08.10.2015 Views

Chapter 128

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

2114 PART 6 ■ Specific Considerations<br />

if inadequate information was given, then the doctor may be held<br />

to be negligent. Thus, if inadequate information about risk is<br />

given, and the child suffers harm, then the parents may claim that<br />

the doctor is responsible because they never gave “informed<br />

consent” in the first place. The question therefore is how closely<br />

does the law match the ethical description of informed consent<br />

given above?<br />

The Different Legal Standards of Disclosure<br />

The reality is that different legal systems in different countries<br />

utilize different standards of disclosure. There are three different<br />

standards:<br />

The professional standard test is the standard of disclosure that<br />

the profession would be expected to tell the patient. Thus, based<br />

on the old English case of Bolam, 42 a doctor would not be guilty of<br />

negligence if he acted in accordance with a practice accepted as<br />

proper by a responsible body of medical opinion skilled in that<br />

particular art. The same test applies to the disclosure of risk. If a<br />

responsible body of medical opinion would not have disclosed<br />

what was omitted by the defendant the doctor would not be found<br />

guilty of negligence. Thus, even a significant minority of doctors<br />

in agreement will leave the plaintiff in difficulties.<br />

The patient standard, on the other hand, can be subdivided into<br />

two: a particular patient standard and a prudent patient standard,<br />

corresponding to subjective or objective standards. The particular<br />

patient (subjective) test defines what the actual patient would have<br />

done if notified of all relevant facts. This test suffers from the<br />

necessity of hindsight, and since the relevant facts only exist in the<br />

mind of the individual, an accusation is very hard to refute. It is,<br />

however, a desirable standard insofar as it embodies personal<br />

factors, including many that are nonmedical, which might affect<br />

a particular person’s decision. The prudent patient test requires<br />

the plaintiff to establish that a reasonable person would not have<br />

undergone a recommended procedure after having been advised<br />

of all significant risks. This also is problematic, as it is impossible<br />

to define what a reasonable person is, specific to each case.<br />

However, it appears fair to both sides in that a reasonable doctor<br />

and a reasonable patient are meeting on comparable terms. 43<br />

The Bolam test for medical negligence still carries significant<br />

weight in the United Kingdom. That is, “a doctor is not negligent<br />

if he acts in accordance with a practice accepted at the time as<br />

proper by a responsible body of medical opinion.” This ruling<br />

arose out of a case in 1957. Bolam, who consented to electroconvulsive<br />

treatment but suffered fractures in the course of the<br />

treatment (he was not given any muscle relaxants), argued that he<br />

had not been informed of the risks. The judge held that the<br />

amount of information given had accorded with generally<br />

accepted medical practice and the case was dismissed. The Bolam<br />

test corresponds to the professional medical standard test—that<br />

“the doctor knows best.” This accords with the principles of<br />

benevolence and nonmaleficence: “do good and do no harm.”<br />

The professional standard test has been attacked by many,<br />

including some judges in the United Kingdom such as Lord<br />

Scarman. Although he would permit the medical experts to<br />

establish the standard of care in relation to diagnosis and treatment,<br />

44 he found it unacceptable in relation to informed consent.<br />

He has commented that the legal standard is, in effect, set by the<br />

medical profession. If a doctor can show that his advice or his<br />

treatment reached a standard of care which was accepted by a<br />

respectable and responsible body of medical opinion as adequate,<br />

he cannot be made liable in damages if anything goes wrong. It is<br />

a totally medical preposition erected into a working rule of law. 45<br />

Since then, the Bolam test, with respect to information<br />

disclosure, has been modified following the case of Bolitho. 46 In<br />

this case, it was decided that a doctor is not negligent if he acts<br />

in accordance with a practice rightly accepted at the time as<br />

proper by a responsible body of medical opinion. The key word<br />

here is “rightly.” In effect, this allows a court to decide if the<br />

“responsible body of medical opinion” is correct. It transfers the<br />

final decision from the medical profession to the legal system.<br />

However, it still remains that the legal doctrine of informed<br />

consent in the United Kingdom is primarily a law of disclosure<br />

based on a general obligation to exercise reasonable care by giving<br />

information.<br />

Giesen in turn states: 47<br />

“The law in most jurisdictions seeks to ensure the full and consistent<br />

protection of the patient’s rights … this goal requires that<br />

objective and judicially determined standards of care be imposed<br />

upon doctors. In relation to consent to medical treatment the primary<br />

value of individual autonomy implies that the informational<br />

needs of the particular patient must determine the legal standard<br />

of disclosure. In so far as English judges have privileged the medical<br />

profession, above all others, by unquestioningly ratifying its<br />

practices in relation to treatment and disclosure, they may be said<br />

to have abandoned their constitutionally mandated tasks of adjudication<br />

and the development of law on an objective basis. This<br />

position is at odds with that in most other common law countries<br />

and is notably isolated within the context of the European<br />

Community.”<br />

In other parts of the world, the “patient-based materiality risk<br />

standard” is well established. In the United States, the landmark<br />

case of Canterbury v. Spence 48 and in Australia the case of Rogers<br />

v. Whitaker 49 imply that doctors must disclose any material risk<br />

about a procedure before informed consent has been given. The<br />

important concept here is an understanding of the meaning of the<br />

word “material.” It implies that, provided knowledge of a particular<br />

risk will be important to the decision making process of the<br />

patient, then such a risk needs to be disclosed, irrespective of<br />

the likelihood of it occurring. This could mean anything from the<br />

simplest to the most life-threatening complication. The issue is<br />

how much importance the patient attaches to the risk of the<br />

complication occurring.<br />

RESEARCH IN CHILDREN<br />

Overview and General Considerations<br />

The issue of undertaking research in children raises many legal<br />

and ethical dilemmas. Apart from the fact that they are vulnerable<br />

to being used to further adult interests, questions such as what<br />

level of maturity is required to consent to a research proposal still<br />

arise. Furthermore, harm, pain, and distress may arise out of any<br />

research, including such simple procedures as taking blood<br />

samples.<br />

Research can conveniently be divided into therapeutic and<br />

nontherapeutic, although in many cases it may be difficult to<br />

differentiate the two. In therapeutic research it is probable (or<br />

at least the aim should be) that the research will directly benefit<br />

the patient. Nontherapeutic research, on the other hand, will<br />

not benefit that particular patient, although the results may be

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!