29.08.2013 Views

Minimality Effects in Syntax · The MLC and Derivational Economy ...

Minimality Effects in Syntax · The MLC and Derivational Economy ...

Minimality Effects in Syntax · The MLC and Derivational Economy ...

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

<strong>The</strong> <strong>MLC</strong> <strong>and</strong> derivational economy 79<br />

(13) Clauseboundedness of the b<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>g of <strong>in</strong> situ wh-phrases <strong>in</strong> H<strong>in</strong>di<br />

*Raam-ne kis-ko kahaa ki Sitaa-ne kis-ko dekhaa<br />

Raam-erg who.dat told that Sita-erg who saw?<br />

“who did Ram tell that Sita saw who?”<br />

Let us now come back to (12). First, we want to expla<strong>in</strong> why (12a) is out with<br />

a pair-list <strong>in</strong>terpretation. This follows if (the relevant version of) German<br />

resembles H<strong>in</strong>di <strong>in</strong> that f<strong>in</strong>ite CPs are barriers for the scope l<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong>g of <strong>in</strong><br />

situ wh-phrases. Consequently, wen cannot be scope-l<strong>in</strong>ked to wer <strong>in</strong> (12a),<br />

which renders the structure ungrammatical under the <strong>in</strong>tended <strong>in</strong>terpretation.<br />

F<strong>in</strong>ite clauses are not, however, barriers for overt movement. <strong>The</strong>refore,<br />

there is a way of construct<strong>in</strong>g a Logical Form for (12) <strong>in</strong> which both whphrases<br />

take matrix scope, viz. by mov<strong>in</strong>g the wh-element from the complement<br />

clause <strong>in</strong>to the matrix-Spec-CP position, <strong>and</strong> by scope-l<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong>g the<br />

matrix subject to the matrix Spec,CP position. This is what has happened <strong>in</strong><br />

(12b). None of the relations established there is <strong>in</strong> conflict with locality<br />

requirements – but the <strong>MLC</strong> is violated. Apparently, this <strong>MLC</strong>-violation is<br />

licensed because the relevant Logical Form cannot be arrived at <strong>in</strong> a different<br />

way – the structure (12a) respect<strong>in</strong>g the <strong>MLC</strong> is <strong>in</strong>compatible with the locality<br />

of the licens<strong>in</strong>g of wh-phrases <strong>in</strong> situ. (12) illustrates the same phenomenon<br />

as (7), but <strong>in</strong> a rather different context.<br />

<strong>The</strong> other examples <strong>in</strong> (12) illustrate two further po<strong>in</strong>ts. (12c) shows that<br />

German is like H<strong>in</strong>di <strong>in</strong> hav<strong>in</strong>g a wh-scope-mark<strong>in</strong>g construction, <strong>in</strong> which<br />

a scope marker (was) rather than the real wh-phrase appears <strong>in</strong> Spec,CP.<br />

(12c) is well-formed <strong>in</strong> all dialects of German, <strong>and</strong> expresses a pair-list<br />

<strong>in</strong>terpretation. A m<strong>in</strong>or po<strong>in</strong>t illustrated by this example is that f<strong>in</strong>ite clauses<br />

are isl<strong>and</strong>s for scope tak<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> German only for wh-phrases that do not<br />

occupy a Spec,CP position (note that the lower wh-phrase is fronted <strong>in</strong> the<br />

complement clause). <strong>The</strong>re are various ways of analys<strong>in</strong>g the construction<br />

(see, e.g., the contributions <strong>in</strong> Lutz, Müller <strong>and</strong> von Stechow 2000), but<br />

details are irrelevant for the more important po<strong>in</strong>t: long wh-movement <strong>in</strong><br />

(12b) <strong>and</strong> wh-scope mark<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> (12c) yield the same <strong>in</strong>terpretation, but the<br />

wh-scope-mark<strong>in</strong>g construction (12c) avoids an <strong>MLC</strong> violation, <strong>in</strong> contrast<br />

to (12b). This shows that the sensitivity of the <strong>MLC</strong> to <strong>in</strong>terpretation cannot<br />

<strong>in</strong>volve a simple, “global” concept of mean<strong>in</strong>g identity. If it would, the<br />

wellformedness of (12c) should imply that the <strong>MLC</strong> is able to rule out<br />

(12b). Given (12c), no <strong>MLC</strong>-violation is necessary for express<strong>in</strong>g the<br />

“mean<strong>in</strong>g” of (12b). <strong>The</strong> <strong>MLC</strong> must therefore not be sensitive to “mean<strong>in</strong>g<br />

identity” <strong>in</strong> a global sense. Rather, the identity of <strong>in</strong>terpretation that is rele-

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!