17.12.2012 Views

Art in its Time: Theories and Practices of Modern Aesthetics

Art in its Time: Theories and Practices of Modern Aesthetics

Art in its Time: Theories and Practices of Modern Aesthetics

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

THE AESTHETICS OF ANTI-AESTHETICS<br />

his <strong>in</strong>timate <strong>in</strong>volvement with the New York scene were certa<strong>in</strong>ly exposed to<br />

aesthetic ideas through conversation with that remarkable man. Nevertheless,<br />

with the exception <strong>of</strong> John Dewey’s <strong>Art</strong> as Experience <strong>of</strong> 1934, which had a certa<strong>in</strong><br />

<strong>in</strong>fluence on a number <strong>of</strong> pa<strong>in</strong>ters, <strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g Thomas Hart Benton <strong>and</strong> his student<br />

Jackson Pollock, 3 academic aesthetics has been <strong>of</strong> little <strong>in</strong>terest to modern<br />

artists <strong>in</strong> the United States.<br />

In this regard it is possible to compare the relations between aesthetics <strong>and</strong> the<br />

actual practice <strong>of</strong> the arts to those between the philosophy <strong>of</strong> science <strong>and</strong> modern<br />

physics <strong>and</strong> mathematics. While scientific figures like E<strong>in</strong>ste<strong>in</strong> <strong>and</strong> Hilbert were<br />

well versed <strong>in</strong> philosophy, the problems with which twentieth-century philosophers<br />

have struggled arose out <strong>of</strong> reflection on developments <strong>in</strong> science <strong>its</strong>elf, <strong>and</strong><br />

have been for the most part happily ignored by the vast majority <strong>of</strong> work<strong>in</strong>g<br />

scientists. Similarly, although artists have been un<strong>in</strong>terested <strong>in</strong> aesthetics, contemporary<br />

philosophers <strong>of</strong> art have largely found their problems—such as the<br />

place <strong>of</strong> expression <strong>in</strong> art, the nature <strong>of</strong> representation <strong>and</strong> the relation <strong>of</strong><br />

art to nature, <strong>and</strong>, above all, the def<strong>in</strong>ition <strong>of</strong> art—<strong>in</strong> this century’s art. Just as<br />

twentieth-century physics came to call <strong>in</strong>to question not only classical mechanics<br />

but also fundamental assumptions about the relation between theory <strong>and</strong> experiment<br />

<strong>and</strong> the nature <strong>of</strong> empirical evidence, so various modern art movements<br />

seem<strong>in</strong>gly collided with the underst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> art at the center <strong>of</strong> the tradition <strong>of</strong><br />

aesthetic theory.<br />

Stemm<strong>in</strong>g from Enlightenment <strong>and</strong> Romantic critical thought, this tradition<br />

located the essence <strong>of</strong> art <strong>in</strong> perceptual properties <strong>of</strong> the artistic object—<strong>its</strong> ability<br />

to evoke an “aesthetic experience” <strong>in</strong> the viewer, thanks to <strong>its</strong> “<strong>in</strong>tr<strong>in</strong>sic<br />

perceptual <strong>in</strong>terest,” what Clive Bell called <strong>its</strong> possession <strong>of</strong> “significant form.”<br />

Given this orientation, aesthetic theory could absorb the abstract art that<br />

appeared <strong>in</strong> the first decades <strong>of</strong> the twentieth century, despite <strong>its</strong> challenge to<br />

artistic convention, without much difficulty. Stiffer tests were posed by various<br />

anti-art movements, by the readymade, by the Pop appropriation <strong>of</strong> commercial<br />

imagery, by aspects <strong>of</strong> M<strong>in</strong>imalism <strong>and</strong> by the Conceptualist near-disappearance<br />

<strong>of</strong> the art object <strong>its</strong>elf.<br />

While most philosophers <strong>of</strong> art simply kept their distance from contemporary<br />

developments, thus ma<strong>in</strong>ta<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g the irrelevance <strong>of</strong> their work to artists Newman<br />

had noted, a few responded theoretically to anti-art. The so-called <strong>in</strong>stitutional<br />

theory <strong>of</strong> art, represent<strong>in</strong>g an anti-aesthetic trend with<strong>in</strong> aesthetics, made <strong>its</strong><br />

appearance <strong>in</strong> 1964 <strong>in</strong> an article written by <strong>Art</strong>hur Danto under (so Danto said)<br />

the <strong>in</strong>fluence <strong>of</strong> Andy Warhol’s Stable Gallery show <strong>of</strong> that year, but reflect<strong>in</strong>g<br />

issues raised much earlier by Marcel Duchamp. 4 George Dickie produced his<br />

3 See Stewart Buettner, “John Dewey <strong>and</strong> the visual arts <strong>in</strong> America,” The Journal <strong>of</strong> <strong>Aesthetics</strong> <strong>and</strong><br />

<strong>Art</strong> Criticism 33 (1975), pp. 381–91. Dewey’s <strong>in</strong>troduction to Alex<strong>and</strong>er Dorner’s The Way Beyond<br />

‘<strong>Art</strong>’: The Work <strong>of</strong> Herbert Bayer (New York: Wittenborn, Schultz, 1947), dedicated to him, provides<br />

another example <strong>of</strong> that philosopher’s contact with the art world.<br />

4 <strong>Art</strong>hur Danto, “The artworld,” Journal <strong>of</strong> Philosophy 61:19 (1964), pp. 571–84.<br />

120

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!