19.07.2013 Views

Emphatic Polarity and C in Spanish - Lear

Emphatic Polarity and C in Spanish - Lear

Emphatic Polarity and C in Spanish - Lear

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

EMPHATIC POLARITY AND C IN SPANISH<br />

(81) a. Bien le ordenaron que se callara.<br />

Well (they) CLDAT ordered that (s(he)) CL rema<strong>in</strong> silent<br />

‘But they did order him/her to rema<strong>in</strong> silent’<br />

b. Bien te han pedido que salgas de aquí.<br />

Well (they) CLDAT have asked that (you) leave<br />

‘But they did ask you to leave’<br />

c. Bien te prometí que todo se arreglaría.<br />

Well (I) CLDAT promised that everyth<strong>in</strong>g would be right<br />

‘But (I) did promise you that everyth<strong>in</strong>g would be right’<br />

Given the analysis I am propos<strong>in</strong>g, the ungrammaticality of the examples<br />

discussed <strong>in</strong> this section is expected, as it follows from the fact that bien,<br />

be<strong>in</strong>g quantificational <strong>in</strong> nature, is ruled out <strong>in</strong> syntactic structures where the<br />

CP doma<strong>in</strong> is filled by a variety of modality markers which have been<br />

claimed to occur <strong>in</strong> a high position <strong>in</strong> the sentence. Formulated <strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong>tuitive<br />

terms, what goes wrong <strong>in</strong> (75b), (76b), (80), etc. is the fact that they entail a<br />

rather contradictory modal value, so to speak. That is, one cannot order an<br />

action, or promise someth<strong>in</strong>g, etc., while at the same time stress<strong>in</strong>g the<br />

positive value of a propositional content. In order to illustrate this po<strong>in</strong>t <strong>in</strong> a<br />

more precise way, let us concentrate on impositive sentences like those <strong>in</strong><br />

(75)-(76). I assume, along the l<strong>in</strong>es of Zanutt<strong>in</strong>i’s (1997) proposal, among<br />

other authors, 56 that imperative clauses are subject to the syntactic<br />

requirement that the functional doma<strong>in</strong> express<strong>in</strong>g the illocutionary force of<br />

the sentence, namely the CP field, must be filled. As is well-known,<br />

imperative verbs have been argued to move to Force 0 , <strong>in</strong> order to check an<br />

[IMPERATIVE] mood feature hosted <strong>in</strong> ForceP (see Rizzi (1997)). In such<br />

a situation, it may be claimed that bien is prohibited due to an <strong>in</strong>tervention<br />

effect. In other words, <strong>in</strong> the ungrammatical examples alluded to, bien<br />

counts as a harmful <strong>in</strong>tervener which prevents the trace of the moved<br />

imperative from b<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>g. I will not engage <strong>in</strong> a more detailed account of this<br />

issue here.<br />

5. From bien to bien que: on the status of C<br />

In the preced<strong>in</strong>g sections, I have shown that <strong>Spanish</strong> has two options to<br />

stress the affirmative value of an assertion, namely, the bien strategy <strong>and</strong> the<br />

bien que strategy. I have also provided evidence support<strong>in</strong>g the claim that<br />

both options, as they convey an emphatic mean<strong>in</strong>g to the sentence, activate<br />

the doma<strong>in</strong> of the left periphery. I will now concentrate on the role played by<br />

56 See also Rivero (1994), <strong>and</strong> Rivero <strong>and</strong> Terzi (1995).<br />

141

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!