13.03.2014 Views

2013 Annual Report - Jesus College - University of Cambridge

2013 Annual Report - Jesus College - University of Cambridge

2013 Annual Report - Jesus College - University of Cambridge

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

THEOLOGY I <strong>Jesus</strong> <strong>College</strong> <strong>Annual</strong> <strong>Report</strong> <strong>2013</strong> 39<br />

as the divine Word and Wisdom, or ‘plan’,<br />

by whom all things are made. This is how it<br />

is possible to speak <strong>of</strong> us being ‘chosen in<br />

him before the foundation <strong>of</strong> the world’<br />

(Ephesians 1:4).<br />

By the time <strong>of</strong> Thomas Aquinas, this<br />

identification between Christ and the divine<br />

ideas has become so obvious that he can say<br />

‘whoever denies the existence <strong>of</strong> the ideas<br />

is an infidel, because he denies the<br />

existence <strong>of</strong> the Son’. These theological<br />

developments seem to resolve some <strong>of</strong> the<br />

classical problems about the ontological<br />

status and location <strong>of</strong> the forms, but other<br />

problems remain in new forms: Are there<br />

as many ideas as there are things or more?<br />

And if the latter, why are some realised<br />

rather than others?<br />

Despite these questions the theory <strong>of</strong> the<br />

divine ideas remained central not just to<br />

Christian philosophy but also to Christian<br />

piety and spirituality well into the middle<br />

ages. However, the rediscovery <strong>of</strong> Aristotle<br />

in the thirteenth century, brought the<br />

problems with the theory to the surface<br />

once again. On the one hand there were<br />

theological conservatives who understood<br />

the Augustinian tradition in a hyper-realist<br />

way, so that the ideas seem to become<br />

quasi-autonomous substances again.<br />

On the other, there were the Aristotelian<br />

radicals who tended towards nominalism,<br />

regarding forms as simply linguistic<br />

constructs and denying any talk <strong>of</strong> ideas<br />

in God as compromising the divine<br />

simplicity.<br />

Despite the efforts <strong>of</strong> Thomas Aquinas<br />

and others to avoid these extremes, the<br />

nominalist position had become dominant<br />

by the latter middle ages and the theory <strong>of</strong><br />

the divine ideas had begun to fade from<br />

theological consciousness. The most<br />

significant consequence <strong>of</strong> this fading <strong>of</strong><br />

the divine ideas was a new stress upon the<br />

divine will. If God does not create according<br />

to the eternally existing pattern <strong>of</strong> his own<br />

being, then the only answer to questions<br />

such as why did God create this or that<br />

must be simply that he wills it.<br />

It seems that whereas early Christian<br />

theologians had used the divine ideas to<br />

argue for the freedom <strong>of</strong> creation,<br />

according to the model <strong>of</strong> an artist, in the<br />

later middle ages the rejection <strong>of</strong> the divine<br />

ideas led to a more extreme voluntarist view<br />

<strong>of</strong> this freedom in terms <strong>of</strong> the arbitrariness<br />

<strong>of</strong> divine will. The subsequent rise <strong>of</strong><br />

voluntarism would have considerable<br />

effects, not only upon the understanding <strong>of</strong><br />

God, but also on the modern view <strong>of</strong> human<br />

freedom.<br />

And yet this was not the end <strong>of</strong> the road<br />

for the divine ideas. The question arose<br />

again in the continental rationalist tradition<br />

with the celebrated debate over grace<br />

and freedom between the Cartesian<br />

philosophers Malebranche and Arnaud in<br />

the 1680s. By this point a more static,<br />

mathematical view <strong>of</strong> the divine ideas had<br />

made their relation to human ideas more<br />

problematic. While Malebranche defended<br />

a hyper-realist account <strong>of</strong> the divine ideas<br />

but rejected innate human ideas, Leibniz<br />

took up the discussion arguing in favour <strong>of</strong><br />

the divine ideas and innate human ideas,<br />

against the empiricism <strong>of</strong> Locke. Closer to<br />

home, the mature Coleridge, influenced<br />

both by German idealism and the earlier<br />

<strong>Cambridge</strong> Platonists, regarded Locke’s<br />

rejection <strong>of</strong> the divine ideas as the death <strong>of</strong><br />

the ‘spiritual Platonic old England’.<br />

Coleridge’s account <strong>of</strong> the divine ideas was<br />

more thoroughly Trinitarian than Leibniz,<br />

and also more poetic rather than<br />

mathematical. For Coleridge the Christian<br />

Platonism <strong>of</strong> the divine ideas enabled him<br />

to move beyond the Hobbesian materialism<br />

<strong>of</strong> Hartley and Priestly which he had<br />

embraced during his Unitarian phase at<br />

<strong>Jesus</strong>, while also supporting his realist<br />

understanding <strong>of</strong> the creative powers <strong>of</strong> the<br />

imagination. Coleridge’s philosophy was<br />

itself significant in shaping the antiutilitarian<br />

strand <strong>of</strong> British social criticism<br />

in the nineteenth century which originally<br />

led me into this project. The story <strong>of</strong> the<br />

divine ideas is then a long and complex one,<br />

which tells us as much about our<br />

understanding <strong>of</strong> what it is to be human as<br />

it may or may not do about God.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!