22.05.2018 Views

Sean Burke The Death and Return of the Author : Criticism and Subjectivity in Barthes, Foucault and Derrida.

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

<strong>Foucault</strong> attempts <strong>the</strong> formidable task <strong>of</strong> present<strong>in</strong>g a history <strong>of</strong> thought with<strong>in</strong> which <strong>the</strong> role <strong>of</strong><br />

<strong>in</strong>dividual th<strong>in</strong>kers over some four hundred <strong>and</strong> fifty years <strong>of</strong> discourse is entirely subord<strong>in</strong>ate to<br />

impersonal forces. 1 <strong>The</strong> determ<strong>in</strong>ism that <strong>Foucault</strong> promulgates is, superficially at least, ak<strong>in</strong> to<br />

Marxist critique <strong>in</strong> that it is periodised <strong>in</strong>to self-regulat<strong>in</strong>g historical structures. <strong>The</strong> statements, <strong>the</strong><br />

texts, <strong>the</strong> philosophical systems <strong>and</strong> sciences <strong>of</strong> any given era will obey a prediscursive network<br />

<strong>of</strong> coherencies <strong>and</strong> rules <strong>of</strong> formation which constitutes <strong>the</strong> most fundamental level <strong>of</strong> knowledge.<br />

<strong>The</strong> similarities which we perceive <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> discourses <strong>of</strong> a particular era, <strong>and</strong> which we ra<strong>the</strong>r<br />

vaguely <strong>in</strong>terpret as <strong>the</strong> spirit or common purpose <strong>of</strong> an age, are, for <strong>Foucault</strong>, emanations <strong>of</strong> a<br />

strict, rigid, epistemological substrate. This substrate is not to be confused with zeitgeist or<br />

weltanschauung, which are simply its visible emanations, <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> form <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> atmosphere <strong>in</strong> which<br />

thought is conducted, or <strong>the</strong> community <strong>of</strong> moral, ethical <strong>and</strong> metaphysical perspectives at a<br />

particular time. So far from be<strong>in</strong>g a paradigm that has been superimposed upon an era, or an<br />

analytic reduction <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> mass <strong>of</strong> discourse, <strong>the</strong> epistemological arrangement is <strong>the</strong> ground <strong>and</strong><br />

possibility <strong>of</strong> thought itself, <strong>the</strong> potency <strong>of</strong> which <strong>the</strong> discourse <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> age is an actualisation. To<br />

this system <strong>of</strong> relations <strong>Foucault</strong> gave <strong>the</strong> name episteme; to <strong>the</strong> science <strong>of</strong> its recovery,<br />

'archaeology'.<br />

It is not <strong>the</strong> surface structures <strong>of</strong> history that are <strong>the</strong> object <strong>of</strong> archaeological research, but <strong>the</strong><br />

epistemological foundations upon which <strong>the</strong> great spectacle <strong>of</strong> Western discourse has been<br />

constructed. At this level, <strong>the</strong> role <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>dividual authors is no more than that <strong>of</strong> epistemic<br />

functionaries. Once aga<strong>in</strong> <strong>Foucault</strong>'s approach shows aff<strong>in</strong>ities with Marxist critique <strong>in</strong> that it sees<br />

ideas as <strong>the</strong> product ra<strong>the</strong>r than <strong>the</strong> motivation for historical change. But whilst many Marxists<br />

allow for a certa<strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong>terplay between impersonal forces <strong>and</strong> immanent subjectivity, Foucauldian<br />

archaeology presents <strong>the</strong> work <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>dividual th<strong>in</strong>kers as entirely determ<strong>in</strong>ed by <strong>the</strong> epistemic<br />

configuration. As <strong>Foucault</strong> writes <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Classical episteme:<br />

it was <strong>the</strong> sign system that l<strong>in</strong>ked all knowledge to a language, <strong>and</strong> sought to replace all<br />

languages with a system <strong>of</strong> artificial symbols <strong>and</strong> operations <strong>of</strong> a logical nature. At <strong>the</strong> level <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

history <strong>of</strong> op<strong>in</strong>ions, all this would appear, no doubt, as a tangled network <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>fluences <strong>in</strong> which<br />

<strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>dividual parts played by Hobbes, Berkeley, Leibniz, Condillac, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> 'Ideologues' would be<br />

revealed. But if we question Classical thought at <strong>the</strong> level <strong>of</strong> what, archaeologically, made it<br />

possible, we perceive that <strong>the</strong> dissociation <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> sign <strong>and</strong> resemblance <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> early seventeenth<br />

century caused <strong>the</strong>se new forms—probability, analysis, comb<strong>in</strong>ation, <strong>and</strong> universal language<br />

system—to emerge, not as successive <strong>the</strong>mes engender<strong>in</strong>g one ano<strong>the</strong>r or driv<strong>in</strong>g one ano<strong>the</strong>r<br />

out, but as a s<strong>in</strong>gle network <strong>of</strong> necessities. And it was this network that made possible <strong>the</strong><br />

<strong>in</strong>dividuals we term Hobbes, Berkeley, Hume, or Condillac. (63)<br />

Like <strong>Foucault</strong>'s first work, Madness <strong>and</strong> Civilization (1961), <strong>The</strong> Order <strong>of</strong> Th<strong>in</strong>gs accepts <strong>the</strong><br />

conventional demarcation <strong>of</strong> post-Medieval history <strong>in</strong>to <strong>the</strong> Renaissance, <strong>the</strong> Classical age, <strong>and</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> modern age. 2 Nor, <strong>of</strong> itself, is <strong>Foucault</strong>'s determ<strong>in</strong>ation <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> essential structures <strong>of</strong><br />

knowledge <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>se eras particularly radical. <strong>The</strong> Renaissance is seen to be constructed around<br />

<strong>the</strong> scholastic <strong>the</strong>ory <strong>of</strong> resemblances; <strong>the</strong> Classical age around <strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>ory <strong>of</strong> representation <strong>and</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> system <strong>of</strong> signs; <strong>the</strong> modern age to be compassed by <strong>the</strong> ethic <strong>of</strong> subjectivity. What<br />

dist<strong>in</strong>guishes <strong>Foucault</strong>'s treatment is <strong>the</strong> absolute <strong>and</strong> reciprocal impenetrability he assumes<br />

between <strong>the</strong>se eras, his refusal <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> possibility <strong>of</strong> any significant <strong>in</strong>fluence carry<strong>in</strong>g over from<br />

one episteme to ano<strong>the</strong>r. <strong>The</strong> epistemi are fully coherent with<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>mselves, <strong>and</strong> yet entirely<br />

discont<strong>in</strong>uous with each o<strong>the</strong>r. <strong>The</strong> homogeneity <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> episteme is <strong>the</strong>refore a factor <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

heterogeneity <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> epistemi, <strong>and</strong> vice versa. <strong>The</strong>re can be no thought <strong>of</strong> man <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> Classical<br />

era, as equally <strong>the</strong>re can be no thought with<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> modern age which is not, at base, th<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong><br />

man.3 Likewise, <strong>the</strong> episterne <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Renaissance is constituted by <strong>the</strong> impossibility <strong>of</strong> th<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong>g<br />

with<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> categories <strong>of</strong> representation, just as <strong>the</strong> Classical era is formed by <strong>the</strong> complete<br />

disappearance <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>ory <strong>of</strong> resemblances from its horizons.<br />

Consequently, just as <strong>the</strong> epistemic arrangement exercises absolute determ<strong>in</strong>ative power dur<strong>in</strong>g<br />

<strong>the</strong> era which it undergirds, so too, when it disappears, it disappears entirely, leav<strong>in</strong>g no residue<br />

but <strong>the</strong> remotest nostalgia for a lost order. It is here that <strong>The</strong> Order <strong>of</strong> Th<strong>in</strong>gs swerves signally<br />

from dialectical histories <strong>in</strong> that such models imply some conservation <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> forms <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

superseded era through <strong>the</strong> syn<strong>the</strong>sis <strong>of</strong> its contradictions, or <strong>the</strong> negation <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> negation. For<br />

<strong>Foucault</strong>, however, <strong>the</strong> hiatus is absolute, irresolvable, acausal. Each episteme is <strong>the</strong> complete<br />

cancellation <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> previous episteme. This po<strong>in</strong>t is axial, <strong>and</strong> all <strong>the</strong> more so <strong>in</strong> that it forms <strong>the</strong>

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!