22.05.2018 Views

Sean Burke The Death and Return of the Author : Criticism and Subjectivity in Barthes, Foucault and Derrida.

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

figures, many <strong>of</strong> which <strong>Derrida</strong> himself has taught us to read <strong>the</strong>re. Images <strong>of</strong> gardens, <strong>of</strong> suitable<br />

soil, <strong>of</strong> boundary, defence, enclosure, <strong>and</strong> cultivation do <strong>the</strong>ir work alongside <strong>the</strong> procedures <strong>of</strong><br />

rational enquiry: all <strong>of</strong> which express healthy constra<strong>in</strong>t, controlled growth, supervised<br />

development, <strong>in</strong> an economy <strong>of</strong> domestication which also defends (boe<strong>the</strong>ia) <strong>and</strong> nurtures that<br />

which is be<strong>in</strong>g tamed. On <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r side, <strong>Derrida</strong>'s figure <strong>of</strong> dissem<strong>in</strong>ation serves eloquently to<br />

mark writ<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>s<strong>of</strong>ar as it drifts, it rolls, (kul<strong>in</strong>deitai: 275e) exceeds domestication, breaks out <strong>of</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> closed <strong>and</strong> controlled spaces <strong>the</strong> dialogic forum, <strong>the</strong> ideal speech situation. However, what<br />

<strong>the</strong> text does not provide is a system <strong>of</strong> imagery configured on <strong>the</strong> axis <strong>of</strong> life/ death. Indeed, <strong>the</strong><br />

figures <strong>of</strong> roll<strong>in</strong>g, drift<strong>in</strong>g, <strong>of</strong> dissem<strong>in</strong>at<strong>in</strong>g express just as much animation—albeit <strong>in</strong> a wild,<br />

untrammelled <strong>and</strong> pr<strong>of</strong>ligate sense <strong>of</strong> liv<strong>in</strong>g, <strong>of</strong> be<strong>in</strong>g animate, <strong>of</strong> mov<strong>in</strong>g. Whilst <strong>the</strong> comparison<br />

<strong>of</strong> writ<strong>in</strong>g to pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g (Phaedrus, 275d) registers <strong>the</strong> fixed nature <strong>of</strong> written logoi,61 it is quickly<br />

succeeded—<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> same speech—by <strong>the</strong> image <strong>of</strong> drift<strong>in</strong>g. (Phaedrus, 275e) Far from be<strong>in</strong>g<br />

cadaverous or petrified, this w<strong>and</strong>er<strong>in</strong>g free-float<strong>in</strong>g energy places itself on <strong>the</strong> disreputable side<br />

<strong>of</strong> a dist<strong>in</strong>ction between two modes <strong>of</strong> vitality: one controlled, enclosed <strong>and</strong> cultivated; <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r,<br />

aleatory, wanton <strong>and</strong> w<strong>and</strong>er<strong>in</strong>g.<br />

<strong>Derrida</strong>, though, is determ<strong>in</strong>ed to discover <strong>the</strong> life/death opposition <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>se four Platonic pages,<br />

<strong>and</strong> it is no co<strong>in</strong>cidence that he beg<strong>in</strong>s to talk <strong>of</strong> writ<strong>in</strong>g substitut<strong>in</strong>g '<strong>the</strong> breathless sign for <strong>the</strong><br />

liv<strong>in</strong>g voice' (92) only when <strong>The</strong>uth has been boxed <strong>in</strong>to <strong>the</strong> corner <strong>of</strong> death:<br />

As a liv<strong>in</strong>g th<strong>in</strong>g, logos issues from a fa<strong>the</strong>r. <strong>The</strong>re is thus for Plato no such th<strong>in</strong>g as a written<br />

th<strong>in</strong>g. <strong>The</strong>re is only a logos more or less<br />

alive, more or less distant from itself. Writ<strong>in</strong>g is not an <strong>in</strong>dependent order <strong>of</strong> signification; it is<br />

weakened speech, someth<strong>in</strong>g not completely dead: a liv<strong>in</strong>g-dead, a reprieved corpse, a deferred<br />

life, a semblance <strong>of</strong> breath. (143)<br />

Presumably this claim does not wish to be taken <strong>in</strong> any historical sense <strong>in</strong> seek<strong>in</strong>g to exploit <strong>the</strong><br />

idea <strong>of</strong> writ<strong>in</strong>g as eidolon, as Hadean shade <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> liv<strong>in</strong>g word, but <strong>the</strong> metaphoric <strong>in</strong>sistence<br />

could be read as an attempt to have <strong>the</strong> Phaedrus say what a Rousseau would have it say as<br />

much as what a Socrates or Plato did say. Certa<strong>in</strong>ly, <strong>the</strong> missions <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Phaedrus are no more<br />

romantic than <strong>the</strong>y are <strong>in</strong> quest <strong>of</strong> a noble primitivism embodied <strong>in</strong> speech: Plato's text does not<br />

export <strong>the</strong> network 'speech/writ<strong>in</strong>g, life/ death' <strong>in</strong>to western conceptuality so much as <strong>Derrida</strong>'s<br />

mythological excursus imports a Rousseauian sense <strong>of</strong> writ<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>to a dialogue which is concerned<br />

with <strong>the</strong> ethical <strong>and</strong> epistemological status <strong>of</strong> discursive media. Indeed, <strong>the</strong> Phaedrus condemns<br />

