17.12.2012 Views

Art in its Time: Theories and Practices of Modern Aesthetics

Art in its Time: Theories and Practices of Modern Aesthetics

Art in its Time: Theories and Practices of Modern Aesthetics

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

It is only shallow people who do not judge by appearances.<br />

Oscar Wilde, The Picture <strong>of</strong> Dorian Gray<br />

Andy Warhol himself once expla<strong>in</strong>ed, <strong>in</strong> words close to Wilde’s, “If you want to<br />

know all about Andy Warhol, just look at the surface: <strong>of</strong> my pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>and</strong> films<br />

<strong>and</strong> me, <strong>and</strong> there I am. There’s noth<strong>in</strong>g beh<strong>in</strong>d it.” 1 This remark, whether<br />

taken as all too true or as coyly mislead<strong>in</strong>g, is <strong>its</strong>elf generally judged <strong>in</strong> a superficial<br />

way. Wilde’s aphorism may help us remember that it is a mode <strong>of</strong><br />

shallowness to be unable or unwill<strong>in</strong>g to explore the structure <strong>and</strong> content <strong>of</strong><br />

appearances. From this po<strong>in</strong>t <strong>of</strong> view, much <strong>of</strong> the consideration critics, art theorists,<br />

<strong>and</strong> philosophers have given Warhol’s work is superficial. F<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>g that<br />

work’s surfaces <strong>in</strong>sufficient, such th<strong>in</strong>kers either condemn it as evidence <strong>of</strong> cultural<br />

decl<strong>in</strong>e or seek to give it significance by sett<strong>in</strong>g it with<strong>in</strong> a framework <strong>of</strong><br />

theory that possesses depths <strong>in</strong>visible <strong>in</strong> the work <strong>its</strong>elf.<br />

This essay exam<strong>in</strong>es accounts <strong>of</strong> Warhol’s work, by a philosopher <strong>and</strong> three<br />

art historians, that seek significance for it <strong>in</strong> this way. I will argue that despite<br />

their differences <strong>and</strong> their many <strong>in</strong>terest<strong>in</strong>g features, they are all flawed <strong>in</strong> be<strong>in</strong>g<br />

critically shallow—I mean, shallow as criticism. I will suggest that we can do<br />

better, <strong>in</strong> some respects at least, by pay<strong>in</strong>g close attention to Warhol’s surfaces.<br />

To beg<strong>in</strong> with an em<strong>in</strong>ent example, the issue <strong>of</strong> the relation between surface<br />

<strong>and</strong> deep mean<strong>in</strong>g lies at the heart <strong>of</strong> the lesson the critic-philosopher <strong>Art</strong>hur<br />

Danto drew from Brillo Boxes, which Warhol exhibited at the Stable Gallery <strong>in</strong><br />

New York <strong>in</strong> 1964. Twenty-five years later, review<strong>in</strong>g Warhol’s postmortem retrospective<br />

at the Museum <strong>of</strong> <strong>Modern</strong> <strong>Art</strong>, Danto called him “the nearest th<strong>in</strong>g<br />

to a philosophical genius the history <strong>of</strong> art has produced.” This is because<br />

1 Gretchen Berg, “Andy: my true story,” Los Angeles Free Press (March 17, 1967), p. 3.<br />

9<br />

THE ANDY WARHOL OF<br />

PHILOSOPHY AND THE<br />

PHILOSOPHY OF<br />

ANDY WARHOL<br />

134

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!