of the preposition “on.”<br />

The phrase “him” is a noun phrase and the subject of the verb “finish.”<br />

The phrase “on him to finish” is a prepositional phrase and a complement of the verb “relied.”<br />

The phrase “she” is a noun phrase and the subject of the verb “asked.”<br />

The word “finish” is an infinitive verb.<br />

The word “him” is a third person singular masculine object pronoun.<br />

The word “on” is a preposition introducing the prepositional phrase “on him to finish.”<br />

The word “relied” is a past tense verb.<br />

The word “relied” is the main verb of “she relied on him to finish.”<br />

The word “she” is a third person singular feminine subject pronoun.<br />

The word “to” is the infinitive marker introducing the infinitive phrase “to finish.”<br />

What are the TG equivalents of these two trees?


SUPPLEMENT NINE: SAMPLE PARSES FROM THE LANGTECH PARSER<br />

SAMPLE PARSES ILLUSTRATING NOUN PHRASES<br />

(1) The Spanish American history teacher resigned.<br />

history teacher who is Spanish and American teacher of American history who is Spanish<br />

history teacher who is Spanish American teacher of Spanish American history<br />

427


428<br />

(2) The kitchen appliance factory guarantee expired.<br />

(3) All the men’s money disappeared.


(4) All those many nosey house guests with excessive demands are a pain in the neck.<br />

(5) The quick brown fox jumped over the lazy dog.<br />

429


430<br />

(6) The soprano from a small town in the south of France collapsed.


SUPPLEMENT TEN: SAMPLE PARSES FROM THE LANGTECH PARSER<br />

(1) Is this the violin Kevin Played?<br />

EMPTY CATEGORIES: Ø, [u], and [e]<br />

a. This violin is the violin.<br />

this violin PRS is the violin<br />

b. This is the violin.<br />

this [u] PRS is the violin<br />

c. Is this the violin?<br />

is i PRS j this [u] [e] j [e] i the violin<br />

d. Is this the violin which Kevin played?<br />

is i PRS j this [u] [e] j [e] i the violin k which k Ø Kevin played [e] k<br />

e. Is this the violin that Kevin played?<br />

is i PRS j this [u] [e] j [e] i the violin k [e] k that Kevin played [e] k<br />

f. Is this the violin Kevin played?<br />

is i PRS j this [u] [e] j [e] i the violin k [e] k Ø Kevin played [e] k<br />

(2) X3 Representaton.<br />

431


432<br />

(2) We believe John to be completely dominated by his wife.<br />

An [e] is coindexed with its closest C-commanding N3.


(3) Saturn’s rings are believed to be completely dominated by its moons.<br />

An [e] is coindexed with its closest C-commanding N3.<br />

433


434<br />

SUPPLEMENT ELEVEN: SAMPLE PARSES FROM THE LANGTECH PARSER<br />

SAMPLE PARSES ILLUSTRATING PARTICIPLES<br />

The internal structure of all –ing and –ed/en forms are as follows:<br />

(1) Progressive Participles (-ing) and Derived Adjectives (DA1).<br />

a. Participle (the lady charming the man): [ C3 [ C0 [ C0 -ing] [ V3 [ V0 charming]]]]<br />

b. Adjective (a very charming lady): [ C3 [ C0 [ V3 [ V0 charming]] [ C0 DA1]]]


(2) Passive Participles (-en) and Derived Adjectives (DA2).<br />

a. Participle (charmed by her flattery): [ C3 [ C0 [ C0 -en] [ V3 [ V0 charmed]]]]<br />

b. Derived Adjective (a very charmed life): [ C3 [ C0 [ V3 [ V0 charmed]] [ C0 DA2]]]<br />

435


436<br />

(3) Gerundial Nominals (-ing) and Derived Nominals (DN).<br />

a. -ing (charming candy from a baby): [ N3 [ N0 [ N0 -ing] [ V3 [ V0 charming]]]]<br />

b. DN: (such charming of snakes): [ N3 [ N0 [ V3 [ V0 charming]] [ N0 DN]]]


