29.08.2013 Views

ARNOLD BRECHT'S POLITICAL THEORY REVISITED Political ...

ARNOLD BRECHT'S POLITICAL THEORY REVISITED Political ...

ARNOLD BRECHT'S POLITICAL THEORY REVISITED Political ...

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

166 THE <strong>POLITICAL</strong> SCIENCE REVIEWER<br />

what it `means,' or (2) why it is `true' or `false,' or otherwise compatible<br />

or incompatible with some norm, standard or rule, or (3)<br />

how it has come to `be there,' what is ' is' (not what it `means'), and<br />

what the consequences of its being there may be" (73). His subsequent<br />

remarks on the first two of these are extremely brief, even<br />

though all three types of explanation appear to be employed with<br />

Scientific Method. That brevity appears all the more strange and<br />

unjustified in the light of certain evident ambiguities concerning the<br />

relationships between the three.<br />

In the first place, it is noteworthy that the second type of explanation,<br />

as described, collects both the the defense of the truth of "scientific"<br />

propositions (synthetic) and the defense of the truth of<br />

derivative evaluative propositions in the same category. In the first<br />

case we show "that acceptance of the proposition as true or false is in<br />

line with other rules of scientific procedure"; and in the second case<br />

we "try to explain why some behavior, attitude, etc., is `right' or<br />

`wrong' by showing that it is or is not in accord with presupposed<br />

norms, standards, or rules" (73). Stated in this formal fashion, there<br />

would appear to be no significant difference between the nature or<br />

authoritativeness of Scientific Method's descriptive account of the<br />

"is" and the normative conclusions produced by a "policy" science<br />

geared to some set of assumed "ulterior" or "ultimate values." In<br />

both cases the relevance and authoritativeness of the product is<br />

wholly contingent upon an unjustifiable acceptance or rejection of<br />

the presupposed "rules" or "norms." This suggests the obvious<br />

possibility of the systematic inclusion of normative considerations in<br />

the study of politics by the inclusion of some "ultimate" value or<br />

values supported by the same "common sense" which is followed in<br />

matters of reality, causality, etc. But Brecht does not discuss such a<br />

possibility here.<br />

To "explain" in the third sense, he tells us, is to explain "an existential<br />

fact or event"; and this means "to present it as a link in the<br />

chain of cause and effect, or, if we are unable to assign it a place in<br />

some pattern of cause and effect, at least to give it a place in some<br />

other pattern of existential regularity." But he allows that such "existential<br />

facts" may also be regarded as "signs" which have some<br />

"definite meaning"; and that implies that they are amenable to the<br />

first mode of explanation (74). This of course raises the possibility of<br />

an inductive exploration of the normative "signs" or significance of<br />

the natural order. Brecht does not notice this possibility for discussion.<br />

But he tells us that such explanations of the "meaning" of ex-

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!