21.07.2016 Views

PENALTY

DBk0302s7Xm

DBk0302s7Xm

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

may be a long life in the hardest and most monotonous toil,<br />

without any of its alleviation or rewards—disbarred from<br />

all pleasant sights and sounds, and cut off from all earthly<br />

hope…….?” 39<br />

Decades later, a committee of the British Parliament concluded in<br />

1930 that the relative physical and psychological pains of execution<br />

are far preferable to the slow decay of body and spirit of life<br />

imprisonment:<br />

“A further alternative is to lengthen the sentence<br />

to the limit of life itself. . . . This is a death sentence<br />

where the inevitable end is reached by the imperceptible<br />

stages of institutional decay instead of by<br />

one full stroke.” 40<br />

RETHINKING THE THEORY OF DETERRENCE<br />

The logic of deterrence rests on the principle that persons people<br />

committing these crimes have motivations that influence their consideration<br />

of the possibility of death as a consequence of their act. There is<br />

strong and consistent social science evidence that persons contemplating<br />

murder tend to heavily undervalue the risks of punishment. They<br />

regard punishment as a distant possibility, and not one to be taken seriously.<br />

41 In some instances, the rewards and gratification from murder<br />

outweigh any risks of death, or even the certainty of death itself. 42<br />

Even in places with frequent and well-publicized executions, there<br />

is no scientific evidence that executions deter homicides marginally<br />

more than do lengthy incarceration prison sentences. 43<br />

39 John Stuart Mill, Collected Works, vol. 28 (London, Routledge, 1868), pp. 266-272.<br />

40 Sir Alexander Paterson, Report of the Committee on Capital Punishment (1930), pp. 484-487.<br />

41 See, for example, Kenneth Polk, When Men Kill: Scenarios of Masculine Violence (New York, Cambridge<br />

University Press, 1994).<br />

42 This can be observed both in the high number of people who commit suicide after killing<br />

before being arrested by police, and also in the acts of terrorism that result in certain death by<br />

the attacker. See, Scott Eliason, “Murder-suicide: a review of the recent literature”, Journal of the<br />

American Academy of Psychiatry and the Law Online, vol. 37 (2009): 371-376.<br />

43 Randi Hjalmarsson, “Does capital punishment have a ‘local’ deterrent effect on homicides?”<br />

American Law and Economics Review, vol. 11 (2009), pp. 310-334.<br />

A recent review of the empirical research on deterrence 44 , concluded<br />

that three preconditions of decision-making by criminal offenders<br />

are necessary for deterrence to be effective:<br />

1. Knowledge—Do offenders know and understand the implications<br />

of the law? Do they know which actions are criminalized<br />

and what will mitigate their culpability?<br />

2. Rationality—If so, will they allow that understanding to<br />

determine their conduct?<br />

3. Perceived net cost—If so, are they likely to choose compliance<br />

as the more beneficial option? Is the punishment worth<br />

avoiding? This in turn requires assessment of three concurrent<br />

probabilities: (a) the probability of being caught and convicted,<br />

(b) the likely severity of a sentence, and the marginal increases in<br />

severity for each level of punishment, and (c) the delay in reaching<br />

the final stage of the most severe punishment.<br />

The third precondition raises the most difficult challenges: assuming<br />

rationality in both perception and weighing of risks associated specifically<br />

with execution. In most instances, the risks are remote: Few<br />

murderers are caught, even fewer sentenced to death, and still fewer<br />

actually executed. 45 In the case of drug trafficking, its apparent high<br />

volume suggests that perceptions of risk are realistically low.<br />

For both murderers and drug traffickers, with detection and punishment<br />

uncertain if not unlikely, and with the payoffs of drug trafficking<br />

well exceeding conventional returns, the net cost hurdle is likely to<br />

defeat deterrence. Empirical research has shown that the calculus drug<br />

offenders apply in their decision making renders deterrence simply<br />

a component of their task to be managed and avoided. But it hardly<br />

changes how net costs are evaluated.<br />

There also are personal rewards that alter the rationality of decision<br />

making. Economic necessity, emotional rewards and other non-rational<br />

44 Paul Robinson and John Darley, “Does the criminal law deter?” Oxford Journal of Law, 24 (2004),<br />

p. 173.<br />

45 See, for example, Scott Phillips and Alena Simon, “Is the modern American death penalty a fatal<br />

lottery? Texas as a conservative test”, Laws, vol. 3 (2014), pp. 85-105, doi:10.3390/laws3010085.<br />

96 97

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!