(4) Summary of Verbal Structures.<br />

a. Verb resides in posthead position.<br />

[ C3 [ C0 [ C0 -ing] [ V3 [ V0 charming]] ]]<br />

[ C3 [ C0 [ C0 -en] [ V3 [ V0 charmed]] ]]<br />

[ N3 [ N0 [ N0 -ing] [ V3 [ V0 charming]] ]]<br />

b. Verb resides in prehead position.<br />

[ C3 [ C0 [ V3 [ V0 charming]] [ C0 DA1] ]]<br />

[ C3 [ C0 [ V3 [ V0 charmed]] [ C0 DA2] ]]<br />

[ N3 [ N0 [ V3 [ V0 charming]] [ N0 DN] ]]<br />

Notice that the four possible ing–forms in English have the feature specification [–VBL] (they are<br />

subjuncts); two are [–NML] (the derived adjective and the present participle); two are [+NML] (the<br />

derived nominal and the gerundial nominal). Further, the two members of each pair are mirror<br />

images of each other. Thus, all are subjuncts with a V3 embedded on their X0 level.<br />

The nominal nature of gerunds is accounted for by embedding that V3 into an N3, and the adjectival<br />

nature of participles is accounted for by embedding that V3 into a C3.<br />

437


438<br />

SAMPLE PARSES FROM THE LANGTECH PARSER<br />

(5) TRANSITIVE (DIRECT OBJECT + BARE INFINITIVE VERB):<br />

i saw him cheer<br />

The clause "i saw him cheer" is a statement.<br />

The phrase "cheer" is the bare infinitive complement of the verb "saw".<br />

The phrase "him" is a noun phrase and the direct object of the verb "saw".<br />

The phrase "i" is a noun phrase and the subject of the verb "saw".<br />

The word "cheer" is a bare infinitive verb.<br />

The word "him" is a third person singular masculine object pronoun.<br />

The word "i" is a first person singular subject pronoun.<br />

The word "saw" is a past tense verb.<br />

The word "saw" is the main verb of "i saw him cheer".


(6) TRANSITIVE (DIRECT OBJECT + PASSIVE PARTICIPLE):<br />

i saw him cheered<br />

The clause "i saw him cheered" is a statement.<br />

The phrase "cheered" is a passive participle phrase describing "him".<br />

The phrase "him" is a noun phrase and the direct object of the verb "saw".<br />

The phrase "i" is a noun phrase and the subject of the verb "saw".<br />

The phrase "[e]" is an empty noun phrase and the direct object of the verb "cheered".<br />

The word "cheered" is a passive participle.<br />

The word "him" is a third person singular masculine object pronoun.<br />

The word "i" is a first person singular subject pronoun.<br />

The word "saw" is a past tense verb.<br />

The word "saw" is the main verb of "i saw him cheered".<br />

The word "[-ed]" is the abstract marker for the passive participle.<br />

439


440<br />

(7) TRANSITIVE (DIRECT OBJECT + PROGRESSIVE PARTICIPLE):<br />

i saw him cheering<br />

The clause "i saw him cheering" is a statement.<br />

The phrase "cheering" is a progressive participle phrase describing "him".<br />

The phrase "him" is a noun phrase and the direct object of the verb "saw".<br />

The phrase "i" is a noun phrase and the subject of the verb "saw".<br />

The word "cheering" is a progressive participle.<br />

The word "him" is a third person singular masculine object pronoun.<br />

The word "i" is a first person singular subject pronoun.<br />

The word "saw" is a past tense verb.<br />

The word "saw" is the main verb of "i saw him cheering".<br />

The word "[-ing]" is the abstract marker for the progressive participle.<br />

The clause "i saw him cheering" is a statement.<br />

The phrase "cheering" is a progressive participle phrase describing "i".<br />

The phrase "him" is a noun phrase and the direct object of the verb "saw".<br />

The phrase "i" is a noun phrase and the subject of the verb "saw".<br />

The word "cheering" is a progressive participle.<br />

The word "him" is a third person singular masculine object pronoun.<br />

The word "i" is a first person singular subject pronoun.<br />

The word "saw" is a past tense verb.<br />

The word "saw" is the main verb of "i saw him cheering".<br />

The word "[-ing]" is the abstract marker for the progressive participle.


