22.08.2013 Views

Legitimate use of military force against state-sponsored - Air University

Legitimate use of military force against state-sponsored - Air University

Legitimate use of military force against state-sponsored - Air University

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

The term collective self-defense is not defined in the UN Charter. Customary<br />

international law and the practice <strong>of</strong> <strong>state</strong>s spell out the conditions necessary to exercise lawful<br />

collective self-defense. All the conditions for the exercise <strong>of</strong> legitimate individual self-defense,<br />

as described in chapter 4, are requirements for collective self-defense.<br />

Some scholars argue that States must satisfy an additional condition if collective selfdefense<br />

is to be legitimate. They imply that an individual and collective action differ in an<br />

essential way by asking: What is the unique condition that authorizes a third party to intervene in<br />

a dispute in support <strong>of</strong> another <strong>state</strong> that is the object <strong>of</strong> an actual or imminent armed attack?<br />

Three schools <strong>of</strong> thought have emerged on this point. The first holds that a <strong>state</strong> has no<br />

legal right <strong>of</strong> collective self-defense separate from individual self-defense. The late Hans Kelsen,<br />

former pr<strong>of</strong>essor <strong>of</strong> law at the <strong>University</strong> <strong>of</strong> California at Berkeley, is the chief proponent <strong>of</strong> this<br />

view. He asserts that self-defense “is a right <strong>of</strong> the attacked or threatened… <strong>state</strong>, and no other.” 8<br />

If several <strong>state</strong>s are acting in collective self-defense, then for them to do so each must be acting<br />

in its own individual self-defense. States unable to claim in their own right to be acting in their<br />

individual self-defense—although they may have an alliance relationship with the victim <strong>state</strong> or<br />

a strong national interest in the matter—cannot act in support <strong>of</strong> another <strong>state</strong>; collective selfdefense<br />

can never be more than the sum <strong>of</strong> <strong>state</strong>s acting in their individual self-defense. Julius<br />

Stone, Australian jurisprudent on the law <strong>of</strong> <strong>force</strong>, summed up this position in these words:<br />

“Under general international law, a State has no right <strong>of</strong> self-defense in respect <strong>of</strong> an armed<br />

attack upon a third State. “ 9<br />

A second school <strong>of</strong> thought, whose chief spokesman is D. W. Bowett, holds that “the<br />

right <strong>of</strong> self-defence is available only to a <strong>state</strong> which defends its own substantive rights.” 10 This<br />

school is less restrictive than the Kelsen school but it is not without strict limitations. Although<br />

Bowett does not believe that a <strong>state</strong> must be able to assert individual self-defense to participate in<br />

a collective self-defense action, he does believe that a close nexus must exist between the<br />

assisting and victimized <strong>state</strong>. He refers to this relationship as an interdependence <strong>of</strong> the<br />

securities <strong>of</strong> the <strong>state</strong>s.<br />

Bowett believes that a preexisting collective self-defense treaty arrangement is a<br />

prerequisite, but—and this is a critically important but—he finds that simply concluding a<br />

collective self-defense treaty will not suffice. 11 Rather, the interests <strong>of</strong> the attacked <strong>state</strong> must be<br />

“so intrinsically bound up with the territorial integrity and political independence <strong>of</strong> another<br />

State that the defence by the latter State <strong>of</strong> the former is truly ‘self-defence.” 12<br />

Bowett has identified three relevant factors in making this determination: geographical,<br />

political, and strategic-economic proximity. 13 These factors are weighed to answer the only<br />

important question: “Whether an attack upon one <strong>state</strong> in fact threatens the security <strong>of</strong> the<br />

other.’’ 14 If this test cannot be satisfied, then collective self-defense is illegitimate.’ 15<br />

The Bowett school believes that collective self-defense must be interpreted narrowly,<br />

otherwise the Charter system would be jeopardized. He writes,

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!