10.07.2015 Views

richard-day-gramsci-is-dead

richard-day-gramsci-is-dead

richard-day-gramsci-is-dead

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

CONCLUSION: TAKING THE TALLYUtopian Social<strong>is</strong>m Then ... 127Indeed, with Landauer we find the full fruition of the anarch<strong>is</strong>tresponse to Marx and Engels’ critique of Utopian social<strong>is</strong>m. To thecharge that Utopian social<strong>is</strong>m seeks to emancipate ‘everyone at once’,the anarch<strong>is</strong>ts responded by elaborating a non-hegemonic theoryof social change that defied the revolution/reform dichotomy, thatdid not seek to free anyone at all but focused on how each of us, asindividuals and members of communities, must free ourselves, inan effort that cannot be expected to terminate in a final event ofrevolution. Objecting as much as the marx<strong>is</strong>ts did to rational<strong>is</strong>ticsocial experiments, but also rejecting marx<strong>is</strong>t ‘planning’, theanarch<strong>is</strong>ts evolved a theory and practice of non-rational<strong>is</strong>tic socialexperiments, an empirically-based search, if you will, of the evershiftingproblem-solution spaces offered by modern western societies.Finally, as I hope to have shown in th<strong>is</strong> chapter, anarch<strong>is</strong>m afterUtopian social<strong>is</strong>m was far from a m<strong>is</strong>h-mash of theories. Bakunin,Kropotkin and even Landauer saw themselves as politically motivatedsocial scient<strong>is</strong>ts. Individual intent, however, <strong>is</strong> a sorry category toinvoke in the context of a genealogical analys<strong>is</strong>. Instead, let us notethe ex<strong>is</strong>tence of a clear line of argumentation and political practice:the emerging theme of structural renewal guided by a logic of affinity,that was always already present in Godwin but had to go through thevic<strong>is</strong>situdes of a century of interaction with the hegemonic forms ofliberal<strong>is</strong>m and marx<strong>is</strong>m in order to find itself, as it were, as a theoryof social revolution d<strong>is</strong>tinct from both marx<strong>is</strong>t political revolutionand liberal political reform.Th<strong>is</strong> <strong>is</strong> a theory and practice that <strong>is</strong> decidedly topian rather thanUtopian. It <strong>is</strong> about the here and now, while not pretending therehas been no past nor that there will be no future. For, as Kropotkinso elegantly showed, the logic of affinity <strong>is</strong> ever-present, even in themost advanced forms of (post)industrial bureaucratic control. It <strong>is</strong>not a dream, but an actuality; not something to be yearned for, butsomething to be noticed in operation everywhere, at every moment ofevery <strong>day</strong>. Thus we can perhaps see that the ongoing battles betweenScientific and Utopian social<strong>is</strong>ms are driven by a narc<strong>is</strong>s<strong>is</strong>m of smalldifferences and a mutual ignorance of the advances made by theopposing tradition. And, as postmarx<strong>is</strong>ts and postanarch<strong>is</strong>ts havepointed out with respect to their own traditions, the theor<strong>is</strong>ts onboth sides of the classical debate were Utopian in a sense that did notoccur to either of them—that <strong>is</strong>, they all believed in the possibility of

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!