17.12.2012 Views

Art in its Time: Theories and Practices of Modern Aesthetics

Art in its Time: Theories and Practices of Modern Aesthetics

Art in its Time: Theories and Practices of Modern Aesthetics

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

5<br />

THE RATIONALIZATION<br />

OF ART<br />

“We are <strong>in</strong> the presence <strong>of</strong> a work <strong>of</strong> art only when it has no preponderant<br />

<strong>in</strong>strumental use, <strong>and</strong> when <strong>its</strong> technical <strong>and</strong> rational organization are not preem<strong>in</strong>ent.”<br />

1 These words seem self-evident to their author, George Kubler,<br />

because they constitute a restatement <strong>of</strong> a fundamental conception <strong>of</strong> modern<br />

aesthetics. The most celebrated early appearance <strong>of</strong> this conception is Kant’s, <strong>in</strong><br />

the Critique <strong>of</strong> Judgment <strong>of</strong> 1791. By ty<strong>in</strong>g the idea <strong>of</strong> “aesthetic experience” to<br />

“dis<strong>in</strong>terestedness” Kant set aesthetic value <strong>in</strong> opposition both to morality <strong>and</strong><br />

to <strong>in</strong>strumental rationality. The aesthetic enjoyment <strong>of</strong> art (as <strong>of</strong> nature) is an<br />

end <strong>in</strong> <strong>its</strong>elf, requir<strong>in</strong>g no justification by reference to further purposes. For<br />

Kant, similarly, artistic production is “play, <strong>in</strong> other words, an occupation that is<br />

agreeable on <strong>its</strong> own account.” 2 It represents an exercise <strong>of</strong> personal autonomy,<br />

unconstra<strong>in</strong>ed by any external goal such as those enforced on the general run <strong>of</strong><br />

producers by the discipl<strong>in</strong>e <strong>of</strong> wage labor, or on their masters by other commercial<br />

<strong>in</strong>terests.<br />

This view was not only distant from the reality <strong>of</strong> artistic production, which if<br />

not “paid for accord<strong>in</strong>g to a def<strong>in</strong>ite st<strong>and</strong>ard” was (as it rema<strong>in</strong>s) a “mercenary<br />

occupation” to the extent that the artist could make it one. It was <strong>in</strong> contradiction<br />

with the actual use <strong>of</strong> art for a variety <strong>of</strong> moral, political, <strong>and</strong> commercial<br />

purposes from the Renaissance to the present day. What Kant’s writ<strong>in</strong>g<br />

expressed, however—<strong>and</strong> this is one <strong>of</strong> the reasons for <strong>its</strong> cont<strong>in</strong>u<strong>in</strong>g centrality to<br />

the discourse <strong>of</strong> aesthetics—was the idea <strong>of</strong> art as the embodiment <strong>of</strong> “spirit,” <strong>in</strong><br />

contrast to the “material,” that is, economic, orientation dom<strong>in</strong>ant <strong>in</strong> modern<br />

life. In Hegel’s characteristic terms, art is a way “<strong>of</strong> br<strong>in</strong>g<strong>in</strong>g to our m<strong>in</strong>ds <strong>and</strong><br />

express<strong>in</strong>g the Div<strong>in</strong>e, the deepest <strong>in</strong>terests <strong>of</strong> mank<strong>in</strong>d, <strong>and</strong> the most comprehensive<br />

truths <strong>of</strong> the spirit.” 3<br />

1 George Kubler, The Shape <strong>of</strong> <strong>Time</strong>: Remarks on the History <strong>of</strong> Th<strong>in</strong>gs (New Haven: Yale University<br />

Press, 1962), p. 16. The text cont<strong>in</strong>ues by associat<strong>in</strong>g with this idea another essential element <strong>of</strong><br />

the modern idea <strong>of</strong> art: “In short, a work <strong>of</strong> art is as useless as a tool is useful. Works <strong>of</strong> art are<br />

as unique <strong>and</strong> irreplaceable as tools are common <strong>and</strong> expendable.”<br />

2 Immanuel Kant, Critique <strong>of</strong> Judgment, tr. Werner S. Pluhar (Indianapolis: Hackett, 1987), p. 170.<br />

3 G. W. F. Hegel, <strong>Aesthetics</strong>. Lectures on F<strong>in</strong>e <strong>Art</strong>, tr. T. M. Knox (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1975),<br />

vol. 1, p. 7.<br />

74

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!