24.01.2013 Views

The Folk Biology of the Tobelo People - Smithsonian Institution ...

The Folk Biology of the Tobelo People - Smithsonian Institution ...

The Folk Biology of the Tobelo People - Smithsonian Institution ...

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

NUMBER 34<br />

Even if we were to limit our description to a single <strong>Tobelo</strong><br />

dialect, we would not solve die problem <strong>of</strong> variation among<br />

speakers, because variation among individuals also occurs.<br />

Nei<strong>the</strong>r a complete description <strong>of</strong> "<strong>the</strong>" <strong>Tobelo</strong> language nor a<br />

complete description <strong>of</strong> "<strong>the</strong>" domain <strong>of</strong> BIOTIC FORMS<br />

among die <strong>Tobelo</strong> would describe any particular individual's<br />

knowledge or competence. Not only are many plants and<br />

animals unidentifiable by, and <strong>the</strong>ir names unfamiliar to, most<br />

<strong>Tobelo</strong>, but <strong>the</strong>re is also considerable apparent disagreement<br />

over <strong>the</strong> correct names for specimens shown <strong>the</strong>m (less <strong>of</strong>ten<br />

for those seen in <strong>the</strong>ir natural context), despite die widespread<br />

<strong>Tobelo</strong> cultural presumption (see 2.3) that each plant and<br />

fair-sized animal should have (or should have formerly had) a<br />

name.<br />

From die ethnographic fieldworker's point <strong>of</strong> view, tiiere are<br />

two kinds <strong>of</strong> causes for tiiis disagreement: <strong>the</strong> "exasperating"<br />

and <strong>the</strong> "interesting." "Exasperating" causes <strong>of</strong> informant<br />

disagreement include <strong>the</strong> methodological problems <strong>of</strong> identifying<br />

plant classes from parts <strong>of</strong> plants when specimens must be<br />

removed from context, or <strong>of</strong> informants who pr<strong>of</strong>fer names<br />

without conviction but with misleading certainty. Social<br />

conventions also play a role, such as those that dictate that<br />

younger <strong>Tobelo</strong> should concede to tiieir elders' opinions in<br />

public, just as hosts should defer to guests; or that most<br />

medicinal uses <strong>of</strong> plants (including tiiose that can be inferred<br />

from names for some plant types) are not freely discussed.<br />

Though exasperating, <strong>the</strong>se sources <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> vast majority <strong>of</strong><br />

cases <strong>of</strong> apparent disagreement are not insurmountable. Many<br />

social conventions can be overcome in private, and names<br />

mistakenly assigned are <strong>of</strong>ten entiiusiastically corrected when<br />

new possibilities are presented. Corrections by <strong>the</strong> more expert<br />

are accepted by otiiers (even in private) as "learning something<br />

new."<br />

<strong>The</strong> disagreement that remains is "interesting," and may lead<br />

to discoveries <strong>of</strong> synonymy, <strong>of</strong> dialectal differences, <strong>of</strong> marked<br />

and unmarked senses <strong>of</strong> terms, or <strong>of</strong> polysemous terms tiiat<br />

include plant or animal names among tiieir senses. All <strong>the</strong>se<br />

possibilities, however, can be investigated only if we continue<br />

to posit, just as a working hypo<strong>the</strong>sis, that a single structural<br />

description <strong>of</strong> die domain under investigation can be derived,<br />

and <strong>the</strong>n try to determine if and how both <strong>of</strong> two terms applied<br />

to <strong>the</strong> same object (or even class) might be predictable with<br />

reference to <strong>the</strong> same structural description.<br />

Perhaps Hays (1976:489) is arguing against such an<br />

approach when he writes:<br />

.. .<strong>the</strong> descriptive problem raised by informants' disagreements has more <strong>of</strong>ten<br />

been sidestepped by adopting ei<strong>the</strong>r <strong>of</strong> two models <strong>of</strong> die culture (or a limited<br />

domain <strong>of</strong> it) to be described. One is that which views a culture as "<strong>the</strong> common<br />

element which all members share, or <strong>the</strong> set <strong>the</strong>oretical INTERSECTION <strong>of</strong><br />

individual competences" (Werner, 1969:333), or ...<strong>the</strong> "shared" model.<br />

