13.01.2015 Views

Untitled

Untitled

Untitled

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

The Age of Touristic Reproduction<br />

demolished to make way for a department store. You think, here is a slice of<br />

authentic, unique, and different life that is going to be destroyed, and once<br />

again everything is about to be flattened and rendered banal; what was once<br />

monumental and eternal is soon to be irrevocably lost. But such mourning<br />

would be premature. For on your next visit to the now gentrified area, you<br />

say: how marvelously insipid, ugly, and banal everything is here—it clearly<br />

must have always been as insipid as this, and will always remain so. With this<br />

the area is instantly remonumentalized—because on one’s travels everydayness<br />

and banality are always experienced as being equally monumental as that<br />

which is aesthetically exceptional. Rather than being guided by some intrinsic<br />

quality pertaining to a monument, our sense of monumentality is derived<br />

from the relentless process of monumentalization, demonumentalization, and<br />

remonumentalization that is unleashed by the romantic tourist’s gaze.<br />

Incidentally, it was Kant—in his theory of the sublime in Critique of<br />

Judgment—who first philosophically assessed the figure of the globally roaming<br />

tourist in search of aesthetic experiences. He describes the romantic tourist<br />

as someone who perceives even his own demise as a possible travel destination<br />

and possesses the capacity to experience it as a sublime event. As examples of<br />

mathematical sublimity Kant cites mountains or oceans, phenomena that<br />

appear to dwarf normal human proportions. As instances of dynamic sublimity<br />

he offers colossal natural events such as storms, volcanic eruptions, and<br />

other catastrophes whose overpowering force directly threatens our lives. Yet<br />

as destinations visited by the romantic tourist, these threats are not in themselves<br />

sublime—just as urban monuments are not intrinsically monumental.<br />

According to Kant sublimity lies not in “anything in nature” but in the<br />

“capacity we have within us” to judge and enjoy without fear the very things<br />

that threaten us. 2 Hence the subject of Kant’s infinite ideas of reason is the<br />

tourist who repeatedly embarks on journeys in search of the extraordinary of<br />

enormity and danger in order to confirm his own superiority and sublimity<br />

in regard to nature. But in another section of this treatise Kant also points<br />

out that, for instance, the inhabitants of the Alps, who have spent their entire<br />

lives in the mountains, by no means regard them as sublime, and “without<br />

hesitation” consider “all worshipers of icy peaks to be fools.” 3 Indeed, in<br />

Kant’s age the romantic tourist’s gaze still differed radically from that of<br />

the mountain dweller. With his globalized gaze the tourist views the<br />

figure of the Swiss peasant, for instance, as a feature of the landscape—and

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!