(8) AMBIGUITY:<br />

i heard the tenor singing<br />

The clause "i heard the tenor singing" is a statement.<br />

The phrase "i" is a noun phrase and the subject of the verb "heard".<br />

The phrase "the tenor singing" is a noun phrase and the direct object of the verb "heard".<br />

The word "heard" is a past tense verb.<br />

The word "heard" is the main verb of "i heard the tenor singing".<br />

The word "i" is a first person singular subject pronoun.<br />

The word "singing" is a singular count noun.<br />

The word "singing" is the head of the noun phrase "the tenor singing".<br />

The word "tenor" is a noun forming a compound noun with "singing".<br />

The word "tenor" is a singular count noun.<br />

The word "tenor" is the head of the noun phrase "tenor".<br />

The word "the" is a determiner specifying the noun "singing".<br />

The clause "i heard the tenor singing" is a statement.<br />

The phrase "i" is a noun phrase and the subject of the verb "heard".<br />

The phrase "singing" is a progressive participle phrase describing "tenor".<br />

The phrase "the tenor singing" is a noun phrase and the direct object of the verb "heard".<br />

The word "heard" is a past tense verb.<br />

The word "heard" is the main verb of "i heard the tenor singing".<br />

The word "i" is a first person singular subject pronoun.<br />

The word "singing" is a progressive participle.<br />

The word "tenor" is a singular count noun.<br />

The word "tenor" is the head of the noun phrase "the tenor singing".<br />

The word "the" is a determiner specifying the noun "tenor".<br />

The word "[-ing]" is the abstract marker for the progressive participle.<br />

441


442<br />

The clause "i heard the tenor singing" is a statement.<br />

The phrase "i" is a noun phrase and the subject of the verb "heard".<br />

The phrase "singing" is a progressive participle phrase describing "tenor".<br />

The phrase "the tenor" is a noun phrase and the direct object of the verb "heard".<br />

The word "heard" is a past tense verb.<br />

The word "heard" is the main verb of "i heard the tenor singing".<br />

The word "i" is a first person singular subject pronoun.<br />

The word "singing" is a progressive participle.<br />

The word "tenor" is a singular count noun.<br />

The word "tenor" is the head of the noun phrase "the tenor".<br />

The word "the" is a determiner specifying the noun "tenor".<br />

The word "[-ing]" is the abstract marker for the progressive participle.<br />

The clause "i heard the tenor singing" is a statement.<br />

The phrase "i" is a noun phrase and the subject of the verb "heard".<br />

The phrase "singing" is a progressive participle phrase describing "i".<br />

The phrase "the tenor" is a noun phrase and the direct object of the verb "heard".<br />

The word "heard" is a past tense verb.<br />

The word "heard" is the main verb of "i heard the tenor singing".<br />

The word "i" is a first person singular subject pronoun.<br />

The word "singing" is a progressive participle.<br />

The word "tenor" is a singular count noun.<br />

The word "tenor" is the head of the noun phrase "the tenor".<br />

The word "the" is a determiner specifying the noun "tenor".<br />

The word "[-ing]" is the abstract marker for the progressive participle.


