20.09.2015 Views

A-dictionary-of-greek-and-roman-antiquities-william-smith

A-dictionary-of-greek-and-roman-antiquities-william-smith

A-dictionary-of-greek-and-roman-antiquities-william-smith

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

UNIVERSITAS. UNIVERSITAS. 1215<br />

material things which form the ideal unit <strong>of</strong> his<br />

property.<br />

In this way we arrive at the correct notion <strong>of</strong> universitas <strong>of</strong> persons, which is the notion <strong>of</strong> a<br />

as a thing in itself, tlmt is, the whole is viewed<br />

pro diviso ; for division in this case is the same as<br />

making many wholes out <strong>of</strong> one whole. It is<br />

here assumed that the thing is in its nature di<br />

visible ; as a piece <strong>of</strong> l<strong>and</strong> which is capable <strong>of</strong><br />

being divided into parts.<br />

But there are parts <strong>of</strong> things corporeal which<br />

are essential to the constitution <strong>of</strong> the whole, so that<br />

the whole cannot be divided into parts without<br />

the destruction <strong>of</strong> its nature ; as a living animal<br />

for instance.<br />

Besides the corporeal parts into which a (cor<br />

poreal) thing is divisible, we may suppose incorpo<br />

real, ideal parts <strong>of</strong> a corporeal thing (Dig. 45. tit,<br />

3. s. 5). These parts are assumed fractions <strong>of</strong> a<br />

whole, not corporeal parts. If such a part is the<br />

object <strong>of</strong> thought, the whole corporeal thing is<br />

viewed pro indiviso : the corporeal object <strong>of</strong> the will<br />

is the thing, <strong>and</strong> the limitation <strong>of</strong> the will to a<br />

part, is merely intellectual. Thus several persons<br />

may be joint owners <strong>of</strong> a piece <strong>of</strong> undivided l<strong>and</strong>,<br />

but no one can say that any particular part belongs<br />

to him. The case just put is that <strong>of</strong> a corporeal<br />

whole <strong>and</strong> ideal parts. But the whole may<br />

be ideal <strong>and</strong> the parts corporeal : as when there<br />

Is a number <strong>of</strong> independent corporeal things, not<br />

materially connected, but they are intellectually<br />

connected so as to form in idea a whole : thus a<br />

flock <strong>of</strong> sheep is an ideal whole, <strong>and</strong> the several<br />

sheep are the independent corporeal things. The<br />

ideal whole is not composed <strong>of</strong> the several corporeal<br />

things, for an ideal whole cannot be composed <strong>of</strong><br />

corporeal parts ; but the ideal whole is a notion<br />

which is formed with reference to some particular<br />

purpose. It is necessary that the purpose <strong>of</strong> the<br />

several things shall not be different from <strong>and</strong> inde<br />

pendent <strong>of</strong> the general purpose for which the notion<br />

is formed, but subservient to it. Thus as separate<br />

corporeal things may be <strong>of</strong>ten materially united to<br />

form a new corpus ; so the several independent<br />

things which are not capable <strong>of</strong> such material<br />

union, may be viewed as an ideal union or as a<br />

a universitas for some purpose ; the flock <strong>of</strong> sheep<br />

may be viewed as a whole, as a universitas, for<br />

the purpose <strong>of</strong> ownership. Such a universitas, as<br />

already observed, is independent <strong>of</strong> the several cor<br />

poreal things : it still exists if they are all changed.<br />

Thus in a flock <strong>of</strong> sheep we have a fictitious, a<br />

juristical whole or thing, <strong>and</strong> in the notion <strong>of</strong><br />

a universitas <strong>of</strong> persons we have a fictitious or ju<br />

ristical person, which is still the same person<br />

though all the individuals are changed. As a<br />

number <strong>of</strong> sheep must have a name,a flock, in order<br />

to be comprehended in one notion, so a juristical<br />

person must have a name, as the universitas <strong>of</strong><br />

Fabri, or the city <strong>of</strong> Rome.<br />

The term universitas then may have various<br />

senses, 1. Both the universitas <strong>and</strong> the parts may<br />

be corporeal (Dig. 50. tit 16. s. 239. § ii) : territorium<br />

est universitas agrorum intra fines cujusquc<br />

civitatis. 2. The universitas may be corpo<br />

real, <strong>and</strong> the parts incorporeal, as when we imagine<br />

fractional parts <strong>of</strong> a thing. 3. The universitas may<br />

be incorporeal, <strong>and</strong> the parts corporeal, ns a flock<br />

<strong>of</strong> sheep. 4. The universitas <strong>and</strong> the parts may<br />

