04.02.2013 Views

The Routledge Dictionary of Literary Terms

The Routledge Dictionary of Literary Terms

The Routledge Dictionary of Literary Terms

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

238 Texture<br />

depend on the ambiguity <strong>of</strong> its contents,<br />

but rather on what could be called the<br />

stereographic plurality <strong>of</strong> the signifiers<br />

that weave it.’ <strong>The</strong> Text is ‘completely<br />

woven with quotations, references and<br />

echoes’. (5) ‘<strong>The</strong> Text...is read without<br />

the father’s signature.’ <strong>The</strong> author can<br />

only come back to the text as ‘a guest’ so<br />

to speak. ‘<strong>The</strong> Text can be read without its<br />

father’s guarantee: the restitution <strong>of</strong> the<br />

intertext paradoxically abolishes the concept<br />

<strong>of</strong> filiation’ (p. 78). So, a text read in<br />

the weave <strong>of</strong> texts no longer is anchored<br />

in the author. (6) <strong>The</strong> Text ‘asks the reader<br />

for an active collaboration’. <strong>The</strong> reader<br />

thus should produce the Text. (7) ‘<strong>The</strong><br />

Text is linked to enjoyment.’ In brief,<br />

Barthes sees the work as ‘closed’ and the<br />

text as ‘open’. Many literary critics have<br />

subsequently been influenced by the work<br />

<strong>of</strong> Foucault and Derrida on the status and<br />

composition <strong>of</strong> both text and the text.<br />

See also TEXTURE.<br />

See Edward Said, <strong>The</strong> World, the Text<br />

and the Critic (1991); Stanley Fish, Is<br />

<strong>The</strong>re a Text in This Class? (1980); Roland<br />

Barthes, ‘From work to text’ in Josue V.<br />

Harari (ed.), Textual Strategies (1979);<br />

Ge<strong>of</strong>frey Hartman, Saving the Text (1983).<br />

AAAC<br />

Texture Strictly, the word texture<br />

when applied to language, describes the<br />

tactile images employed to represent various<br />

physical surfaces, but by extension<br />

has come to mean the representation in<br />

words <strong>of</strong> all physical phenomena. <strong>The</strong><br />

widespread use <strong>of</strong> the term is based on the<br />

assumption that words have an expressive<br />

or simulative aspect which helps to illustrate<br />

their meanings more immediately.<br />

This belief in the onomatopoeic properties<br />

<strong>of</strong> language has not always gone<br />

unchallenged, but the existence <strong>of</strong> techniques<br />

for producing particular sensory<br />

effects in the reader is undisputed, and it<br />

is thus possible to describe the texture <strong>of</strong><br />

language in terms <strong>of</strong> either <strong>of</strong> the means<br />

used or the effects obtained. Assonance<br />

(identity <strong>of</strong> vowel sounds), consonance<br />

(identity <strong>of</strong> consonant sounds) and alliteration<br />

(repetition <strong>of</strong> initial consonants)<br />

may each be used to produce such effects<br />

as cacophony (a sense <strong>of</strong> strain in pronunciation)<br />

or euphony (a sense <strong>of</strong> ease in<br />

pronunciation). All are exemplified in<br />

Alexander Pope’s famous exercise ‘An<br />

Essay in Criticism’:<br />

When Ajax strives some rock’s vast<br />

weight to throw,<br />

<strong>The</strong> line too labours, and the words<br />

move slow;<br />

Not so when swift Camilla scours the<br />

plain,<br />

Flie o’er th’unbending corn, and skims<br />

along the main.<br />

Samuel Johnson, however, attempting to<br />

prove that the mind governs the ear and<br />

not the reverse, quotes more lines with<br />

similar textural qualities and demonstrates<br />

quite convincingly that not even<br />

‘the greatest master <strong>of</strong> numbers can fix<br />

the principles <strong>of</strong> representative harmony’<br />

(Life <strong>of</strong> Pope, 1779).<br />

Many other critical theorists from<br />

Aristotle to I. A. Richards have disputed<br />

the possibility <strong>of</strong> any natural connection<br />

between the sounds <strong>of</strong> any language,<br />

and the things signified. Richards in <strong>The</strong><br />

Philosophy <strong>of</strong> Rhetoric (1936) asks:<br />

what resemblance or natural connection<br />

can there be between the semantic<br />

and phonetic elements in the morpheme?<br />

One is a sound the other a<br />

reference. Is (fl-) {in flicker, flash,<br />

flare} really like ‘moving light’ in any<br />

way in which (si-) or (gi-) is not? Is<br />

that not like asking whether the taste<br />

<strong>of</strong> turkey is like growing in some way<br />

that the taste <strong>of</strong> mint is not?

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!