26.03.2013 Views

Strauss on Xenophon's Socrates Xenophon's Socratic Discourse: An ...

Strauss on Xenophon's Socrates Xenophon's Socratic Discourse: An ...

Strauss on Xenophon's Socrates Xenophon's Socratic Discourse: An ...

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

STRAUSS ON XENOPHON 149<br />

On page 74, he says, "wisdom for which the philosophers l<strong>on</strong>g is<br />

obviously something noble . . . ." Shortly afterwards however he<br />

raises the questi<strong>on</strong>, as <strong>on</strong>e yet to be answered, whether "the good,<br />

the noble, and the pleasant are the same, if not simply, at least in the<br />

most important case " (77-78) . By " the most important case, " <str<strong>on</strong>g>Strauss</str<strong>on</strong>g><br />

almost surely means wisdom (cf. 125, "<strong>on</strong> the highest level"). What<br />

this questi<strong>on</strong> means, as applied to wisdom, appears from the immediate<br />

c<strong>on</strong>text. <str<strong>on</strong>g>Strauss</str<strong>on</strong>g> has just come close to identifying the<br />

"beautiful" (a term he appears to use interchangeably with<br />

"noble"-119, 167; cf. Xenoph<strong>on</strong>'s <strong>Socratic</strong> <strong>Discourse</strong> 121), insofar<br />

as it is something solid, with the pleasant or reducing the beautiful<br />

to the pleasant (77 and the reference <strong>on</strong> 120 to the textual passage<br />

discussed <strong>on</strong> 77; cf. 85, 167); with this tentative identificati<strong>on</strong> in<br />

mind, he asks whether it is necessary to retain the beautiful or noble<br />

as a distinct category or characteristic in the case of wisdom, or<br />

whether wisdom cannot be understood adequately in terms of the<br />

good and pleasant al<strong>on</strong>e. The promised or half-promised answer to<br />

this questi<strong>on</strong> is never given as such, although it may be implied in<br />

<str<strong>on</strong>g>Strauss</str<strong>on</strong>g>'s account of the coinicidence, in wisdom and its pursuit, of<br />

"the greatest good" and "the greatest pleasure" (125; of. 114, 115),<br />

an account which is silent <strong>on</strong> the beautiful. Later <strong>on</strong>, <str<strong>on</strong>g>Strauss</str<strong>on</strong>g> treats<br />

more or less disparagingly a reference to <strong>Socrates</strong>' nobility (139);<br />

and he insists that <strong>Socrates</strong>' losing a beauty c<strong>on</strong>test to Kritoboulos is<br />

not to be taken as due to a lack of bodily beauty al<strong>on</strong>e (167); <strong>on</strong> the<br />

other hand, he says that Xenoph<strong>on</strong>, a man of "light-heartedness,<br />

grace, and flexibility," was a lover of <strong>Socrates</strong> (171).<br />

There are several passages-the <strong>on</strong>e <strong>on</strong> pages 80-81 standing<br />

out-in which <str<strong>on</strong>g>Strauss</str<strong>on</strong>g> appears to suggest that the objects of wisdom<br />

are or bel<strong>on</strong>g to the beautiful or noble things (cf. 85 and 167; 104,<br />

103; c<strong>on</strong>sider the repeated references to Memorabilia I1.2.3). A later<br />

statement, however, which is his most extensive and explicit <strong>on</strong>e <strong>on</strong><br />

the subject, distinguishes the objects of wisdom from the beautiful or<br />

noble (as well as the good) things (118-120). Still, it is not completely<br />

clear how` definitive this statement is meant to be, or how far it is<br />

meant to go. The difficulty which strikes us first is that <str<strong>on</strong>g>Strauss</str<strong>on</strong>g> calls<br />

here the objects of wisdom "the most excellent things" (119). In an<br />

earlier ;passage, where he had called things akin to the examples now<br />

given of objects of wisdom "the best things," he spoke of them as being<br />

higher "in rank" than likenesses of things which can <strong>on</strong>ly be seen<br />

(83; of. "Plato" in History of Political Philosophy, ed. <str<strong>on</strong>g>Strauss</str<strong>on</strong>g> and<br />

Cropsey, 2nd editi<strong>on</strong>, 51). We are reminded by this of the fact that

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!