05.08.2013 Views

The Blackwell Guide to the Philosophy of Science - The Department ...

The Blackwell Guide to the Philosophy of Science - The Department ...

The Blackwell Guide to the Philosophy of Science - The Department ...

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

Social <strong>Science</strong>s<br />

(Papineau, 1991; Earman and Roberts, 1999). Yet <strong>the</strong> doctrine is broad enough<br />

that some important points remain even if one rejects <strong>the</strong> commitment <strong>to</strong> capacities<br />

or natures. Social scientists have picked up on <strong>the</strong> idea that <strong>the</strong>y are committed<br />

<strong>to</strong> “generative mechanisms.” Here <strong>the</strong>y are rejecting instrumentalist ideas<br />

which have shaped social scientific research. Much social research proceeds by<br />

running regressions or o<strong>the</strong>r statistical tests on a set <strong>of</strong> variables without any <strong>the</strong>oretical<br />

rationale or without any <strong>the</strong>oretical account <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir interrelation. <strong>The</strong><br />

variables and <strong>the</strong>ir corresponding data are <strong>of</strong>ten drawn from ordinary language<br />

notions and lack any clear <strong>the</strong>ory <strong>of</strong> what is being measured and how. Asking for<br />

“generative mechanisms” is thus rejecting social science research that claims <strong>to</strong><br />

stick merely <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> observable and <strong>to</strong> eschew <strong>the</strong>oretical commitment. In short,<br />

this version <strong>of</strong> realism rejects traditional instrumentalism, a doctrine which underwent<br />

wi<strong>the</strong>ring criticism in philosophy <strong>of</strong> science some time ago. Thus <strong>the</strong> social<br />

science realists are in this way on <strong>the</strong> mark.<br />

Ano<strong>the</strong>r point about <strong>the</strong> realism debates worth noting concerns <strong>the</strong> global<br />

nature <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> arguments on both sides (Kincaid, 2000). <strong>The</strong> standard version <strong>of</strong><br />

realism argues that <strong>the</strong> best explanation for <strong>the</strong> methodological successes <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

social sciences is that <strong>the</strong> relevant claims are at least approximately true. This argument<br />

takes some general characteristic <strong>of</strong> social scientific practice and infers from<br />

that trait that <strong>the</strong> science in question must be right. In this sense, it is a global<br />

argument. Similarly, antirealist arguments go from <strong>the</strong> claim that all social science<br />

involves persuasion, for example, <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> claim that it is a social construct. Entire<br />

domains <strong>of</strong> investigation are evaluated in one fell swoop.<br />

This global approach <strong>to</strong> realism issues is suspect. If <strong>the</strong> best explanation <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

methodological practices <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> social sciences is <strong>the</strong>ir approximate truth, <strong>the</strong>n we<br />

must rule out o<strong>the</strong>r possible explanations. But <strong>the</strong>re is good empirical evidence<br />

that o<strong>the</strong>r explanations cannot always be ruled out. For example, significance<br />

testing is widely used in <strong>the</strong> social sciences <strong>to</strong> determine what is believable and<br />

what is not. Yet <strong>the</strong>re are good reasons <strong>to</strong> think that practice is quite misguided<br />

(Cohen, 1994). Apparently, <strong>the</strong> social processes <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> disciplines none<strong>the</strong>less<br />

ensure that <strong>the</strong> practice continues. Similarly, careful study <strong>of</strong> research on various<br />

“psychological disorders” shows <strong>the</strong> ways standard methods can be used <strong>to</strong> construct<br />

– literally – syndromes (Hacking, 1995). And <strong>the</strong>re are deep foundational<br />

issues concerning <strong>the</strong> requirements for measurement in <strong>the</strong> social sciences (e.g.<br />

additivity) that have arguably been largely ignored ra<strong>the</strong>r than solved (Michell,<br />

1999).<br />

Antirealist arguments about <strong>the</strong> social sciences are likewise implausibly global.<br />

As I just suggested, it is plausible <strong>the</strong>re that some social research superficially<br />

employs standard scientific procedures while outcomes are really determined by<br />

<strong>the</strong> social interests <strong>of</strong> investiga<strong>to</strong>rs. However, showing that this can happen is far<br />

from showing that it always does or must.<br />

I turn next <strong>to</strong> debates over <strong>the</strong> nature <strong>of</strong> explanation in <strong>the</strong> social sciences,<br />

beginning with <strong>the</strong> individualism–holism controversy. <strong>The</strong> individualism–holism<br />

issue has been plagued by debates over unclear <strong>the</strong>ses, and some progress can be<br />

301

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!