INDEX<br />

Abstract Noun ..............................................................371<br />

Acceptable .................................................................358<br />

Accidental Gap ..............................................................76<br />

Accompanier ...............................................................261<br />

Accusative .................................................................375<br />

Acoustic Phonetics ............................................................55<br />

Active.....................................................................375<br />

Adjective ........................................................53, 54, 182, 372<br />

Adjunct....................................................................148<br />

Adverb ....................................................................372<br />

Affix......................................................................374<br />

Affricate ....................................................................61<br />

Agent .....................................................................260<br />

Agentive...................................................................261<br />

Agglutinating Language ......................................................376<br />

Allomorph ..................................................................78<br />

Allophone ...................................................................70<br />

Alphabet...................................................................387<br />

Alternative Element ..........................................................135<br />

Alveolar ................................................................. 59-61<br />

Ambiguity .............................................................257, 364<br />

Analytic Language ...........................................................376<br />

Anaphor ...............................................................196, 318<br />

Anaphora ..................................................................325<br />

Antepenult ...............................................................69, 89<br />

Anterior .................................................................60, 63<br />

Antonym ..................................................................256<br />

Argumentation ...............................................................30<br />

Articulatory Phonetics .........................................................55<br />

Aspect ....................................................................375<br />

Aspiration...................................................................69<br />

Assimilate .................................................................350<br />

Assimilation .................................................................81<br />

Attributive Position ..........................................................372<br />

Auditory Phonetics ...........................................................55<br />

Auxiliary ..................................................................182<br />

Back .................................................................... 57-59<br />

Barrier ....................................................................318<br />

Barriers....................................................................335<br />

Behaviorism ................................................................345<br />

Bilabial..................................................................59, 60<br />

Binding Relation ............................................................319<br />

Binding Resident ........................................................315, 335<br />

Bound Morpheme ...........................................................374


444<br />

Brace .....................................................................135<br />

C-command ........................................................195, 318, 327<br />

Case ......................................................................375<br />

Case Grammar ..............................................................260<br />

Case Relation ...............................................................261<br />

Central .....................................................................57<br />

Cerebral Lateralization .......................................................345<br />

Characterizer ...............................................................171<br />

Chunk .....................................................................126<br />

Clause..................................................................36, 373<br />

Co-occurrence Restriction .....................................................147<br />

Cognition ..................................................................305<br />

Collective Noun .............................................................371<br />

Command..............................................................195, 203<br />

Common Noun..............................................................371<br />

Common Nouns .............................................................137<br />

Comparative Degree .........................................................372<br />

Complement................................................................156<br />

Complementizer.............................................................182<br />

Concrete Noun ..............................................................371<br />

Conditional.............................................................136, 375<br />

Conjugation ................................................................374<br />

Conjunction ................................................................373<br />

Connotation ................................................................255<br />

Consonant ..................................................................59<br />

Consonantal .................................................................63<br />

Continuant ..................................................................63<br />

Continuity Theory I ..........................................................366<br />

Continuity Theory II .........................................................366<br />

Contraction Block Condition ...................................................200<br />

Coordinating ...............................................................182<br />

Copulative Verb .............................................................372<br />

Core Grammar ...........................................................34, 347<br />

Coronal..................................................................60, 63<br />

Count Noun ................................................................371<br />

Creativity ...................................................................28<br />

Curly Bracket...............................................................135<br />

C–command ................................................................318<br />

Dative.....................................................................261<br />

Declarative .................................................................373<br />

Declension .................................................................374<br />

Deep Structure ..............................................................193<br />

Degree Word ...............................................................182<br />

Demonstrative Pronoun .......................................................372


Denotation .................................................................255<br />

Descriptive Adequacy .....................................................38, 132<br />

Descriptive Grammar..........................................................28<br />

Determiner .................................................................182<br />

Dimensional ................................................................283<br />

Diphthong ..................................................................59<br />

Direct .....................................................................127<br />

Direct Object ............................................................53, 127<br />

Discontinuity Theory .........................................................366<br />

Distinctive Feature.........................................................58, 71<br />

Empiricism.................................................................345<br />

Empty Categories....................................................192, 197, 325<br />

Empty Category Condition ................................................199, 336<br />

Endocentricity ..........................................................145, 157<br />

Exclamatory ................................................................373<br />

Experiencer ................................................................261<br />

Explanatory Adequacy.....................................................38, 132<br />

Feminine ..................................................................375<br />

First Person ............................................................118, 375<br />

Flap .......................................................................62<br />

