05.08.2013 Views

The Blackwell Guide to the Philosophy of Science - The Department ...

The Blackwell Guide to the Philosophy of Science - The Department ...

The Blackwell Guide to the Philosophy of Science - The Department ...

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

Michael Silberstein<br />

Humphreys suggests (1997) if <strong>the</strong>re were widespread mereological emergence<br />

or nonseparability <strong>the</strong>n lower-level property instances would <strong>of</strong>ten “merge” in <strong>the</strong><br />

formation <strong>of</strong> higher-level properties such that <strong>the</strong>y no longer exist as separate subvenient<br />

entities. Widespread mereological emergence calls in<strong>to</strong> question <strong>the</strong> very<br />

picture <strong>of</strong> reality as divided in<strong>to</strong> a “discrete hierarchy <strong>of</strong> levels”; ra<strong>the</strong>r it is<br />

more likely that even if <strong>the</strong> ordering on <strong>the</strong> complexity <strong>of</strong> structures ranging from<br />

those <strong>of</strong> elementary physics <strong>to</strong> those <strong>of</strong> astrophysics and neurophysiology is discrete,<br />

<strong>the</strong> interactions between such structures will be so entangled that any separation in<strong>to</strong><br />

levels will be quite arbitrary (Humphreys, 1997, p. 15).<br />

Given widespread mereological emergence, <strong>the</strong> standard divisions and hierarchies<br />

between phenomena that are considered fundamental and emergent, simple and<br />

aggregate, kinematic and dynamic, and perhaps even what is considered physical,<br />

biological and mental are redrawn and redefined. Such divisions will be dependent<br />

on what question is being put <strong>to</strong> nature and what scale <strong>of</strong> phenomena is being<br />

probed.<br />

But on <strong>the</strong> face <strong>of</strong> it, one can embrace <strong>the</strong>se alternative models <strong>of</strong> inter<strong>the</strong>oretic<br />

reduction while maintaining that all apparent emergence is just a function<br />

<strong>of</strong> ignorance. For example, Schaffner strongly suggests that nothing about such<br />

tangled causal processes warrants any claims for ei<strong>the</strong>r mereological emergence or<br />

nomological emergence (such as vital or configurational forces). Ra<strong>the</strong>r, at worst,<br />

such systems provide us with cases <strong>of</strong> predictive/explana<strong>to</strong>ry emergence or representational/cognitive<br />

emergence (Schaffner, 1998, pp. 242–5).<br />

At present, both <strong>the</strong> emergentist and reductionist feel that, so far, things are<br />

going <strong>the</strong>ir way. <strong>The</strong> emergentist points <strong>to</strong> failures <strong>of</strong> on<strong>to</strong>logical and methodological<br />

reductionism, and <strong>the</strong> reductionist points <strong>to</strong> successes. Regarding <strong>the</strong><br />

problematic cases <strong>of</strong> inter<strong>the</strong>oretic reduction, <strong>the</strong> perennial reductionist reply is<br />

<strong>to</strong> claim that <strong>the</strong> future will bring success, just as in <strong>the</strong> past; emergentists likewise<br />

feel that <strong>the</strong>y will be redeemed by <strong>the</strong> future just as <strong>the</strong>y are by <strong>the</strong> present.<br />

This much is true I think, given <strong>the</strong> examples <strong>of</strong> both epistemological and on<strong>to</strong>logical<br />

emergence canvassed, <strong>the</strong>re is no reason why <strong>the</strong> burden <strong>of</strong> pro<strong>of</strong> should<br />

continue <strong>to</strong> lie exclusively with emergentism. At this juncture, nei<strong>the</strong>r view is irrational<br />

in light <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> evidence and nei<strong>the</strong>r view is conclusive. Ultimately, emergentists<br />

and reductionists are divided by a deeply held philosophical or aes<strong>the</strong>tic<br />

preference that nei<strong>the</strong>r will relinquish easily. For example, many philosophers<br />

persist in assuming that nomological and mereological reductionism are true in<br />

spite <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> actual state <strong>of</strong> unification within science and in spite <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> fact that<br />

fundamental physics itself might prove a counter-example <strong>to</strong> mereological supervenience.<br />

Do <strong>the</strong> past successes <strong>of</strong> reductionism warrant those assumptions on<br />

<strong>the</strong>ir part or is <strong>the</strong> assumption based largely on faith?<br />

We know what questions need <strong>to</strong> be answered <strong>to</strong> resolve <strong>the</strong> debate between<br />

emergentism and reductionism, but is it possible <strong>to</strong> ever answer <strong>the</strong>m? How will we<br />

know when we have answered <strong>the</strong>m? It is no doubt prudent <strong>to</strong> remain agnostic<br />

102

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!