10.04.2013 Views

Cognitive Semantics : Meaning and Cognition

Cognitive Semantics : Meaning and Cognition

Cognitive Semantics : Meaning and Cognition

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

58 PETER HARDER<br />

function served by the utterance as a whole. The function of sub-utterance<br />

items must similarly be described by a top-down procedure of the kind<br />

followed above: the function of a constituent element is its contribution to the<br />

job done by the whole utterance.<br />

This approach provides a perspective on dependence that is different<br />

from the one described by Langacker. The basic motivation for it is that one<br />

linguistic element needs another because it cannot do the whole job on its<br />

own; when you code a sub-utterance item, there is always something missing<br />

before you have a fully functional utterance. In this formulation, it is true of all<br />

utterance fragments; but the central asymmetry of the elements in the layered<br />

structure suggests a differentiation between two types of “incompleteness”.<br />

As we saw, the coding differentiation embodied in the layered model distinguishes<br />

between “oper<strong>and</strong>s” <strong>and</strong> “operators”; <strong>and</strong> the defining mark of operators<br />

is that they “use” the oper<strong>and</strong>s in order to create a new <strong>and</strong> more complex<br />

item. At the top (or “output”) end we found the functional types of meaning<br />

(that relate content to the situation); at the bottom (or “input”) end we find<br />

conceptual content, which is “used” in various ways by higher-level operators.<br />

On the basis of this dichotomy, we can set up two complementary types of<br />

incompleteness, giving rise to two types of dependence relations.<br />

The incompleteness of operators consists in the lack of a content to<br />

operate upon. Starting from the top, we began by differentiating between the<br />

illocution (for example, declarative or interrogative) <strong>and</strong> the propositional<br />

content. The illocution operator specifies function, for example, that the<br />

utterance is a question, but in isolation it would lack a content. With a slight<br />

overgeneralization, I shall call the dependence of an operator upon its oper<strong>and</strong><br />

conceptual dependence. The motivation for this name is that the dependence<br />

points downward in the structure, towards the conceptual end, <strong>and</strong> that what is<br />

missing therefore includes the conceptual content. The overgeneralization is<br />

due to the fact that there may be something else apart from conceptual content<br />

missing.<br />

The oper<strong>and</strong> is incomplete in the opposite way. What is missing is a<br />

specification of what to do with it — in the example we have a proposition, but<br />

we do not know whether it is to be used to make a statement or ask a question.<br />

Therefore the dependence of oper<strong>and</strong> upon operator will be called functional<br />

dependence. Seen from the purely conceptual point of view, there is nothing<br />

incomplete about a proposition — we are perfectly capable of entertaining a<br />

proposition mentally, as part of an inventory of “issues”, without incorporat-

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!