05.08.2013 Views

The Blackwell Guide to the Philosophy of Science - The Department ...

The Blackwell Guide to the Philosophy of Science - The Department ...

The Blackwell Guide to the Philosophy of Science - The Department ...

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

Harold Kincaid<br />

ideas, and it is helpful <strong>to</strong> sort <strong>the</strong>m out. At least <strong>the</strong> following kinds <strong>of</strong> “meaning”<br />

might reasonably be at issue:<br />

Doxastic meaning: what a subject believes<br />

Intentional meaning: what a subject intends, desires, etc.<br />

Linguistic meaning: how <strong>the</strong> verbal behavior <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> subject is <strong>to</strong> be translated<br />

Symbolic meaning: what <strong>the</strong> behavior <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> subject symbolizes<br />

Normative meaning: what norms <strong>the</strong> behavior <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> subjects reflects or<br />

embodies<br />

While no doubt <strong>the</strong>re are interconnection between <strong>the</strong>se various senses <strong>of</strong><br />

“meaning,” <strong>the</strong>y are importantly different.<br />

Perhaps <strong>the</strong> most influential argument from <strong>the</strong> past based on meaning was <strong>the</strong><br />

type advanced by Taylor (1971). He argued that <strong>the</strong>re are no brute or bare data<br />

in <strong>the</strong> human sciences and that every categorization <strong>of</strong> human behavior rests on<br />

prior understandings. This argument is regularly repeated by those in <strong>the</strong> social<br />

sciences who want <strong>to</strong> draw a sharp distinction between quantitative and qualitative<br />

methods. Yet this argument ignores <strong>the</strong> main developments in philosophy <strong>of</strong><br />

science since <strong>the</strong> positivists. Given <strong>the</strong> holism <strong>of</strong> testing, <strong>the</strong> experimenter’s regress,<br />

<strong>the</strong> place <strong>of</strong> skill in testing, and o<strong>the</strong>r such phenomena widely identified in <strong>the</strong><br />

natural sciences, “brute data” without “prior understandings” are not <strong>to</strong> be found<br />

<strong>the</strong>re ei<strong>the</strong>r.<br />

<strong>The</strong> holism <strong>of</strong> testing is also relevant <strong>to</strong> two o<strong>the</strong>r traditional interpretivist type<br />

arguments, namely, those concerning rationality and <strong>the</strong> subject’s categories.<br />

Rationality is thought <strong>to</strong> make <strong>the</strong> social sciences different because <strong>the</strong> interpreter<br />

must make normative assumptions about what is rational in order <strong>to</strong> attribute<br />

beliefs <strong>to</strong> subjects and must assume that <strong>the</strong> subject is on <strong>the</strong> whole rational. This<br />

principle <strong>of</strong> charity was treated as an a priori methodological rule. <strong>The</strong> holism <strong>of</strong><br />

testing would suggest that methodological rules are ultimately justified by <strong>the</strong>ir fit<br />

with experience and can likewise be rejected when <strong>the</strong>y do not. From this perspective,<br />

<strong>the</strong> principle <strong>of</strong> charity is a contingent, defeasible rule. We should assume<br />

that individuals are rational only <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> extent that we have evidence that <strong>the</strong>y are;<br />

we should assume our standards <strong>of</strong> rationality are universal only <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> extent that<br />

<strong>the</strong> empirical evidence warrants that claim. Of course, we must make assumptions<br />

about rationality <strong>to</strong> get interpretation <strong>of</strong>f <strong>the</strong> ground. But <strong>the</strong> holism <strong>of</strong> testing<br />

tells us that no science ga<strong>the</strong>rs data without prior <strong>the</strong>ory. Thus assumptions about<br />

rationality are no different than o<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong>oretical assumptions. This general<br />

response <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> rationality debate has been ably defended by Henderson (1991,<br />

1993). <strong>The</strong>re are none<strong>the</strong>less still dissenters (Hollis, 1996).<br />

<strong>The</strong> holism <strong>of</strong> testing also bears upon arguments over <strong>the</strong> subject’s selfconceptions.<br />

How <strong>the</strong> subject views <strong>the</strong> world is one piece <strong>of</strong> evidence about his<br />

or her behavior, but a piece that must be evaluated on <strong>the</strong> basis <strong>of</strong> everything else<br />

that we know. Subjects can be entirely mistaken about <strong>the</strong> causes <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir behavior<br />

as a large body <strong>of</strong> work shows (Liska, 1975). To ignore <strong>the</strong> subject’s under-<br />

298

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!