26.12.2014 Views

Paul Grice and the philosophy of language

Paul Grice and the philosophy of language

Paul Grice and the philosophy of language

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

514 STEPHEN NEALE<br />

proposition that is ei<strong>the</strong>r true or false. 7 So <strong>the</strong> view, perhaps borrowed<br />

from classical logic, that every use <strong>of</strong> an indicative sentence involves <strong>the</strong><br />

expression <strong>of</strong> a truth or a falsehood must be ab<strong>and</strong>oned.<br />

In his closing paragraph, Strawson suggests that <strong>the</strong> very idea <strong>of</strong> a <strong>the</strong>ory<br />

<strong>of</strong> meaning for a natural <strong>language</strong> based on classical logic is misguided:<br />

Nei<strong>the</strong>r Aristotelian nor Russellian rules give <strong>the</strong> exact logic <strong>of</strong> any expression <strong>of</strong> ordinary<br />

<strong>language</strong>; for ordinary <strong>language</strong> has no exact logic. (p. 344)<br />

Two years later, Strawson backed up this claim with his influential text<br />

Introduction to Logical Theory, in which, among o<strong>the</strong>r things, he launched<br />

an attack on <strong>the</strong> view that <strong>the</strong> logic <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> formal devices '&', 'v', 'D',<br />

'(Vx)', '(3x)', <strong>and</strong> '(tx)' captures <strong>the</strong> meanings <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> natural <strong>language</strong><br />

expressions '<strong>and</strong>', 'or', 'if', 'every', 'a', <strong>and</strong> '<strong>the</strong>'. A single example, modified<br />

somewhat, will suffice. If an utterer U asserts a sentence <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> form<br />

rp or q~, U will st<strong>and</strong>ardly be taken to imply that he has non truthfunctional<br />

grounds for <strong>the</strong> assertion, i.e., U will st<strong>and</strong>ardly be taken to<br />

imply that he does not know which <strong>of</strong> p <strong>and</strong> q is true. The ordinary<br />

<strong>language</strong> philosopher impressed by this observation might <strong>the</strong>n conclude<br />

that an utterance <strong>of</strong> rp or q7 in which this condition is not satisfied involves<br />

a misuse <strong>of</strong> <strong>language</strong>. It is, in some sense, part <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> meaning <strong>of</strong> r p or<br />

qT, that such a locution is used correctly only if <strong>the</strong> speaker does not know<br />

that p is true <strong>and</strong> does not know that q is true. If this condition is not<br />

satisfied, <strong>the</strong> utterance cannot be taken to express a truth. And so, <strong>the</strong><br />

ordinary <strong>language</strong> philosopher might conclude, it would be a serious mistake<br />

to suppose that <strong>the</strong> meaning <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> English word 'or' is given by <strong>the</strong><br />

semantics <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> logical particle 'v'; <strong>the</strong> semantics <strong>of</strong> 'v' is stipulated by<br />

<strong>the</strong> logician to be truth-functional, but <strong>the</strong> semantics <strong>of</strong> 'or' is determined<br />

by actual linguistic practice (use), which does not square with <strong>the</strong> logician's<br />

truth-functional analysis.<br />

<strong>Grice</strong> himself was an exceptional practitioner <strong>of</strong> ordinary <strong>language</strong><br />

<strong>philosophy</strong> <strong>and</strong> broadly sympa<strong>the</strong>tic to many <strong>of</strong> its aims <strong>and</strong> methods.<br />

Indeed, his own <strong>philosophy</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>language</strong> involves both an original refinement<br />

<strong>and</strong> an original critique <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> idea <strong>of</strong> meaning as use. In his first<br />

publication on meaning, his 1957 article 'Meaning' (Essay 14 <strong>of</strong> Studies),<br />

<strong>Grice</strong> expresses allegiance to <strong>the</strong> position that a <strong>the</strong>ory <strong>of</strong> meaning must,<br />

in some sense, be sensitive to use. In this paper, <strong>Grice</strong> presents his first<br />

attempts to say exactly what meaning is. It ought to be possible, he<br />

suggests, to explicate <strong>the</strong> meaning <strong>of</strong> an expression (or any o<strong>the</strong>r sign)<br />

7 My wording here is supposed to be neutral between (a) a proposition is expressed but it<br />

is nei<strong>the</strong>r true nor false, <strong>and</strong> (b) no proposition is expressed at all. Strawson is not consistent<br />

on this matter. For discussion, see Neale (1990) chap. 2.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!