26.12.2014 Views

Paul Grice and the philosophy of language

Paul Grice and the philosophy of language

Paul Grice and the philosophy of language

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

PAUL GRICE AND THE PHILOSOPHY OF LANGUAGE 555<br />

dered in a way licensed by a system <strong>of</strong> rules (syntactical<br />

rules), <strong>and</strong><br />

(3) X means "p" in virtue <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> particular meanings <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

elements in X, <strong>the</strong>ir order <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir syntactical structure. 67<br />

<strong>Grice</strong>'s unhappiness with (V) derives from <strong>the</strong> existence <strong>of</strong> conventional<br />

implicatures. 6s Recall that <strong>Grice</strong> does not want to allow <strong>the</strong> sorts <strong>of</strong><br />

implications that result from <strong>the</strong> use <strong>of</strong> words such as 'but', 'yet', 'still',<br />

'even', <strong>and</strong> 'moreover', to count as part <strong>of</strong> what is said. For example, if<br />

U (sincerely <strong>and</strong> nonironically) utters <strong>the</strong> sentence 'She is poor but she is<br />

honest', U does not say that <strong>the</strong>re is some sort <strong>of</strong> contrast between<br />

poverty <strong>and</strong> honesty (or between her poverty <strong>and</strong> her honesty). Ra<strong>the</strong>r, U<br />

performs a "central speech act", by which U says that she is poor <strong>and</strong> she<br />

is honest, <strong>and</strong> performs in addition a "noncentral speech act", by which<br />

U conventionally implicates some sort <strong>of</strong> attitude toward what is said.<br />

Putting toge<strong>the</strong>r what U says <strong>and</strong> what U conventionally implicates we<br />

get what U conventionally means (see Fig. 2). So for <strong>Grice</strong>, at best <strong>the</strong><br />

three conditions in (V) define ~by uttering X, U conventionally meant that<br />

p~ ra<strong>the</strong>r than ~by uttering X, U said that p~.<br />

<strong>Grice</strong> goes no fur<strong>the</strong>r in Studies. In short, he leaves us with <strong>the</strong> nontrivial<br />

task <strong>of</strong> separating what U says <strong>and</strong> what U conventionally implicates. This<br />

may seem like a ra<strong>the</strong>r disappointing terminus. The more one reflects on<br />

his work, <strong>the</strong> more one feels that <strong>the</strong> notion <strong>of</strong> what is said is for <strong>Grice</strong><br />

a fundamentally important notion in <strong>philosophy</strong>. If this or that philosopher<br />

is unclear about what he is saying (as opposed to what he or she is<br />

implicating) <strong>the</strong>n that philosopher is liable to make all sorts <strong>of</strong> mistakes,<br />

as is borne out, <strong>Grice</strong> thinks, by <strong>the</strong> crude way in which, for instance <strong>the</strong><br />

Causal Theory <strong>of</strong> Perception <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Theory <strong>of</strong> Descriptions have been<br />

written <strong>of</strong>f by philosophers concerned with <strong>the</strong> nuances <strong>of</strong> ordinary <strong>language</strong>.<br />

Fur<strong>the</strong>rmore, not until what is said <strong>and</strong> what is conventionally<br />

67 It is clear that condition (3) must ultimately make reference to applied timeless meaning<br />

ra<strong>the</strong>r than timeless meaning. In <strong>Grice</strong>'s initial discussion <strong>of</strong> saying (pp. 87-88), <strong>the</strong> suggested<br />

definiens makes reference to what X means (timeless meaning) ra<strong>the</strong>r than to what X meant<br />

here (applied timeless meaning). But suppose X has "q" as well as "p" as one <strong>of</strong> its meanings.<br />

In principle, U might produce a token <strong>of</strong> X that means here "q" <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>reby conversationally<br />

implicate that p. Clearly <strong>Grice</strong> would not want to count this as a case <strong>of</strong> saying that p, <strong>and</strong><br />

this is probably why his later definiens (pp. 120) makes reference to applied timeless meaning.<br />

68 The nature <strong>of</strong> conditions (2) <strong>and</strong> (3) demonstrates just how wrong it is to claim that <strong>Grice</strong><br />

rejects <strong>the</strong> view that <strong>the</strong> meaning <strong>of</strong> a sentence is a function <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> meanings <strong>of</strong> its parts <strong>and</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong>ir syntactical arrangement. At <strong>the</strong> same time, it should be noted that charges <strong>of</strong> circularity<br />

sparked by <strong>the</strong> appearance in (V) <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> notion <strong>of</strong> word meaning are groundless: for <strong>Grice</strong>,<br />

word meaning is a species <strong>of</strong> incomplete utterance-type meaning, a notion which is itself to<br />

be analysed in terms <strong>of</strong> complete utterance-type meaning.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!