13.11.2014 Views

proofs

proofs

proofs

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

114 Sets, functions, and the continuum hypothesis<br />

Next we assume c = ℵ 1 . Consider the set D ⊆ C of complex numbers<br />

p + iq with rational real and imaginary part. Since for each p the set<br />

{p + iq : q ∈ Q} is countable, we find that D is countable. Furthermore,<br />

D is a dense set in C: Every open disk in the complex plane contains some<br />

point of D. Let {z α : 0 ≤ α < ω 1 } be a well-ordering of C. We shall<br />

now construct a family {f β : 0 ≤ β < ω 1 } of ℵ 1 -many distinct analytic<br />

functions such that<br />

f β (z α ) ∈ D whenever α < β. (1)<br />

Any such family satisfies the condition (P 0 ). Indeed, each point z ∈ C has<br />

some index, say z = z α . Now, for all β > α, the values {f β (z α )} lie in<br />

the countable set D. Since α is a countable ordinal number, the functions<br />

f β with β ≤ α will contribute at most countably further values f β (z α ), so<br />

that the set of all values {f β (z α )} is likewise at most countable. Hence, if<br />

we can construct a family {f β } satisfying (1), then the second part of the<br />

theorem is proved.<br />

The construction of {f β } is by transfinite induction. For f 0 we may take<br />

any analytic function, for example f 0 = constant. Suppose f β has already<br />

been constructed for all β < γ. Since γ is a countable ordinal, we may<br />

reorder {f β : 0 ≤ β < γ} into a sequence g 1 , g 2 , g 3 , . . .. The same reordering<br />

of {z α : 0 ≤ α < γ} yields a sequence w 1 , w 2 , w 3 , . . .. We shall<br />

now construct a function f γ satisfying for each n the conditions<br />

f γ (w n ) ∈ D and f γ (w n ) ≠ g n (w n ). (2)<br />

The second condition will ensure that all functions f γ (0 ≤ γ < ω 1 ) are<br />

distinct, and the first condition is just (1), implying (P 0 ) by our previous<br />

argument. Notice that the condition f γ (w n ) ≠ g n (w n ) is once more a<br />

diagonalization argument.<br />

To construct f γ , we write<br />

f γ (z) := ε 0 + ε 1 (z − w 1 ) + ε 2 (z − w 1 )(z − w 2 )<br />

+ ε 3 (z − w 1 )(z − w 2 )(z − w 3 ) + . . ..<br />

If γ is a finite ordinal, then f γ is a polynomial and hence analytic, and we<br />

can certainly choose numbers ε i such that (2) is satisfied. Now suppose γ<br />

is a countable ordinal, then<br />

f γ (z) =<br />

∞∑<br />

ε n (z − w 1 ) · · · (z − w n ). (3)<br />

n=0<br />

Note that the values of ε m (m ≥ n) have no influence on the value f γ (w n ),<br />

hence we may choose the ε n step by step. If the sequence (ε n ) converges<br />

to 0 sufficiently fast, then (3) defines an analytic function. Finally, since<br />

D is a dense set, we may choose this sequence (ε n ) so that f γ meets the<br />

requirements of (2), and the proof is complete.<br />

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!