05.07.2013 Views

linguistic structures - Professor Binkert's Webpage - Oakland ...

linguistic structures - Professor Binkert's Webpage - Oakland ...

linguistic structures - Professor Binkert's Webpage - Oakland ...

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

(51) a. Assimilate [+NASAL] consonants to the place of articulation of a following stop,<br />

that is, to the features [ANTERIOR] and [CORONAL].<br />

b. Assimilate adjacent [–NASAL] consonants in voicing.<br />

Of course, (51) is directly related to the nature of the human vocal apparatus. It is more natural to<br />

make adjacent features similar because it is easier to articulate them when they are similar. Children<br />

engage in such simplification from the earliest stages of language acquisition when their vocal<br />

apparatus is still not completely formed. For example, they say things such as gig kig for big pig<br />

assimilating the stops to the same place of articulation because it is too difficult for them to<br />

articulate a syllable like big which begins with an anterior stop and ends with a nonanterior one; it<br />

is easier to make them both the same, so children say gig.<br />

With regard to levels of adequacy, the above characterization proceeds as follows. If it stops at<br />

simply noting the data in (46), then only observational adequacy would be attained. If it stops at the<br />

rule (48), which describes (44) in generalized terms applicable to other data (cf. (49)), then<br />

descriptive adequacy would be attained. If the characterization continues to principle (51) and<br />

relates (51) to the structure of the human vocal apparatus, then explanatory adequacy has been<br />

attained.<br />

The significance of the highest level is that one can separate what is expected to occur in natural<br />

language from what is not expected to occur. Also, at the level of explanatory adequacy, the real<br />

nature of apparent exceptions is often clarified. To see this, notice that the rule (48) is not always<br />

followed, even in English. Consider the following data involving the prefix non– meaning ‘not,’<br />

which is also of Latin origin:<br />

(52) a. [n] nonperson, nonbiodegradable, nonman<br />

b. [n] nontaxable, nondelivery, nonnative<br />

c. [n] noncombat, nongaseous<br />

Notice that non is always pronounced with a final [n]. We must say, therefore, that, if non is a<br />

prefix, it is an exception to (48). However, the matter does not stop there. The prefixes in– and<br />

con– are of Latin origin, and, in Latin, they also function as prefixes, though they are related to<br />

independent words (in and cum). Similarly, syn–, which is of Greek origin, functions as a prefix in<br />

Greek, though it is related to an independent Greek word (syn). The element non, on the other hand,<br />

never functions as a prefix in Latin; it occurs only as a separate word meaning ‘not’ and in a few<br />

compound words. Even in English, the merger of non with the following word is not as complete<br />

as the merger with in– or con– or syn–. Notice the slight pause and shift of articulatory posture after<br />

saying non in the examples of (52). Such hesitation and adjustment does not occur in the examples<br />

in (46), (49) and (50). This indicates that our characterization has missed something. Even in<br />

English, it is probably wrong to consider non a prefix, though it looks like one. If we treat words<br />

like nonman as compounds like snowman or manhole, then non is not a prefix and, accordingly, is<br />

not subject to rule (48). Thus, an apparent exception, after closer examination, is seen not to be an<br />

exception at all.<br />

41

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!