According to a second view, an ethnographic description is "an attempt to<br />

characterize <strong>the</strong> set <strong>the</strong>oretical UNION <strong>of</strong> all individual competences" (Werner,<br />

1969:333), an approach commonly used in folk biology .. .where <strong>the</strong> notion <strong>of</strong><br />

an -omniscient informant" is employed; this model <strong>of</strong> a culture I will refer to as<br />

a "composite."<br />

Uncritical adoption <strong>of</strong> ei<strong>the</strong>r approach can lead to descriptions which are<br />

incomplete, misleading, or simply reifications<br />

Hays has instead (1976, 1979) commendably attempted to<br />

document <strong>the</strong> degree <strong>of</strong> intra-cultural variation in plant<br />

classification among a sample <strong>of</strong> Ndumba informants. Aside<br />

from some methodological problems (particularly that study's<br />

complete reliance on a controlled naming response using only<br />

pressed herbarium vouchers as stimuli), it still appears from his<br />

discussion <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Ndumba data that at least one point about<br />

documenting such variation remains to be considered: ei<strong>the</strong>r all<br />

informants do share a single system <strong>of</strong> classification or <strong>the</strong>y do<br />

not. If <strong>the</strong>y do, <strong>the</strong>n we may adequately describe it with a single<br />

model. If tiiey do not, we still need a model witiiin which<br />

individual, dialectal, or otiier variation can be described (or<br />

more ideally, "predicted"). If "composite model" is meant to<br />

imply a model tiiat fails to predict variation wherever it occurs,<br />

<strong>the</strong>n I join in rejecting it; but if it could provide a structural<br />

explanation for and an adequate description <strong>of</strong> dialectal (and,<br />

ideally, even individual) variation, I would see no choice but to<br />

adopt it.<br />

Of course, one might instead try to document die knowledge<br />

<strong>of</strong> each individual, treating that as his own system <strong>of</strong><br />

classification. Though <strong>the</strong>re are methodological difficulties,<br />

such an effort among <strong>Tobelo</strong> would undoubtedly produce<br />

interesting results; however, to leave <strong>the</strong> description <strong>the</strong>re<br />

seems to deny many facts <strong>of</strong> language in general and <strong>of</strong> <strong>Tobelo</strong><br />

language and culture in particular.<br />

1. In every specialized area <strong>of</strong> language some native speakers<br />

must rely on o<strong>the</strong>rs for terms in that specialized domain, about<br />

which tiiey can inquire for "correct" terms much as we might<br />

search for <strong>the</strong>m in an encyclopedia.<br />

2. Speakers <strong>of</strong> a language <strong>the</strong>mselves generally have a<br />

definite idea that some terms are correctly and o<strong>the</strong>rs<br />

incorrectly applied to objects, including <strong>the</strong> various BIOTIC<br />

FORMS. Witiiin die restraints <strong>of</strong> local etiquette (which frowns<br />

upon correcting hosts, guests, or those older than oneself),<br />

<strong>Tobelo</strong> generally appear wdling to (and frequendy do) discuss<br />

die "proper" terms for particular organisms. <strong>The</strong>re are also<br />

certain cultural presumptions about <strong>the</strong> existence <strong>of</strong> "proper"<br />

terms (see 2.3).<br />

3. Finally, despite <strong>the</strong>se cultural presumptions about die<br />

existence <strong>of</strong> an already established system <strong>of</strong> folk classification<br />

laid down by ancestors, <strong>the</strong>re is considerable evidence that<br />

when individuals or groups <strong>of</strong> individuals do revise die<br />

classification system, tiiey do so by productively applying to<br />

new situations <strong>the</strong> classificatory relations used throughout <strong>the</strong><br />

system. This shared system is <strong>the</strong> source <strong>of</strong> die particular<br />

"appropriateness" <strong>of</strong> such revisions, though <strong>the</strong>y may be made<br />

by an individual or a small group, and may in fact be "esoteric"<br />

or idiosyncratic (see 5.2.2.4 below). Revisions tiiat are<br />

"esoteric" or "idiosyncratic" (see 2.3 and 5.2.2.4) are such<br />

precisely because tiiey are recognized, even by tiiose who use<br />

<strong>the</strong>m, to be variations within <strong>the</strong> context <strong>of</strong> a more generally<br />

accepted non-"esoteric" folk classification (though <strong>of</strong> course

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!