Floating Quantifier...........................................................325<br />

Formal Universal .........................................................34, 349<br />

Free Morpheme .............................................................374<br />

Free Resident ...........................................................316, 335<br />

Free Variation ...............................................................78<br />

Fricative ....................................................................61<br />

Front.......................................................................57<br />

Functional Category..........................................................133<br />

Fusional Language ...........................................................377<br />

Future .....................................................................136<br />

Gender ....................................................................375<br />

Genitive ...................................................................375<br />

Glide....................................................................59, 62<br />

Glottal .....................................................................60<br />

Goal ......................................................................262<br />

Grammar ...................................................................28<br />

Grammatical.............................................................23, 358<br />

Grammatical Characterization Problem........................................25, 339<br />

Grammatical Realization Problem............................................25, 341<br />

Head ..................................................................152, 373<br />

Head-Only Category .........................................................318<br />

Head–Only .................................................................146<br />

Hierarchical Order ...........................................................124<br />

Hierarchy ..................................................................133<br />

445


446<br />

High .......................................................................58<br />

Historical Classification.......................................................378<br />

Holonymy .................................................................256<br />

Homonym .................................................................256<br />

Homorganic .................................................................81<br />

Hypernymy ................................................................256<br />

Hyponymy .................................................................256<br />

Idioms ....................................................................256<br />

Imperative .........................................................136, 373, 375<br />

Indefinite Pronoun ...........................................................371<br />

Indicative ..................................................................375<br />

Indo–European ..............................................................378<br />

Inflection ..................................................................374<br />

Inflectional Ending ..........................................................374<br />

Inflectional Language ........................................................377<br />

Instrument .............................................................260, 261<br />

Instrumental ................................................................261<br />

Intensive Pronoun ...........................................................371<br />

Inter-dental..................................................................60<br />

Interdental ..................................................................61<br />

Interrogative................................................................373<br />

Interrogative Pronoun ........................................................372<br />

Intransitive Verb ........................................................192, 372<br />

Isolating Language ...........................................................376<br />

L-command ............................................................318, 332<br />

Labeled Brackets ........................................................154, 184<br />

Labio-dental .................................................................60<br />

Labiodental .................................................................61<br />

Language Variation ...........................................................43<br />

Lateral .....................................................................62<br />

Lax ........................................................................59<br />

Left Branching Construction ...................................................361<br />

Levels of Adequacy ...........................................................38<br />

Lexical Ambiguities .........................................................161<br />

Lexical Component ...........................................................86<br />

Lexicon ....................................................................86<br />

Linear Order................................................................124<br />

Linguistic Competence .................................................24, 25, 339<br />

Linguistic Performance ....................................................25, 341<br />

Linguistic Structure ...........................................................30<br />

Linguistic Universal .......................................................34, 347<br />

Liquid......................................................................62<br />

Locative ...................................................................262<br />

Long Term Memory ..........................................................126


Low .......................................................................58<br />

LTM ......................................................................126<br />

L–Command ...............................................................318<br />

Manner ....................................................................182<br />

Manner Adverb .............................................................131<br />

Manner of Articulation ........................................................60<br />

Marked ...............................................................37, 81, 85<br />

Masculine..................................................................375<br />

Mass Noun .................................................................371<br />

Maximal Projection ..........................................................145<br />

Mentalism .................................................................345<br />

Meronymy .................................................................256<br />

Mid........................................................................57<br />

Minimal Pair ................................................................72<br />

Modal .................................................................136, 182<br />

Mode .................................................................135, 375<br />

Mood .................................................................135, 375<br />

Morpheme ..............................................................77, 374<br />

Morphology .............................................................77, 374<br />

Morphophonemic .............................................................78<br />

Morphophonological Rule ......................................................78<br />

Multiple Branching Construction ...............................................361<br />

Nasal ...................................................................62, 63<br />

Native Language .............................................................23<br />

Native Language Acquisition ..................................................341<br />

Native Speaker...............................................................23<br />

