05.08.2013 Views

The Blackwell Guide to the Philosophy of Science - The Department ...

The Blackwell Guide to the Philosophy of Science - The Department ...

The Blackwell Guide to the Philosophy of Science - The Department ...

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

PX ( Y)<br />

PXY ( )=<br />

PY ( )<br />

provided P(Y) > 0. We can now prove versions <strong>of</strong> Bayes’ <strong>the</strong>orem:<br />

PBAPA ( ) . ( )<br />

PAB ( )=<br />

PB ( )<br />

PBAPA ( ) . ( )<br />

=<br />

PBAPA ( ) . ( )+ PB ( ÿAP<br />

) . ( ÿA)<br />

More generally, suppose we have a partition <strong>of</strong> hypo<strong>the</strong>ses {H1, H2,..., Hn},<br />

and evidence E. <strong>The</strong>n we have, for each i:<br />

PH ( E)=<br />

i<br />

PEH ( ) PH ( )<br />

n<br />

Â<br />

j=<br />

1<br />

i i<br />

PEH ( ) PH ( )<br />

j j<br />

Alan Hájek and Ned Hall<br />

<strong>The</strong> P(E|Hi) terms are called likelihoods, and <strong>the</strong> P(Hi) terms are called priors.<br />

If P(X|Y) = P(X) – equivalently, if P(Y|X) = P(Y); equivalently, if P(X Y ) =<br />

P(X)P(Y ) – <strong>the</strong>n X and Y are said <strong>to</strong> be independent. Two cautions: first, <strong>the</strong><br />

locution “X is independent <strong>of</strong> Y ” is somewhat careless, encouraging one <strong>to</strong> forget<br />

that independence is a relation that events or sentences bear <strong>to</strong> a probability<br />

function. Second, this technical sense <strong>of</strong> “independence” should not be identified<br />

unreflectively with causal independence, or any o<strong>the</strong>r pre<strong>the</strong>oretical sense <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

word, even though such identifications are <strong>of</strong>ten made in practice. If P(X|Y) > P(X)<br />

– equivalently, if P(Y|X) > P(Y) – <strong>the</strong>n X and Y are positively correlated. A corners<strong>to</strong>ne<br />

<strong>of</strong> any probabilistic approach <strong>to</strong> induction is <strong>the</strong> idea that evidence about <strong>the</strong><br />

observed is positively correlated with various hypo<strong>the</strong>ses about <strong>the</strong> unobserved.<br />

We now turn <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> so-called “interpretations” <strong>of</strong> probability. <strong>The</strong> term is misleading<br />

twice over. Various quantities that intuitively have nothing <strong>to</strong> do with<br />

“probability” obey Kolmogorov’s axioms – for example, length, volume, and mass,<br />

each suitably normalized – and are thus “interpretations” <strong>of</strong> it, but not in <strong>the</strong><br />

intended sense. Conversely, <strong>the</strong> majority <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> most influential “interpretations”<br />

<strong>of</strong> P violate countable additivity, and thus are not genuine interpretations <strong>of</strong><br />

Kolmogorov’s full probability calculus at all. Be that as it may, we will drop <strong>the</strong><br />

scare quotes <strong>of</strong> discomfort from now on.<br />

<strong>The</strong> Classical Interpretation<br />

<strong>The</strong> classical interpretation, which owes its name <strong>to</strong> its early and august pedigree<br />

– notably <strong>the</strong> Port-Royal Logic, Arnauld (1662) and Laplace (1814) – purports <strong>to</strong><br />

determine probability assignments in <strong>the</strong> face <strong>of</strong> no evidence at all, or symmetri-<br />

158

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!