both be incorporeal.<br />

The fourth is the case when the notion <strong>of</strong> a<br />

whole <strong>and</strong> its parts is not applied to things, but to<br />

rights : thus a man's whole property may be<br />

viewed as a unit, or as a universitas, which compre<br />

hends the several rights that he has to the several<br />

fictitious person imagined for certain purposes, as<br />

the notion <strong>of</strong> a universitas <strong>of</strong> independent material<br />

things is the notion <strong>of</strong> a fictitious thing, imagined<br />

for certain purposes.<br />

A single person only can properly be viewed as<br />

the subject <strong>of</strong> rights <strong>and</strong> duties ; but the notion <strong>of</strong><br />

legal capacity may by a fiction be extended to an<br />

imaginary person, to a universitas personanim, but<br />

the fictitious person is not a unit composed <strong>of</strong> the<br />

real persons : it is a name in which the several<br />

persons or a majority may act for certain permanent<br />

purposes. The purpose itself is sometimes the<br />

fictitious person, as when property is given for<br />

the service <strong>of</strong> religion, whether it is administered<br />

by one person or several persons. Such juristical<br />

persons have certain legal capacities as individuals<br />

have ; but their legal capacities are limited to<br />

property as their object. It is true that the Ro<br />

mans <strong>of</strong>ten considered persons as a collective unity,<br />

simply because they all exercised the same<br />

functions : thus they speak <strong>of</strong> the Collegium<br />

<strong>of</strong> the consuls [Collegium], <strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong> theTribuni<br />

Plebis. In like manner they say that the Duum<br />

viri <strong>of</strong> a municipum are to be viewed as one person.<br />

(Dig. 50. tit. 1. s. 25). But these fictitious<br />

unities have only reference to Jus Publicum, <strong>and</strong><br />

they have no necessary connection with juristical<br />

persons, the essential character <strong>of</strong> which is the<br />

capacity to have <strong>and</strong> acquire property by some<br />

name.<br />

Juristical persons could be subjects <strong>of</strong> owner<br />

ship, Jura in re, obligationes, <strong>and</strong> hereditas :<br />

they could own slaves <strong>and</strong> have the Patronatus ;<br />

but all the relations <strong>of</strong> Familia, as the Patria Potestas<br />

<strong>and</strong> others <strong>of</strong> a like kind, were foreign to the<br />

notion. But though the capacity to have property<br />

is the distinguishing characteristic <strong>of</strong> Juristical<br />

persons viewed with relation to Jus Privatum, the<br />

objects for which the property is had <strong>and</strong> applied<br />

may be any ; <strong>and</strong> the capacity to have property<br />

implies a purpose for which it is had, which is<br />

<strong>of</strong>ten much more important than this mere capacity.<br />

But the purposes for which Juristical persons have<br />

property ore quite distinct from their capacity to<br />

have it. This will appear from all or any <strong>of</strong> the<br />

examples hereinafter given.<br />

The following are Juristical persons: (1) Civitas:<br />

(2) Municipes: this term is more common<br />

than Municipium, <strong>and</strong> comprehends both citizens<br />

<strong>of</strong> a Municipium <strong>and</strong> a Colony ; it is also used<br />

when the object is to express the Municipium as<br />

a whole opposed to the individual members <strong>of</strong> it.<br />

(3) Respublica. In the republican period, when<br />

used without an adjunct, Respublica expressed<br />

Rome, but in the old jurists it signifies a Ci vitas<br />

dependent on Rome. (4) Respublica Civitatis or<br />

Municipii : (5) Commune, Communitas. Besides<br />

the Civitates, component parts <strong>of</strong> the Civitates are<br />

also Juristical persons : (1) Curiae or Decuriones ;<br />

the word Decuriones <strong>of</strong>ten denotes the individuals<br />

composing the body <strong>of</strong> Decuriones as opposed to<br />

the Civitas (Municipes), which appears from a<br />

passage in the Digest (4. tit 3. s. 15), where it is<br />

stated that an action for Dolus will not lie against<br />

the Municipes, for a fictitious person cannot be<br />

guilty <strong>of</strong> Dolus, but such action will lie against the<br />

individual Decuriones who administer the affairs

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!