20.07.2013 Views

Notes on computational linguistics.pdf - UCLA Department of ...

Notes on computational linguistics.pdf - UCLA Department of ...

Notes on computational linguistics.pdf - UCLA Department of ...

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

Stabler - Lx 185/209 2003<br />

10.6 Some remaining issues<br />

10.6.1 Locality<br />

When phrasal movement was defined in §9.1 <strong>on</strong> page 170, it will be recalled that we <strong>on</strong>ly allowed the operati<strong>on</strong><br />

to apply to a structure with a +f head and exactly 1 -f c<strong>on</strong>stituent. 48 We menti<strong>on</strong>ed that this restricti<strong>on</strong> is a<br />

simple, str<strong>on</strong>g versi<strong>on</strong> <strong>of</strong> a kind <strong>of</strong> “shortest move c<strong>on</strong>straint” in the sense that each -f c<strong>on</strong>stituent must move<br />

to the first available +f positi<strong>on</strong>. If there are two -f c<strong>on</strong>stituents in any structure, this requirement cannot<br />

be met. This is also a kind <strong>of</strong> “relativized minimality” c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong> in the sense that the domains <strong>of</strong> movement<br />

are relativized by the inventory <strong>of</strong> categories (Rizzi, 1990). A -wh c<strong>on</strong>stituent cannot get by any other -wh<br />

c<strong>on</strong>stituent, but it can, for example, get by a -k c<strong>on</strong>stituent.<br />

Notice that while this c<strong>on</strong>straint allows a wh element to move to the fr<strong>on</strong>t <strong>of</strong> a relative clause,<br />

the man whoi you like ti visited us yesterday<br />

it properly blocks moving another wh-element out, e.g. forming a questi<strong>on</strong> by questi<strong>on</strong>ing the subject you:<br />

*whoj did the man whoi tj like ti visited us yesterday * the man whoi I read a statement whichj tj was about<br />

ti is sick<br />

When this impossiblity <strong>of</strong> extracting out <strong>of</strong> a complex phrase like the man who you like was observed by<br />

Ross (1967), he observed that extracti<strong>on</strong> out <strong>of</strong> complex determiner phrases is quite generally blocked, even<br />

when there are (apparently) no other movements <strong>of</strong> the same kind (and not <strong>on</strong>ly in English). For example, the<br />

following should not be accepted:<br />

*whoi did the man with ti visit us<br />

* the hat whichi I believed the claim that Otto was wearing ti is red<br />

How can we block these? The SMC is apparently too weak, and needs to be strengthened. (We will see below<br />

that the SMC is also too str<strong>on</strong>g.)<br />

Freezing<br />

Wexler, Stepanov, et al.<br />

10.6.2 Multiple movements and resumptive pr<strong>on</strong>ouns<br />

In other respects, the SMC restricti<strong>on</strong> is too str<strong>on</strong>g. In English we have cases like (22a), though it is marginal<br />

for many speakers (Fodor, 1978; Pesetsky, 1985):<br />

(22) a. ?? Which violins1 did you say which s<strong>on</strong>atas2 were played t2 <strong>on</strong> t1<br />

b. * Which violins1 did you say which s<strong>on</strong>atas2 were played t1 <strong>on</strong> t2<br />

The example above is particularly troubling, and resembles (23a) famously observed by Huang (1982):<br />

(23) a. ? [Which problem]i do you w<strong>on</strong>der howj to solve ti tj?<br />

b. * Howj do you w<strong>on</strong>der [which problem]i to solve ti tj?<br />

It seems that in English, extracti<strong>on</strong> <strong>of</strong> two wh-elements is possible (at least marginally) if an argument whphrase<br />

moves across an adjunct wh-phrase, but it is notably worse if the adjunct phrase extracts across an<br />

argument phrase. We could allow the first example if wh-Adverbs have a different feature than wh-DPs, but<br />

then we would allow the sec<strong>on</strong>d example too. If there is really an argument-adjunct asymmetry here, it would<br />

apparently require some kind <strong>of</strong> fundamental change in the nature <strong>of</strong> our SMC.<br />

Developing insights from Obenauer (1983), Cinque (1990), Baltin (1992) and others, Rizzi (2000) argues that<br />

what is really happening here is that certain wh-elements, like the wh-DP in a above, can be related to their<br />

traces across another wh-element when they are “referential” in a certain sense. This moves the restricti<strong>on</strong> <strong>on</strong><br />

movement relati<strong>on</strong>s closer to “binding theory,” which will be discussed in §11. (Similarly semantic accounts<br />

have been <strong>of</strong>fered by many linguists.<br />

48 In our implementati<strong>on</strong>, we actually do not even build a representati<strong>on</strong> <strong>of</strong> any c<strong>on</strong>stituent which has two -f parts, for any f.<br />

227

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!