06.06.2013 Views

Theory of Statistics - George Mason University

Theory of Statistics - George Mason University

Theory of Statistics - George Mason University

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

Notes and Further Reading 139<br />

and formulates two postulates that essentially require invariance <strong>of</strong> the limit<br />

under any selections within the collective. This notion came to be called “statistical<br />

probability”. Two years later, Keynes (1921) developed a concept <strong>of</strong><br />

probability in terms <strong>of</strong> the relative support one statement leads to another<br />

statement. This idea was called “inductive probability”. As Kolmogorov’s axiomatic<br />

approach (see below) came to define probability theory and statistical<br />

inference for most mathematicians and statisticians, the disconnect between<br />

statistical probability and inductive probability continued to be <strong>of</strong> concern.<br />

Leblanc (1962) attempted to reconcile the two concepts, and his little book is<br />

recommended as a good, but somewhat overwrought, discussion <strong>of</strong> the issues.<br />

Define probability as a special type <strong>of</strong> measure<br />

We have developed the concept <strong>of</strong> probability by first defining a measurable<br />

space, then defining a measure, and finally defining a special measure as a<br />

probability measure.<br />

Define probability by a set <strong>of</strong> axioms<br />

Alternatively, the concept <strong>of</strong> probability over a given measurable space could<br />

be stated as axioms. In this approach, there would be four axioms: nonnegativity,<br />

additivity over disjoint sets, probability <strong>of</strong> 1 for the sample space, and<br />

equality <strong>of</strong> the limit <strong>of</strong> probabilities <strong>of</strong> a monotonic sequence <strong>of</strong> sets to the<br />

probability <strong>of</strong> the limit <strong>of</strong> the sets. The axiomatic development <strong>of</strong> probability<br />

theory is due to Kolmogorov in the 1920s and 1930s. In Kolmogorov (1956),<br />

he starts with a sample space and a collection <strong>of</strong> subsets and gives six axioms<br />

that characterize a probability space. (Four axioms are the same or similar<br />

to those above, and the other two characterize the collection <strong>of</strong> subsets as a<br />

σ-field.)<br />

Define probability from a coherent ordering<br />

Given a sample space Ω and a collection <strong>of</strong> subsets A, we can define a total<br />

ordering on A. (In some developments following this approach, A is required<br />

to be a σ-field; in other approaches, it is not.) The ordering consists <strong>of</strong> the<br />

relations “≺”, “”, “∼”, “≻”, and “”. The ordering is defined by five axioms<br />

it must satisfy. (“Five” depends on how you count, <strong>of</strong> course; in the five<br />

laid out below, which is the most common way the axioms are stated, some<br />

express multiple conditions.) For any sets, A, Ai, B, Bi ∈ A whose unions and<br />

intersections are in A (if A is a a σ-field this clause is unnecessary), the axioms<br />

are:<br />

1. Exactly one <strong>of</strong> the following relations holds: A ≻ B, A ∼ B, or A ≺ B.<br />

2. Let A1, A2, B1, B2 be such that A1 ∩ A2 = ∅, B1 ∩ B2 = ∅, A1 B1, and<br />

A2 B2. Then A1 ∪ A2 B1 ∪ B2. Furthermore, if either A1 ≺ B1 or<br />

A2 ≺ B2, then A1 ∪ A2 ≺ B1 ∪ B2.<br />

3. ∅ A and ∅ ≺ Ω.<br />

4. If A1 ⊇ A2 ⊇ · · · and for each i, Ai B, then ∩iAi B.<br />

<strong>Theory</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>Statistics</strong> c○2000–2013 James E. Gentle

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!