Native Speaker Intuition .......................................................32<br />

Nativism...................................................................345<br />

Natural Class ................................................................71<br />

Neighborhood ..........................................................315, 327<br />

Nested Construction..........................................................362<br />

Neuter.....................................................................375<br />

Node Admissibility Condition ..................................................308<br />

Nominative ................................................................375<br />

Nonaccidental Gap ............................................................76<br />

Nonanterior ..............................................................60, 63<br />

Nonback ....................................................................59<br />

Nonconsonantal ..............................................................63<br />

Noncontinuant ...............................................................63<br />

Noncoronal...............................................................60, 63<br />

Nondistinctive Feature .........................................................71<br />

Nonhigh ....................................................................58<br />

Nonlow.....................................................................58<br />

Nonnasal ...................................................................63<br />

447


448<br />

Nonpositional Thematic Relation ...................................279, 283, 286, 292<br />

Nonround ...................................................................59<br />

Nonsibilant..................................................................63<br />

Nonsonorant .................................................................63<br />

Nonstative .................................................................278<br />

Nontense ...................................................................59<br />

Nonvocalic ..................................................................63<br />

Nonvoiced ..................................................................63<br />

Noun............................................................53, 54, 182, 371<br />

Number ...................................................................375<br />

Nurturism ..................................................................345<br />

Object.....................................................................171<br />

Object Formation ............................................................263<br />

Objective ..................................................................261<br />

Objective ..................................................................375<br />

Observational Adequacy ...................................................38, 132<br />

Obstruent ...................................................................63<br />

Omission .......................................................31, 126, 131, 350<br />

Optional Element ............................................................135<br />

Palatal...................................................................60, 61<br />

Paraphrase .............................................................257, 364<br />

Parentheses.................................................................135<br />

Parser .....................................................................309<br />

Parts of Speech ..............................................................371<br />

Passive ....................................................................375<br />

Past.......................................................................136<br />

Patient ....................................................................261<br />

Penult ...................................................................69, 89<br />

Perfective ..................................................................375<br />

Permanent Resident ..................................................313, 317, 335<br />

Person.....................................................................375<br />

Personal Pronoun ............................................................371<br />

Personal Pronoun ...........................................................325<br />

Phoneme ....................................................................70<br />

Phonetic Symbol .............................................................56<br />

Phonetician ..................................................................55<br />

Phonetics ...................................................................55<br />

Phonological Component .......................................................85<br />

Phonological Rule ........................................................73, 108<br />

Phonologist .................................................................55<br />

Phonology ...............................................................55, 69<br />

Phonotactic Rule .............................................................76<br />

Phonotactics .................................................................76<br />

Phrase.........................................................124, 125, 152, 373


Phrase Structure Filter ........................................................182<br />

Phrase Structure Grammar.....................................................143<br />

Pitch .......................................................................67<br />

Place of Articulation ..........................................................60<br />

Placement .......................................................31, 126, 131, 350<br />

Polysynthetic Language .......................................................377<br />

Positional ..................................................................273<br />

Positional Thematic Relation...................................................273<br />

Positive Degree .............................................................372<br />

Possessive .................................................................262<br />

Possessive .................................................................375<br />

Possessive Pronoun ......................................................119, 371<br />

Pragmatics .................................................................259<br />

Predicate...............................................................127, 373<br />

Predicate Position ...........................................................372<br />

Prefix .....................................................................374<br />

Preposition .............................................................182, 373<br />

Prescriptive Grammar .........................................................28<br />

Present ....................................................................136<br />

Progressive.................................................................375<br />

Pronoun ...............................................................182, 371<br />

Proper Noun................................................................371<br />

Proper Nouns ...............................................................137<br />

Quantifier ..................................................................182<br />

R-command ............................................................318, 331<br />

Rationalism ................................................................345<br />

Recipient ..................................................................261<br />

Reciprocal Pronoun ......................................................325, 372<br />

Recoverability of Deletion Condition ............................................202<br />

