12.07.2015 Views

The requirement to respect autonomy - The Royal New Zealand ...

The requirement to respect autonomy - The Royal New Zealand ...

The requirement to respect autonomy - The Royal New Zealand ...

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS
  • No tags were found...

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

ethicsCritiqueIf this account of the argument against publicfunding of treatments for obesity such as bariatricsurgery is accurate, it exposes a number ofpoints that warrant further investigation.Claim 1 makes a substantive normative claimabout the general duties of citizens. It is rathera plausible claim <strong>to</strong> make, tapping in<strong>to</strong> easilyaccepted ideas about fair shares, and the moralimportance of being attentive <strong>to</strong> the effect ofone’s actions upon others. <strong>The</strong> idea is that claims<strong>to</strong> common resources that arise from genuineand unavoidable need are legitimate, and do notwrong or harm others, whilst claims that are notso based are illegitimate, and harm others byreducing available public funds without legitimatecause.One aspect of this claim that requires clarificationrelates <strong>to</strong> baselines for harm. In what senseare those in need of health care harmed by theclaims of others? <strong>The</strong> intuitive response would be<strong>to</strong> say that the claims of one, P, reduce the fundsavailable <strong>to</strong> satisfy the claims of another, Q. Ifthat means that a lower standard of care is available<strong>to</strong> Q, perhaps Q is harmed by P.But we wouldn’t normally think that patientsharm each other by drawing on public resources.<strong>The</strong> resources are there for all who need them,and it is in the nature of communal resources thatcompromises in individual claims are sometimesrequired. <strong>The</strong> entitlement of Q is not reducedby P, since P was never entitled <strong>to</strong> more than areasonable share, given competing demands.But this does not fully diffuse Claim 1. <strong>The</strong>point it advances is that there is a differencebetween legitimate claims (those which could notreasonably be minimised) and illegitimate claims(those which the patient has in some way allowed<strong>to</strong> arise). Legitimate claims do not harm others,because they do not reduce entitlements, butillegitimate claims do: they wrongfully lay claim<strong>to</strong> resources that could otherwise have been used<strong>to</strong> satisfy truly unavoidable health needs.<strong>The</strong> idea that we ought <strong>to</strong> minimise our claimson public resources has intuitive appeal. Butif we consider the vast range of activities thatwe consider permissible, and even valuable insociety, the idea that there is an absolute duty<strong>to</strong> minimise claims <strong>to</strong> public resources loses itslustre. Surely we are not required <strong>to</strong> refrain fromabsolutely every activity that might elevate claims<strong>to</strong> public resources, since many of the activitiesthat we value—having children, playing contactsports, entering certain professions (the fire service;the military; and perhaps medicine)—harbourpalpable health-related risks.To rescue Claim 1 from the perils of implausibility,it is necessary <strong>to</strong> find some way <strong>to</strong> distinguishbetween worthwhile activity of the kind that is<strong>to</strong> be fostered by society and activity that doesnot justify the associated risks. Perhaps it shouldbe rephrased as follows:‘Claim 1: Competent adults have a responsibility<strong>to</strong> minimise their claims <strong>to</strong> limited publicresources whilst pursuing worthwhile life goals.’This rephrasing exposes its inevitably judgementalnature. To argue against funding treatment forobesity on the basis of Claim 1, one has <strong>to</strong> showthat the actions and choices that lead <strong>to</strong> obesityare not compatible with the pursuit of worthwhilelife goals. That may not be as easy as itseems. <strong>The</strong> reasons that people become obese maybe much more value-laden than one might gatherfrom some commenta<strong>to</strong>rs. Eating is a source ofenormous personal, social and cultural importand can solidify and confirm a sense of personaland group identity. 5–9 In some cases, particularrituals and routines around food may be risky.One can object <strong>to</strong> the risk, and call for it <strong>to</strong> bereduced, without claiming that becoming obeseis in contravention of a responsibility of the sortexpressed in Claim 1.Claims 2–5 take an empirical form and thus standor fall according <strong>to</strong> the evidence. But even if itcould be demonstrated that the vast majority ofadults do recognise the health risks attached <strong>to</strong>obesity, these claims might remain problematic.Obesity often has its roots in childhood and,once obesity is established, it is very difficult <strong>to</strong>banish through conventional means like dietingand increased physical activity. 10–12 Althoughadults may well be expected <strong>to</strong> know that obesityVOLUME 2 • NUMBER 4 • DECEMBER 2010 J OURNAL OF PRIMARY HEALTH CARE 345

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!