<strong>the</strong> spoken <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> same terms as <strong>the</strong> written. (Phaedrus, 277e) 62 Altoge<strong>the</strong>r banally, we shall<br />

f<strong>in</strong>d that statements are evaluated through <strong>the</strong> validity <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir logoi ra<strong>the</strong>r than <strong>the</strong>ir lexis, for <strong>the</strong>ir<br />

proximity to 'justice <strong>and</strong> honour <strong>and</strong> goodness'. (Phaedrus, 278a)<br />

A second area <strong>of</strong> difficulty <strong>in</strong> <strong>Derrida</strong>'s treatment <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> myth <strong>of</strong> writ<strong>in</strong>g centres on his identification<br />

<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Platonic view with <strong>the</strong> pronouncement <strong>of</strong> K<strong>in</strong>g Thamus. Talk<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> play <strong>of</strong> signification<br />

set <strong>in</strong> motion by <strong>the</strong> pharmakon, <strong>Derrida</strong> asserts: 'It is precisely this ambiguity that Plato, through<br />

<strong>the</strong> mouth <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> K<strong>in</strong>g, attempts to master, to dom<strong>in</strong>ate by <strong>in</strong>sert<strong>in</strong>g its def<strong>in</strong>ition <strong>in</strong>to simple, clearcut<br />

oppositions'. (103: my emphasis) <strong>The</strong> significance <strong>of</strong> this statement to <strong>the</strong> essay's construal <strong>of</strong><br />

authorial <strong>in</strong>tention need hardly be underl<strong>in</strong>ed. <strong>The</strong> 'voice' <strong>of</strong> a mythic character is given by <strong>Derrida</strong><br />

as an authorial 'voice': Thamus becomes <strong>the</strong> place from which <strong>the</strong> Platonic wisdom speaks. In<br />

trac<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>tricate cha<strong>in</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> pharmakon, <strong>Derrida</strong> neglects to consider <strong>the</strong> vertig<strong>in</strong>ous play <strong>of</strong><br />

signatures <strong>in</strong> this scene: <strong>in</strong> a dialogue written by Plato, K<strong>in</strong>g Thamus 'speaks' <strong>the</strong> judgement on<br />

writ<strong>in</strong>g with<strong>in</strong> a myth which is 'spoken' by Socrates. Narrative, mimetic <strong>and</strong> technical<br />

considerations militate aga<strong>in</strong>st declar<strong>in</strong>g that it is Socrates or Plato who speaks <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> K<strong>in</strong>g's<br />

words; <strong>and</strong> all this before one even beg<strong>in</strong>s to ask how mythic logoi accommodate to dialectical<br />

logoi <strong>in</strong> a tale whose authorship is immediately challenged by Phaedrus. (Phaedrus, 275b) Even<br />

were <strong>the</strong> judgement <strong>of</strong> Thamus shown to be <strong>in</strong> consort with <strong>the</strong> Socratic viewpo<strong>in</strong>t—a task which<br />

is rendered counter<strong>in</strong>tuitive when weighed aga<strong>in</strong>st that recapitulatory statement at 278b—d<br />

(which we shall consider <strong>in</strong> due course)—<strong>Derrida</strong> would still be called upon to balance <strong>the</strong><br />

delicate scales <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Socratic problem.63 Moreover, <strong>the</strong> first axiom <strong>of</strong> judgement established by<br />

Thamus is <strong>in</strong> clear contradiction with what <strong>Derrida</strong> justly takes to be a central argument <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

Phaedrus. <strong>The</strong> strongest objection Plato makes to writ<strong>in</strong>g specifies its separation <strong>of</strong> a discourse<br />

from <strong>the</strong> subject who produced it, a separation which orphans a piece <strong>of</strong> writ<strong>in</strong>g, leaves it helpless<br />

before <strong>in</strong>competent, malign <strong>and</strong> abusive readers: '<strong>the</strong> composition . . . drifts all over <strong>the</strong> place . .<br />

. it doesn't know how to address <strong>the</strong> right people, <strong>and</strong> not to address <strong>the</strong> wrong. (Phaedrus,

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!