Recursive ...............................................................28, 174<br />

Redundancy Rule .............................................................85<br />

Reference ...........................................................31, 125, 350<br />

Reflexive Pronoun ...................................................118, 325, 371<br />

Relative Pronoun ............................................................372<br />

Release .....................................................................71<br />

Residence ..............................................................172, 306<br />

Residential Domain ..................................................318, 319, 335<br />

Residential Grammar .....................................................170, 194<br />

Right Branching Construction ..................................................361<br />

Root ......................................................................374<br />

Round ...................................................................58, 59<br />

Rule Formalism ..............................................................89<br />

R–Command ...............................................................318<br />

Second Language Acquisition ..................................................341<br />

449


450<br />

Second Person ..........................................................118, 375<br />

Semantic Function ...........................................................260<br />

Semantic Network .......................................................294, 296<br />

Semantics ..................................................................255<br />

Semivowel ..................................................................62<br />

Sentence ...............................................................127, 373<br />

Sentence Adverb .........................................................30, 131<br />

Short Term Memory .........................................................126<br />

Sibilant .....................................................................63<br />

Slash–dash Notation ......................................................73, 111<br />

Sonorant ....................................................................63<br />

Source ....................................................................262<br />

Specifier ...................................................................149<br />

Spelling ....................................................................87<br />

Stative ....................................................................278<br />

Stem ......................................................................374<br />

STM ......................................................................126<br />

Stop ....................................................................59, 63<br />

Stress ......................................................................67<br />

Structural Ambiguities ........................................................162<br />

Structural Category ..........................................................133<br />

Structural Grammar ......................................................132, 143<br />

Subject .........................................................53, 127, 171, 373<br />

Subject Formation ...........................................................263<br />

Subordinating ...............................................................182<br />

Substantive.................................................................374<br />

Substantive Universal .....................................................34, 347<br />

Suffix .....................................................................374<br />

Superlative Degree...........................................................372<br />

Suprasegmental ..............................................................67<br />

Surface Structure ............................................................193<br />

Synonym ..................................................................256<br />

Syntactic Categories .........................................................371<br />

Syntactic Construction........................................................373<br />

Syntactic Feature ............................................................147<br />

Syntactic Function ...........................................................260<br />

Syntactic Unit ..............................................................152<br />

Syntax ............................................................117, 305, 374<br />

Tense ...........................................................58, 59, 135, 375<br />

Thematic Relation .......................................................261, 302<br />

Theme ....................................................................261<br />

Third Person................................................................375<br />

Time ......................................................................135<br />

Topicalization ..............................................................191


Trace .....................................................................192<br />

Traditional Grammar .........................................................127<br />

Transformational Grammar ................................133, 137, 145, 147, 191, 193<br />

Transformational Rule ........................................................192<br />

Transitive Verb .........................................................192, 372<br />

Tree Diagram ...............................................................127<br />

Typological Classification .....................................................376<br />

Ultima ..................................................................69, 89<br />

Unacceptable ...............................................................358<br />

Ungrammatical...........................................................23, 358<br />

Universal Grammar .....................................................28, 32, 34<br />

Unmarked.............................................................37, 81, 85<br />

Velar....................................................................59, 60<br />

Verb ........................................................53, 54, 127, 182, 372<br />

Verb Phrase ............................................................127, 133<br />

Vocalic .....................................................................63<br />

Voice .....................................................................375<br />

Voiced ...............................................................55, 61, 63<br />

Voiceless ................................................................61, 63<br />

Voicing.....................................................................55<br />

Vowel..................55, 117, 120, 121, 123, 125, 126, 138, 142, 203, 206, 214, 217, 218<br />

Vowel Harmony..............................................................65<br />

Writing .....................................................................29<br />

X-Bar Syntax ...................................................152, 153, 157, 159<br />

451


452<br />

NOTES


NOTES<br />

453


454<br />

NOTES


NOTES<br />

455


456<br />

NOTES


NOTES<br />

457


458<br />

NOTES

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!